The Implicit Mind: Cognitive Architecture, the Self, and Ethics

Heroes are often admired for their ability to act without having "one thought too many," as Bernard Williams put it. Likewise, the unhesitating decisions of masterful athletes and artists are part of their fascination. Examples like these make clear that spontaneity can represent an ideal. However, recent literature in empirical psychology has shown how vulnerable our spontaneous inclinations can be to bias, shortsightedness, and irrationality. How can we make sense of these different roles that spontaneity plays in our lives? The central contention of this book is that understanding these two faces of spontaneity-its virtues and its vices-requires understanding the "implicit mind." In turn, understanding the implicit mind requires considering three sets of questions. The first set focuses on the architecture of the implicit mind itself. What kinds of mental states make up the implicit mind? Are both "virtue" and "vice" cases of spontaneity products of one and the same mental system? What kind of cognitive structure do these states have, if so? The second set of questions focuses on the relationship between the implicit mind and the self. How should we relate to our spontaneous inclinations and dispositions? Are they "ours," in the sense that they reflect on our character or identity? Are we responsible for them? The third set focuses on the ethics of spontaneity. What can research on self-regulation teach us about how to improve the ethics of our implicit minds? How can we enjoy the virtues of spontaneity without succumbing to its vices? Bringing together several streams of philosophical and psychological research, The Implicit Mind is the first book to offer a philosophical account of implicit attitudes.

128 downloads 5K Views 12MB Size

Recommend Stories

Empty story

Idea Transcript


The Implicit Mind

The Implicit Mind Cognitive Architecture, the Self, and Ethics

MICHAEL BROWNSTEIN

1

1 Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and certain other countries. Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America. © Oxford University Press 2018 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by license, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reproduction rights organization. Inquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above. You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer. CIP data is on file at the Library of Congress ISBN 978–​0–​19–​063372–​1 1 3 5 7 9 8 6 4 2 Printed by Sheridan Books, Inc., United States of America

CONTENTS

Acknowledgments 

vii

1. Introduction 

1

PART ONE  MIND

2. Perception, Emotion, Behavior, and Change: Components of Spontaneous Inclinations  29 3. Implicit Attitudes and the Architecture of the Mind  64 PART T WO  SELF

4. Caring, Implicit Attitudes, and the Self  101 5. Reflection, Responsibility, and Fractured Selves 

123

PART THREE  ETHICS

6. Deliberation and Spontaneity  7. The Habit Stance  177 8. Conclusion 

153

206

Appendix: Measures, Methods, and Psychological Science  References  233 Index  257

211

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

I’m so grateful for the generous, supportive, and incisive feedback I’ve received over the years, on this and related projects, from Alex Acs, Marianna Alessandri, Louise Antony, Mahzarin Banaji, Michael Brent, Lawrence Buell, Brent Cebul, Jason D’Cruz, James Dow, Yarrow Dunhum, Ellen Fridland, Katie Gasdaglis, Bertram Gawronski, Maggie Gram, Daniel Harris, Sally Haslanger, Jules Holroyd, Bryce Huebner, Zachary Irving, Gabbrielle Johnson, Eric Katz, Sean Kelly, Julian Kiverstein, Joshua Knobe, Victor Kumar, Benedek Kurdi, Calvin Lai, Carole Lee, Edouard Machery, Eric Mandelbaum, Kenny Marotta, Christia Mercer, Eliot Michaelson, John Morrison, Myrto Mylopolous, Brian Nosek, Keith Payne, Jonathan Phillips, Jeremy Pober, Emily Remus, Luis Rivera, Laurie Rudman, Hagop Sarkissian, Eric Schwitzgebel, Claire Seiler, Rena Seltzer, Paschal Sheeran, Robin Sheffler, David Shoemaker, Susanna Siegel, Nico Silins, Holly Smith, Chandra Sripada, Alex Stehn, Shannon Sullivan, Joseph Sweetman, Virginia Valian, Natalia Washington, Thomas Webb, Alison Wylie, Sunny Yang, and Robin Zheng. Many thanks, too, to Peter Ohlin, Lacey Davidson, Mary Becker, and two anonymous reviewers for Oxford University Press. You have helped to improve this book in countless ways. Taylor Carman and John Christman gracefully tolerated ham-​ handed earlier attempts to work out the ideas contained herein. Thank you to both, now that I’ve worked it all out flawlessly . . . I owe extra-​special thanks to Daniel Kelly, Tamar Gendler, and Jennifer Saul, each of whom is an inspiration and a role model. And I owe extra-​special super-​ duper thanks to Alex Madva, my one-​in-​a-​million collaborator. You flipped-​turned my life upside down, so just take a minute, sit right there, and consider yourself the prince of this affair. Mom, Dad, Erick, and Carrie: I can’t promise it’s worth looking, but you’ll find yourselves in here. Thank you for unwavering love and support. Above all, my deepest thanks to Reine, Leda, Iggy, and Minerva. I  love  you, I love you, I love you, and I love you too.

vii

viii

Acknowledgments

Parts of the book were conceived, written, and revised with support—​for which I’m very grateful—​from the American Council of Learned Societies, the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, and the Leverhulme Trust. Some of the material in this book has appeared in print previously in an earlier form. In particular, some of the examples in Chapter 1 were presented in Brownstein (2014) and Brownstein and Madva (2012a,b). Chapter 2 is a much-​expanded version of part of Brownstein and Madva (2012b). Also in Chapter 2, an earlier version of §4 appeared in Brownstein (2017) and an earlier version of part of §4.2 appeared in Brownstein and Madva (2012a). Parts of §3 and §5 in Chapter 3 are derived from Brownstein and Madva (2012a,b), and parts of §6 were published in a different form in Madva and Brownstein (2016). Parts of Chapters 4 and 5 are derived from Brownstein (2014). In Chapter 4 as well, an earlier version of §4.1 appeared in Brownstein and Madva (2012a), and an earlier version of §4.2 appeared in Brownstein (2014). Some parts of Chapter 7 are derived from Brownstein (2016) and a few passages of the Appendix are derived from Brownstein (2015). I’m grateful to these presses and to my co-​author, Alex Madva, for permission to edit and develop our collaborative work here.

The Implicit Mind

1

Introduction

Victims of violent assault sometimes say, after the fact, that “something just felt wrong” about the person walking on the other side of the street. Or offering to help carry the groceries into their apartment. Or hanging out in the empty hallway. But to their great regret, they dismissed these feelings, thinking that they were just being paranoid or suspicious. In The Gift of Fear, Gavin de Becker argues that the most important thing people can do to avoid becoming victims of assault is to trust their intuition when something about a person or situation seems amiss. He writes: A woman is waiting for an elevator, and when the doors open she sees a man inside who causes her apprehension. Since she is not usually afraid, it may be the late hour, his size, the way he looks at her, the rate of attacks in the neighborhood, an article she read a year ago—​it doesn’t matter why. The point is, she gets a feeling of fear. How does she respond to nature’s strongest survival signal? She suppresses it, telling herself: “I’m not going to live like that; I’m not going to insult this guy by letting the door close in his face.” When the fear doesn’t go away, she tells herself not to be so silly, and she gets into the elevator. Now, which is sillier: waiting a moment for the next elevator, or getting into a soundproofed steel chamber with a stranger she is afraid of? (1998, 30–​31) De Becker offers trainings promising to teach people how to notice their often very subtle feelings of fear and unease—​their “Pre-​Incident Indicators”—​in potentially dangerous situations. These indicators, he argues, are responsive to nonverbal signals of what other people are thinking or planning. For example, we may feel unease when another’s “micro-​expression,” like a quick sideways glance, or rapid eye-​blinking, or slightly downturned lips, signals that person’s intentions, even though we might not notice such cues consciously. De Becker’s trainings have been adapted for police officers, who also often say, after violent encounters, that they could tell that something was wrong in a situation, but they ignored those feelings because they didn’t seem justified at the time.

1

Introduction

2

This approach has been influential. De Becker designed the MOSAIC Threat Assessment System that is used by many police departments to screen threats of spousal abuse, and is also used to screen threats to members of the US Congress, the Central Intelligence Agency, and federal justices, including the justices of the Supreme Court.1 But there is a problem with de Becker’s advice. Stack his recommendations up against research on “implicit bias” and a dilemma emerges. Roughly speaking, implicit biases are evaluative thoughts and feelings about social groups that can contribute to discriminatory behavior even in the absence of explicitly prejudiced motivations.2 These thoughts and feelings are captured by “indirect” measures of attitudes. Such measures are indirect in the sense that they avoid asking people about their feelings or thoughts directly. Instead, on the most commonly used indirect measure—​the “Implicit Association Test” (IAT; Greenwald et al., 1998)—​participants are asked to sort names, images, or words that reflect social identity as quickly as possible. What emerges is thought to reflect mental associations between social groups and concepts like “good,” “bad,” “violent,” “lazy,” “athletic,” and so on. Such associations result at least in part from common stereotypes found in contemporary societies about members of these groups. On the black–​white race IAT, most white people (more than 70%) demonstrate negative implicit attitudes toward blacks, and roughly 40% of black participants do too.3 Moreover, tests like the IAT sometimes  predict biased behavior,  and in some contexts, they  do  so  better than traditional self-​report measures.4 Consider, for example, research on “shooter bias.” In a computer simulation, participants are quickly shown images of black and white men holding either guns or harmless objects like cell phones. They are told to “shoot” all and only those people depicted holding guns. The results are unsettling. Participants are more likely to shoot an unarmed black man than an unarmed white man and are more likely to fail to shoot an armed white man than an armed black man (Correll et al., 2002; Mekawi and Bresin, 2015). Measures of implicit bias like the IAT can predict these results. People who demonstrate strong implicit racial biases (in particular, strong implicit associations between “black” and “weapons”) are more likely to make these race-​ based mistakes than people who demonstrate weaker or no implicit racial biases (Glaser and Knowles, 2008). These findings are ominous in light of continued and recent police shootings of unarmed black men in the United States. And there are

  See http://​gavindebecker.com/​main/​.   There is much debate about how to define implicit bias. See Brownstein and Saul (2016) for discussion. 3   See Nosek et al. (2002, 2007), Ashburn-​Nardo et al. (2003), and Dasgupta (2004). 4   See Nosek et al. (2007) and Greenwald et al. (2009). See the Appendix for a more in-​depth discussion of the IAT and behavioral prediction. Readers unfamiliar with the IAT may want to skip ahead to the Appendix to read the section explaining how the test works. 1 2

Int roduc tion

3

thousands of related studies uncovering the pervasiveness of implicit biases against blacks, women, gay people, and members of other socially stigmatized groups.5 Findings like these show that the way we perceive, and act upon our perceptions of, micro-​expressions and subtle social signals is often influenced by stereotypes and prejudices that most people—​or most people reading this book, at least—​ disavow. Shooter bias involves acting on the basis of subtle feelings of fear that most white Americans are more likely to feel (but not necessarily notice themselves feeling) when they are in the presence of a black man than when they are facing a white man.6 Research shows that these feelings are indeed race-​based. For example, shooter bias is exacerbated after participants read newspaper stories about black criminals, but not after reading newspaper stories about white criminals (Correll et al., 2007). These subtle feelings of fear pervade many mundane situations, too, often in ways that only victims of prejudice notice. George Yancy (2008), for example, describes the purse-​clutching, averted gazes, and general unease of some white women when they are in an elevator with a black man, such as himself. In commenting on the death of Trayvon Martin, Barack Obama made a similar point: [T]‌here are very few African-​American men who haven’t had the experience of walking across the street and hearing the locks click on the doors of cars. That happens [sic] to me, at least before I was a senator. There are very few African-​Americans who haven’t had the experience of getting on an elevator and a woman clutching her purse nervously and holding her breath until she had a chance to get off. That happens often.7 So while one’s Pre-​Incident Indicators might be justifiably set off by a potential assailant’s posture or gestures, they might also be set off by an innocent person’s skin color, hoodie, or turban. This means that it might be both true that subtle feelings and intuitions can act like social antennae, tuning us into what’s happening around

5   As I discuss in the Appendix, no one psychological study is sufficient for concluding the existence of some psychological phenomenon. And, sometimes, many studies appearing to demonstrate some phenomenon can all turn out to be false positives or otherwise flawed, as the so-​called replication crisis in psychology has shown. So I do not mean to suggest that the sheer number of studies on implicit bias is definitive of the existence of implicit bias. But the breadth of a research program does count as evidence, however defeasible, of the program’s core findings. 6   Evidence for the fact that shooter bias involves acting on the basis of subtle feelings of fear stems in part from the fact that shooter bias can be mitigated by practicing the plan “If I see a black face, I will think ‘safe!’ ” (Stewart and Payne, 2008). But planning to think “quick!” or “accurate!” doesn’t have the same effect on shooter bias (see Chapter 7). Note also the intersection of race and gender in this stream of research, as all shooter bias studies use male targets only (so far as I know). White Americans’ implicit associations with black women are likely to be different than their implicit associations with black men. 7   See http://​www.huffingtonpost.com/​2013/​07/​19/​obama-​racial-​profiling_​n_​3624881.html.

Introduction

4

us, and also true that these very same feelings can be profoundly affected by prejudice and stereotypes. Our Pre-​Incident Indicators might be a valuable source of attunement to the world, in other words, but they might also be a tragic source of moral and rational failing.8 This is a grave point, particularly given de Becker’s recommendations to police officers to trust their intuition about potential criminal suspects. The juxtaposition of de Becker’s recommendations with research on implicit bias illustrates a tension that is replicated across the sciences of the mind. On the one hand, our spontaneous inclinations and dispositions are often attuned to subtle elements of the world around us, sometimes even more so than our reasoned judgments. Converging research in philosophy and psychology suggests that these unreasoned (but not unreasonable) inclinations—​our instincts, intuitions, gut feelings, sixth senses, heuristics, snap judgments, and so on—​ play key roles in thought and action and have the potential to have moral and rational credibility. On the other hand, one might read the headline of the past seventy-​f ive years of research in cognitive and social psychology as putting us “on notice” about the moral and rational failings of our spontaneous inclinations and dispositions. From impulsivity, to “moral myopia,” to implicit bias, it seems as if we must be constantly on guard against the dangers of our “mere” inclinations. The central contention of this book is that understanding these “two faces of spontaneity”—​ its virtues and vices—​ requires understanding what I  call the “implicit mind.”9 In turn, understanding the implicit mind requires considering three sets of questions. The first set focuses on the architecture of the implicit mind itself, the second on the relationship between the implicit mind and the self, and the third on the ethics of spontaneity. First, what kinds of mental states make up the implicit mind? Are both “virtue cases” and “vice cases” of spontaneity products of one and the same mental system? What kind of cognitive structure do these states have, if so? Are implicit mental states basic stimulus-​response reflexes? Are they mere associations? Or are they beliefs? Second, how should we relate to our spontaneous inclinations and dispositions? Are they “ours,” in the sense that they reflect on our character? Commonly we think of our beliefs, hopes, values, desires, and so on in these terms, as “person-​level” states. Do implicit mental states reflect on who we are in this sense? Relatedly, under   For related discussion, in which our spontaneous reactions are framed as sometimes at once epi­ stemically rational and morally faulty, see Gendler (2011), and see also replies from Egan (2011) and Madva (2016a). 9   I will speak often of “spontaneity,” but I do not mean it in the Kantian sense of the mind making active contributions to the “synthesis” of perceptual experience. I use the term in the folk sense, to refer to actions not preceded by deliberation, planning, or self-​focused thought. 8

Int roduc tion

5

what conditions are we responsible for spontaneous and impulsive actions, that is, those that result from the workings of the implicit mind? And, finally, how can we improve our implicit minds? What can we do to increase the chances of our spontaneous inclinations and dispositions acting as reliable indicators rather than as conduits for bias and prejudice? It is tempting to think that one can simply reflect carefully upon which spontaneous inclinations to trust and which to avoid. But in real-​time, moment-​to-​moment life, when decisions and actions unfold quickly, this is often not plausible. How then can we act on our immediate inclinations while minimizing the risk of doing something irrational or immoral? How can we enjoy the virtues of spontaneity without succumbing to its vices? A  poignant formulation of this last question surfaced in an unlikely place in 2012. In the climactic scene of Warner Bros.’ The Lego Movie (Li et al., 2014), with the bad guys closing in and the moment of truth arriving, the old wise man Vitruvius paradoxically exhorts his protégé, “Trust your instincts . . . unless your instincts are terrible!” Indeed. A  plethora of research in the sciences of the mind shows that very often we cannot but trust our instincts and that in many cases we should, unless our instincts are terrible, which the sciences of the mind have also shown that they often are.

1.  Many Virtues, Many Vices To pursue these questions, I draw upon a wide range of examples. These have a family resemblance, roughly all involving agents who act in some way without explicitly thinking about what they are doing or even, in some cases, being aware of what they are doing. I discuss these examples in more depth throughout the book. There are, of course, many important differences between the cases, but it is my contention that a theory of the implicit mind requires consideration of the vast diversity of relevant examples. My only aim here, in this chapter, is to flesh out the territory that I intend my account of the implicit mind to cover. The edges of this territory will be blurry. Imagine that you’re walking through a museum, with your back to the wall, and you turn around to see a very large painting from very close up.10 You will likely have an immediate inclination to step back from the large painting. Some artists seem to be aware of this phenomenon. Consider the following caption, which was displayed beside one of Barnett Newman’s paintings in the Museum of Modern Art in New York:   I borrow this example from Hubert Dreyfus and Sean Kelly (2007), who are in turn influenced by Maurice Merleau-​Ponty (1962/​2002). I  presented this example, along with the example of distance-​standing discussed later, with Alex Madva, in Brownstein and Madva (2012b). 10

Introduction

6

Vir Heroicus Sublimus, Newman’s largest painting at the time of its completion, is meant to overwhelm the senses. Viewers may be inclined to step back from it to see it all at once, but Newman instructed precisely the opposite. When the painting was first exhibited, in 1951 . . . Newman tacked to the wall a notice that read, “There is a tendency to look at large pictures from a distance. The large pictures in this exhibition are intended to be seen from a short distance.”11 Newman seems to be anticipating the impulse to step back in order to improve your orientation to the work. Indeed, he seems to be challenging this impulse, perhaps in order to help you see his work in a new way. But ordinarily we step back from a large painting in order to get the best view of it. We also ordinarily do so spontaneously, without any explicit thought or deliberation. More generally, navigating our way around objects in the ambient environment requires constant readjustment as we automatically seek out the “right” place to stand, sit, walk, and so on (Kelly, 2005). This process of automatically and continually adjusting our position in space is evident in social contexts too, such as interpersonal interaction. Compare the behavior of the museumgoer with “distance-​ standing,” or knowing how and where to stand in relation to your interlocutor during conversation. When you are too far or too close, you (usually) feel an immediate need to readjust your body, by stepping backward or forward. This isn’t a one-​and-​done reaction, but rather a process of continual readjustment. The distance-​stander’s feel for where to stand will be informed by the mood, the subject matter, the personal history between interlocutors, and the like. One can be especially adept or klutzy at automatically adjusting in these situations, particularly if one travels abroad and must learn to adjust one’s sense of appropriate distances. Some “close-​talkers,” like the one parodied on Seinfeld, chronically fail to exhibit the ordinary flexible self-​modification that typically characterizes distance-​standing. This kind of ability—​to spontaneously orient ourselves in physical and social space in the right way—​certainly supports our goals in an instrumental sense (i.e., to get the best view of the painting or to have a good conversation). But these are goals that we often do not even know we have. Museumgoers may not consciously and deliberately strive to find the right place from which to see big paintings; and few people intentionally aim to stand the right distance from others during conversation. Those who do are sometimes the worst at it. In the museumgoer and distance-​stander cases, our spontaneous moment-​ to-​moment inclinations enable us to “get  along” adequately in the world. But in other cases, our spontaneous inclinations and dispositions play key roles in

  Abstract Expressionist New York, Museum of Modern Art, New York, 2010–​2011.

11

Int roduc tion

7

exemplary action. Peter Railton describes skilled spontaneous action in the arts and in conversation: A talented saxophonist can barrel into a riveting improvised solo that shifts key and rhythm fluidly to make a satisfying expressive whole, without making decisions along the way. A wit can find a funny and all-​too-​ true remark escaping her lips even before she has thoughts about what to say—​sometimes to her regret. In such cases, individuals naturally describe themselves as acting “spontaneously” or “intuitively,” “without thinking about it.” (2014, 815–​816) Expert athletes exemplify similar phenomena. And often it seems as if their magisterial skill is in some way a product of their ability to act in an unhesitating, undoubting way. Research in sports psychology suggests that particular kinds of self-​focused thought—​thinking about how one is going to return the oncoming serve or consciously choosing which way to turn to avoid a defender—​can inhibit expert performance (Beilock, 2010). As David Foster Wallace put it, this sort of reflective hesitance “breaks the rhythm that excludes thinking.”12 This may also be tied to why top athletes sometimes seem to have very little to say about how they do what they do. Of course, it’s not for lack of intelligence. Rather, it’s because their decisions are spontaneous and unplanned. As the National Football League Hall of Fame running back Walter Payton said, “People ask me about this move or that move, but I  don’t know why I  did something. I  just did it.”13 Wallace opined on this facet of expertise too, suggesting that the genius of top tennis players may have something to do with their uncanny ability to turn off the “Iago-​like voice of the self ” (2006, 154). Experiences like these are sometimes described in terms of athletes being “in the flow.”14 “Flow” is a concept emerging from research in positive psychology on well-​being. Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi argues that flow is a kind of “optimal experience,” accessible not just in sports but through a wide range of activities. People experience flow, Csikszentmihalyi argues, when they “become so involved in what they are doing that the activity becomes spontaneous, almost automatic; they stop being aware of themselves as separate from the actions they are performing” (1990, 3–​4). Flow is found in periods of intense concentration, when one is focused on and engaged in a difficult but worthwhile task.15 Athletes and artists   Quoted in Zadie Smiths’ memoriam on David Foster Wallace. See http://​fivedials.com/​fiction/​ zadie-​smith/​ 13   Quoted in Beilock (2010, 224). See Chapter 6 for a more in-​depth discussion of these examples. 14   See my “Rationalizing Flow” (Brownstein, 2014). 15   That is, a task that one subjectively perceives to be worthwhile. Perhaps, though, flow can sometimes also be found in activities one believes to be trivial (e.g., doing crossword puzzles). If so, this 12

Introduction

8

and writers sometimes talk about being in the flow in this sense. Those who have experienced something like it probably know that flow is a fragile state. Phone calls and police sirens can take one out of the flow, as can self-​reflection. According to Csikszentmihalyi, happiness itself is a flowlike state, and the fragility of flow explains why happiness is elusive. Other examples are found in research suggesting that our spontaneous inclinations are central to some forms of prosocial behavior. This opens the door to considering the role of spontaneity in ethics. For example, in some situations, people are more cooperative and less selfish when they act quickly, without thinking carefully. David Rand and colleagues (2012), for instance, asked people in groups of four to play a public goods game. All the participants were given the same amount of money and were then asked if they would like to contribute any of that money to a common pool. Whatever was contributed to the common pool, they were told, would then be doubled by the experimenter and distributed evenly among all four participants. It turns out that people contribute more to the common pool when they make fast, spontaneous decisions. The same is true when spontaneous decision-​making is manipulated; people contribute more to the common pool when they are given less time to decide what to do. This doesn’t just reflect subjects’ calculating their returns poorly when they don’t have time to think. In economic games in which cooperative behavior is optimal, such as the prisoner’s dilemma, people act more cooperatively when they act spontaneously. This is true in one-​shot games and iterated games, in online experiments and in face-​to-​face interactions, in time-​pressure manipulation experiments and in conceptual priming experiments, in which subjects act more charitably after writing about times when their intuition led them in the right direction compared with times when careful reasoning led them in the right direction (Rand et al., 2012).16 Consider also the concept of “interpersonal fluency,” a kind of ethical expertise in having and acting upon prosocial spontaneous inclinations.17 Then President-​ Elect Obama exhibited interpersonal fluency during his botched attempt in 2009 to take the Oath of Office. In front of millions of viewers, Obama and Chief Justice of the Supreme Court John Roberts both fumbled the lines of the oath, opening the possibility of a disastrously awkward moment.18 But after hesitating for a moment,

suggests that the subjective perception of worth can conflict with one’s beliefs about which activities are worthwhile. See Chapter 4 for related discussion. Thanks to Reine Hewitt for this suggestion.   These experiments are different from those used to defend so-​called Unconscious Thought Advantage (UTA) theory. UTA experiments have typically been underpowered and have not been replicated. For a critique of UTA, see Nieuwenstein et al. (2015). 17   See Brownstein and Madva (2012a) for discussion of the following example. See Madva (2012) for discussion of the concept of interpersonal fluency. 18   For a clip of the event and an “analysis” of the miscues by CNN’s Jeanne Moos, see http://​www. youtube.com/​watch?v=EyYdZrGLRDs. 16

Int roduc tion

9

Obama smiled widely and nodded slightly to Roberts, as if to say, “It’s okay, go on.” This gesture received little explicit attention, but it defused the awkwardness of the moment, making it possible for the ceremony to go on in a positive atmos­ phere. Despite his nervousness and mistakes, Obama’s social fluency was on display. Moreover, most of us know people with similar abilities (aka “people skills”). These skills require real-​time, fluid spontaneity, and they lead to socially valuable ends (Manzini et al., 2009).19 Similar ideas are taken up in theories of virtue ethics. Aristotle argued that the virtuous person will feel fear, anger, pity, courage, and other emotions “at the right time, about the right thing, towards the right people, for the right end, and in the right way” (2000, 1106b17–​20). To become virtuous in this way, Aristotle stressed, requires training. Like the athlete who practices her swing over and over and over again, the virtuous person must practice feeling and acting on her inclinations over and over and over again in order to get them right. This is why childhood is so crucial in Aristotle’s conception of the cultivation of virtue. Getting the right habits of character at a young age enables us to be virtuous adults. The result is a picture of virtue as a kind of skilled and flexible habit, such that the ethical phronimos—​the person of practical wisdom, who acts habitually yet ethically—​is able to come up with the right response in all kinds of situations spontaneously. Contemporary virtue ethicists have voiced similar ideas. Julia Annas writes, “People who perform brave actions often say afterwards that they simply registered that the person needed to be rescued, so they rescued them; even when prodded to come up further with reasons why they did the brave thing, they often do not mention virtue, or bravery” (2008, 22). Courageous people, in other words, immediately recognize a situation as calling for a brave act, and act bravely without hesitation. Sometimes these virtuous impulses run counter to what we think we ought to do. Recall Wesley Autrey, the New York City “Subway Hero”: Autrey saved the life of an epileptic man who, in the midst of a seizure, had fallen onto the tracks. Autrey jumped onto the tracks and held the man down while the train passed just inches overhead. Afterward, Autrey reported “just reacting” to the situation. But he might well have also thought, after the fact, that he acted recklessly, particularly given that his children had been standing on the platform with him. If so, Autrey’s case would resemble those described by Nomy

  Indeed, research suggests that interpersonal fluency can be impaired in much the same way as other skills. Lonely people, Megan Knowles and colleagues (2015) find, perform worse than nonlonely people on social sensitivity tasks when those tasks are described as diagnostic of social aptitude, but not when the same tasks are described as diagnostic of academic aptitude. In fact, lonely people often outperform nonlonely people on these tasks when the tasks are described as diagnostic of academic aptitude. This is arguably a form of stereotype threat, the phenomenon of degraded performance on a task when the group of which one is a member is stereotyped as poor at that activity and that stereotype has been made salient. 19

Introduction

10

Arpaly (2004) as cases of “inverse akrasia,” in which a person acts virtuously despite her best judgment. The pride of place given to spontaneity is not limited to Western virtue ethical theories either. Confucian and Daoist ethics place great emphasis on wu-​wei, or a state of effortless action. For one who is in wu-​wei, “proper and effective conduct follows as automatically as the body gives in to the seductive rhythm of a song” (Slingerland, 2014, 7). Being in wu-​wei, in other words, enables one to be simultaneously spontaneous and virtuous. Or as Edward Slingerland puts it, “The goal is to acquire the ability to move through the physical and social world in a manner that is completely spontaneous and yet fully in harmony with the proper order of the natural and human worlds” (2014, 14). Early Chinese scholars differed on how to achieve wu-​wei. Confucius, for example, emphasized an exacting and difficult set of rituals—​akin in some ways to the kind of training Aristotle stressed—​while later thinkers such as Laozi reacted against this approach and recommended instead letting go of any effort to learn how to act effortlessly. But for all of this, spontaneity has many profound and dangerous vices, and it is surely wrong to think that acting with abandon, just as such, promotes a well-​led life. This is the problem with the way in which these ideas have percolated into the contemporary American imagination, from Obi-​Wan Kenobi teaching Luke Skywalker to “trust your feelings,” to the Nike corporation motivating athletes to “just do it,” to Malcolm Gladwell (2007) touting “the power of thinking without thinking.” One could easily come away from these venues thinking all too straightforwardly, “I should just stop thinking so much and trust all my instincts!” In some ways, we all already know this would be a terrible idea. An understanding of the dangers of acting on whims and gut feelings is embedded in common folk attitudes (e.g., are there any parents who haven’t implored their misbehaving kid to “think before you act”?). It is also embedded in Western cultural and philosophical history (e.g., in Plato’s tripartite account of the soul). Sentiments like Kahlil Gibran’s—​“ Your soul is oftentimes a battlefield, upon which your reason and your judgment wage war against your passion and your appetite” (1923, 50)—​are also familiar. These sentiments have been taken up in toned-​down form by research psychologists too. For example, Keith Payne and Daryl Cameron (2010) channel Hobbes in characterizing our implicit attitudes as “nasty, brutish, and short-​sighted,” in contrast to our reasoned beliefs and judgments. Perhaps the most familiar worry is with simply being impulsive. Indeed, we often call a nondeliberative action spontaneous when it has a good outcome but impulsive when it has a bad outcome.20 The costs of impulsivity are well documented. Walter Mischel’s “marshmallow experiments” are a locus classicus. Beginning with a group of three-​to six-​year-​olds at the Bing Nursery School at Stanford University in

  See the discussion in Chapter 5 of experimental research on folk attitudes toward the “deep self.”

20

Int roduc tion

11

the late 1960s, Mischel and colleagues began to test how children delay gratification by offering them a choice: one marshmallow now or two in fifteen minutes—​but only if the child could wait the fifteen minutes to eat the first marshmallow. What’s striking about this study only emerged over time: the children who waited for two marshmallows were better at coping with and responding to stress more than ten years later, and even had higher SAT scores when they applied to college (Mischel et al., 1988). The marshmallow experiments helped give rise to an entire subfield of research psychology focused on self-​control and self-​regulation. The objects of study in this field are familiar. For example, the four chapters dedicated to “Common Problems with Self-​Regulation” in Kathleen Vohs and Roy Baumeister’s Handbook of Self-​ Regulation (2011) focus on substance addictions, impulsive eating, impulsive shopping, and attention-​deficit/​hyperactivity disorder. These are all problems with impulsivity, and some in the field simply define good self-​regulation as the inhibition of impulses (e.g., Mischel et al., 1988). The consequences of uncontrolled impulses can be huge, of course (but so too can the conceptualization of all impulses as things to be controlled, as I discuss later).21 Problems like these with impulsivity are compounded, moreover, when one’s deliberative capacities are diminished. Behavioral economists have shown, for example, that people are much more likely to impulsively cheat, even if they identify themselves as honest people, if they are cognitively depleted (Gino et al., 2011). This finding is an example of a broad phenomenon known as “ego depletion” (Baumeister et al., 1998).22 The key idea is that self-​control is a limited resource, akin to a muscle, and that when we stifle impulses or force ourselves to focus on difficult tasks, we eventually tire out. Our self-​regulatory resources being depleted, we then exhibit poorer than usual self-​control on subsequent tasks that require self-​ control. Once depleted (by, e.g., suppressing stray thoughts while doing arithmetic), individuals are more prone to break their diets (Vohs and Heatherton, 2000), to drink excessively, even when anticipating a driving test (Muraven et al., 2002),   A case in point (of the idea that it is problematic to conceptualize all impulses as things to be controlled) is the marshmallow experiment itself, for which various explanations are available, only some of which have to do with impulsivity. While the most commonly cited explanation of Mischel’s findings focuses on the impulsivity of the children who couldn’t wait for a second marshmallow, another possibility is that the marshmallow experiment gauges the degree to which children trust the experimenter and have faith in a reliable world. See, for instance, Kidd and colleagues (2013). Thanks to Robin Scheffler for pointing out this possibility to me. Of course, the degree to which one trusts others may itself be a product of one’s spontaneous reactions. 22   There is increasing concern about research on ego depletion, however. One recent meta-​analysis found zero ego depletion effects across more than two thousand subjects (Hagger et al., 2016). But even some who have taken the reproducibility crisis the most seriously, such as Michael Inzlicht, continue to believe in the basic ego depletion effect. See http://​soccco.uni-​koeln.de/​cscm-​2016-​debate. html and see the Appendix for discussion of reproducibility in psychological science. 21

Introduction

12

and to feel and express anger (Stucke and Baumeister, 2006). In cases like these, it seems clear that we would be better at reining in our problematic impulses if our deliberative capacities weren’t depleted. In addition to undermining well-​being, spontaneity can lead us to act irration­ ally. For example, in the mid-​1990s, AIDS activist and artist Barton Benes caused controversy with an exhibition called Lethal Weapons, which showed at museums like the Chicago Art Institute and the Smithsonian. The exhibition consisted of ordinary objects filled with Benes’s or others’ HIV-​infected blood. In an interview, Benes explained how he came up with the idea for Lethal Weapons.23 He had experienced the worst of the early days of the AIDS epidemic in the United States, watching nearly half his friends die of the disease. Benes recalled the rampant fear of HIV-​positive blood and how doctors and nurses would avoid contact with him. (Benes was HIV-​positive, and like most people at the time, he knew that HIV affected patients’ blood, but didn’t know much else.) While chopping parsley in his apartment one night, Benes accidentally cut his finger. On seeing his own blood on his hands, Benes felt a rush of fear. “I was terrified I would infect myself,” he thought. The fear persisted long enough for Benes to find and wear a pair of rubber gloves, knowing all the while that his fear of contaminating himself made no sense, since he already had the disease. Later, Benes saw the experience of irrationally fearing infection from his own blood as signifying the power of the social fears and cultural associations with HIV and blood. These fears and associations resided within him too, despite his own disavowal of them. Lethal Weapons was meant to force these fears and associations into public view. Benes’s reaction was spontaneous and irrational. It was irrational in that it conflicted with what he himself believed (i.e., that he couldn’t infect himself with HIV). In this sense, Benes’s reaction is structurally similar to other “belief-​ discordant” behaviors, in which we react to situations one way, despite seeming to believe that we ought to react another way. Tamar Szabó Gendler has discussed a number of vivid examples, including people who hesitate to eat a piece of fudge molded to resemble feces, despite acknowledging that the ugly fudge has the same ingredients as a regular piece they had just eaten (2008a, 636); sports fans who scream at their televisions, despite acknowledging that their shouts can’t transcend space and time in order to affect the game’s outcome (2008b, 553, 559); and shoppers who are more willing to purchase a scarf that costs $9.99 than one that costs $10.00, despite not caring about saving a penny (2008a, 662). One of Gendler’s most striking examples is adapted from the “problem of the precipice” discussed by Hume, Pascal, and Montaigne. The modern-​day equivalent of what these early modern philosophers imagined exists today in Grand Canyon National

  See http://​www.poz.com/​articles/​217_​11353.shtml. For images of Benes’s artwork, as well as discussion of his story, see http://​www.radiolab.org/​story/​308930-​lethal-​weapons/​. 23

Int roduc tion

13

Park (among other places, such as the Willis [Sears] Tower in Chicago). It is a glass walkway extending seventy feet out from the rim of the canyon called the “Skywalk.” Tourists who venture out on the Skywalk act terrified. (Search for “Grand Canyon Skywalk” on YouTube for evidence.) They shake, act giddy, and walk in that slow, overly careful way that dogs do when they cross subway grates. But as Gendler makes clear, there is something strange about these behaviors. Presumably the tourists on the Skywalk believe that they are safe. Would they really venture onto it if they didn’t? Wouldn’t they accept a bet that they’re not going to fall through the platform? Wouldn’t you? Research by Fiery Cushman and colleagues (2012) illuminates similar phenomena in controlled laboratory settings. Diabolically, they ask subjects to perform pretend horrible actions, like smashing a fake hand with a hammer and smacking a toy baby on a table. Participants in these studies acknowledge that their actions are pretend; they clearly know that the hand and the baby are just plastic. But they still find the actions far more aversive than equally unharmful analogous actions, like smashing a nail with a hammer or smacking a broom on a table. Some of these examples lead to worse outcomes than others. Nothing particularly bad happens if you shake and tremble on the Skywalk despite believing that you’re safe. Even if nothing particularly bad happens as a result, however, the skywalker’s fear and trembling are irrational from her own perspective. Whatever is guiding her fearful reaction conflicts with her apparent belief that she’s safe. One way to put this is that the skywalker’s reaction renders her “internally disharmonious” (Gendler, 2008b). Her action-​guiding faculties are out of sync with her truth-​taking faculties, causing disharmony within her. Plato might call this a failure to be just, for the just person is one who “puts himself in order, harmonizes . . . himself . . . [and] becomes entirely one, moderate and harmonious” (Republic, 443de in Plato, 380 bce/​1992; quoted in Gendler, 2008b, 572). Whether or not failing to be just is the right way to put it, I suspect that most people can relate to the skywalker’s disharmony as some kind of shortcoming, albeit a minor one. In other cases, of course, irrational belief-​discordant behavior can lead to very bad outcomes. Arguably this is what Benes’s exhibition was meant to illustrate. The history (and persistence) of horrific social reactions to HIV and AIDS were very likely driven, at least in part, by the irrational fears of ordinary people. While HIV can be lethal, so too can mass fear. Gendler discusses research on implicit bias in a similar vein. Not only do implicit biases cause us to act irrationally, from the perspective of our own genuinely held beliefs, but they also cause us to fail to live up to our moral ends. A plethora of research on the “moral myopia” (Greene and Haidt, 2002) of spontaneous judgment supports a similar conclusion. Consider perceptions of “moral luck.” Most people believe that there is a significant moral difference between intended and accidental actions, such that accidental harms ought to be judged or

14

Introduction

punished more leniently than intended harms (or not at all).24 But when the outcomes of accidents are bad enough, people often feel and act contrary to this belief, and seem to do so on the basis of strong, and seemingly irrational, gut feelings. Justin Martin and Cushman (2016) describe the case of Cynthia Garcia-​Cisneros, who drove through a pile of leaves, only to find out later (from watching the news on TV) that two children had been hiding under the pile. The children were tragically killed. Martin and Cushman described this case to participants in a study and found that 94% of participants thought that Garcia-​Cisneros should be punished. But when another group heard the same story, except they were told that the bumps Garcia-​Cisneros felt under her car turned out to be sticks, 85% thought that she deserved no punishment. This seems irrational, given that it was a matter of pure bad luck that children were hiding in the leaves. Moreover, even though this particular study focused on participants’ considered verbal judgments, it seems likely that those judgments were the product of brute moral intuitions. When experimental participants are placed under cognitive load, and are thus less able to make deliberative judgments (compared to when they are not under load), they tend to judge accidental harms more harshly, as if those harms were caused intentionally (Buon et al., 2013). This is not due to a failure to detect harm doers’ innocent intentions. Rather, it seems that people rely on an intuitive “bad outcome = punishment” heuristic when they are under load.25 Experimental manipulations of all sorts create analogous effects, in the sense of showing how easily our intuitive nondeliberative judgments and actions can “get it wrong,” morally speaking. People tend to judge minor negative actions more harshly when they are primed to feel disgust, for example (Wheatley and Haidt, 2005). Worse still, judges in Israel were shown to render harsher verdicts before lunch than after (Danziger et  al., 2011). Both of these are examples of deliberative judgments going awry when agents’ (sometimes literal) gut feelings get things wrong. As Mahzarin Banaji (2013) put it, summarizing a half century of research on “bounded rationality” like this, we are smart compared with some species, but not smart enough compared with our own standards of rationality and morality.26 Often we fail to live up to these standards because we are the kinds of creatures for whom spontaneity can be a potent vice. 24   Although see Velleman (2015) for a discussion of interesting cross-​cultural data suggesting that not all cultures distinguish between intended and accidental harms. 25    Martin and Cushman (2016) argue that judgments about moral luck are actually rationally adaptive. See also Kumar (2017) for thoughtful discussion. 26   In other words, we are error-​prone in surprising ways, by our own standards of rationality and morality, for example, even when we are experts in a domain or when we have perfectly good intentions. See Kahneman (2003) for a summary of the many “deficits” of spontaneous and impulsive decision-​ making. For related discussion of the moral pitfalls of acting on the basis of heuristic judgments, see Sunstein (2005). For a brief reply to Sunstein that recommends a research framework similar in some respects to what I present in this book, see Bartsch and Wright (2005).

Int roduc tion

15

2. Implicitness I have suggested that understanding these virtues and vices of spontaneity requires understanding the implicit mind. But what does “implicit” mean? Ordinarily, for something to be implicit is, roughly speaking, for it to be communicated indirectly.27 When a friend repeatedly fails to return your calls, disrespect may be implicit in her inaction. If she returns your calls, but just to tell you that you’re not worth her time, then her disrespect is explicit. The disrespect is obvious, intended, and aboveboard. You don’t have to infer it from anything.28 Similarly, if I won’t make eye contact with you, my unfocused gaze suggests that perhaps I feel uncomfortable. My discomfort is implicit in my lack of eye contact. Or imagine a terrific painter. Her deep understanding of color, texture, shape, and so on may be implicit in her work. We infer her skill from what she does on the canvas, notwithstanding whatever she might or might not say explicitly about her paintings. The distinction between explicit and implicit may be familiar in these examples, but its nature is not clear. At least three senses seem to be implied when we say that so-​and-​so’s feelings, thoughts, or skills are implicit in her behavior: Implicit = unarticulated: Thoughts and feelings that are implicit are often not verbalized. Just as it would render her disrespect explicit if your friend called to say that you’re not worth her time, the discomfort bespoke by my lack of eye contact would be obviously more explicit if I told you, “It’s hard to look you in the eye because you make me feel uncomfortable.” Similarly, the painter’s understanding of color and so on would be explicit if she said, “Dabs of bright color should never superimpose hard dark lines.” The idea here is that thoughts and feelings become explicit when they are articulated, whether in verbal speech, as in these examples, or writing, or some other form of clear communication.29 Implicit  =  unconscious:  Perhaps the reason we don’t verbalize our thoughts and feelings, when they are implicit, is that we are unaware of them. When I won’t make eye contact with you, implicitly suggesting to you that I’m uncomfortable, it could be the case that I have no idea that I’m in this state. Who hasn’t been told by a loved one, “You seem sad” or “You seem angry,” and realized only then that yes, it’s true, you have been   The Oxford English Dictionary offers two additional common uses:  (1) essentially connected with (e.g., “the values implicit in the school ethos”); and (2) absolute (e.g., “an implicit faith in God”). See https://​en.oxforddictionaries.com/​definition/​implicit. 28   I’m not referring to inference in any technical sense. Understanding explicit assertions, like “You’re not worth my time,” may require inference-​making. 29   Of course, posture and eye contact and so on are forms of communication, and sometimes they can convey a message clearly. 27

Introduction

16

feeling sad or angry without knowing it at the time? This way of thinking might also elucidate cases in which people seemingly can’t articulate their feelings or thoughts. Perhaps the painter can’t express her understanding of how to paint simply because she is unaware of how she paints the way she does. She isn’t choosing not to say. She can’t explain it because perhaps it’s outside the ambit of her self-​awareness. Implicit = automatic: A final idea is that while explicit mental states are under the agent’s control, implicit states are automatic. That I avoid eye contact with you seems automatic in the sense that at no point did I form the explicit intention to “avoid eye contact.” In the right circumstances, with the right cues, it just happens. It might even be the case that if I set myself the intention to make eye contact with you, I’ll end up avoiding your eyes all the more, in just the way that you’ll automatically think of a white bear if you try not to think of one (Wegner et al., 1987). Similarly, the painter might be able to paint successfully only when “letting it flow,” giving up the effort to enact a premeditated plan. Each of these senses of implicitness draws upon a long history, running from Plato’s and St. Augustine’s ideas about parts of the soul and self-​knowledge, through Descartes’s and Leibniz’s ideas about differences between human and nonhuman animal minds, to contemporary dual-​systems psychology.30 Often these senses of what it is for something to be implicit overlap, for example, when I fail to articulate a mood that I’m unaware of being in. I also take it that while implicit mental states are often unarticulated, unconscious, and/​or automatic, sometimes they are articulated, conscious, and, to some extent, controlled. (Similarly, in my view, explicit mental states can sometimes be unarticulated, unconscious, and automatic.) For these reasons, moving forward, I do not define implicit mental states as being unarticulated, unconscious, or automatic, although they often have some combination of these qualities. Rather, as I describe below (§§3.1 and 3.2), I define implicit mental states in terms of their cognitive components and their distinctive place in psychological architecture.31 What stand out about the history of ideas underlying implicitness, particularly in the twentieth century, are the striking parallels between streams of research that focused, more or less exclusively, on either the virtues or the vices of spontaneity. Consider two examples.   For insightful discussion of the history of dichotomous views of the mind, see Frankish and Evans (2009). 31   I do, however, stress the automaticity of certain processes within implicit states. See Chapters 2 and 3. Note also that I do not offer a companion account of explicit mental states. Given that I argue, in Chapter 3, that implicit mental states are not beliefs, I am happy to consider explicit mental states beliefs, or belief-​like, and to rely upon an established theory of belief. See Chapter 3. 30

Int roduc tion

17

Beginning roughly in the middle of the twentieth century, two bodies of research focused on the phenomenon of, as Michael Polonyi put it, “knowing more than we can tell.” In The Tacit Dimension (1966/​2009), Polonyi argued that it is a pervasive fact about human beings that we can do many things skillfully without being able to articulate how we do them (cf. Walter Payton’s claim in §1). Human beings are adept at recognizing faces, for example, but few of us can say anything the least bit informative about how we do this. Polonyi’s focal examples were scientists, artists, and athletes who exemplified certain abilities but nevertheless often lacked an articulate understanding of those abilities. Contemporary research in the tacit knowledge tradition similarly focuses on skillful but unarticulated abilities, such as the tacit knowledge of laboratory workers in paleontology labs (Wylie, 2015). For Gilbert Ryle (1949) and for “anti-​intellectuals” writing in his wake, the reason that people often know more than they can tell is that knowing how to do something (e.g., knowing how to paint) is irreducible to knowing a set of propositions (e.g., knowing that red mixed with white makes pink). Ryle’s concept of “knowledge-​how,” the distinct species of knowledge irreducible to “knowledge-​ that,” exerts a greater influence on contemporary philosophy than Polonyi’s concept of tacit knowledge. Perhaps this is in part due to Ryle’s stronger claim, namely, that knowledge-​how isn’t simply unarticulated, but is in fact unavailable for linguistic articulation. For most contemporary psychologists, however, the phrase “knowing more than we can tell” is probably associated with Richard Nisbett and Timothy Wilson’s classic paper, the title of which tellingly (though unintentionally, I assume) inverts Polonyi’s phrase. In “Telling More than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes” (1977), Nisbett and Wilson captured a less admirable side of what people often do when they don’t know how or why they do things: they make shit up. In the case of Nisbett and Wilson’s seminal study, people confabulated their reasons for choosing a nightgown or pair of pantyhose from a set of options (see discussion in Chapter 6). Implied in research like this on “choice blindness” and confabulation is that these phenomena lead people to make decisions for suboptimal reasons. This study and the large body of research it inspired, in other words, take the potential gulf between the reasons for which we act and the reasons we articulate to explain our actions to be a problem. A vice. What in the tacit knowledge and knowledge-​how traditions appears as skillful activity without accompanying articulation appears in the confabulation literature as a source of poor decision-​making with confabulation covering its trail. Very similar phenomena are described in these streams of research, the salient difference between them being the normative status of the objects of study. A second example stems from twentieth-​century theories of learning. William James’s (1890) writings on habit arguably instantiated a century-​long focus on the idea that learning involves the automatization of sequences of information. William Bryan and Noble Harter’s (1899) study of telegraphers exemplified this idea. At

Introduction

18

first, they observed, telegraphers had to search for the letters effortfully. As they improved, they could search for whole words. Then they could search for phrases and sentences, paying no attention to individual letters and words. Finally, they could search for the meaning of the message. This idea—​of learning by making automatic more and more sequences of information—​was taken up in several distinct streams of research. In the 1960s, Arthur Reber developed an influential account of “implicit learning,” the most well-​known aspect of which was the artificial grammar learning paradigm. What Reber (1967) showed was that participants who were presented with strings of letters to memorize automatically absorbed grammatical rules embedded in those strings (unbeknownst to them).32 In his account of “skilled coping,” which he used to critique the idea of artificial intelligence, Hubert Dreyfus (2002a,b, 2005, 2007a,b) described the development of expertise in strikingly similar ways to Bryan and Harter (1899). George Miller (1956), in his celebrated paper on “the magic number seven, plus or minus two,” gave this process—​of the automatization of action through grouping sequences of action—​the name “chunking.” Some even applied the basic idea to an account of human progress. Alfred North Whitehead wrote: It is a profoundly erroneous truism, repeated by all copy-​books and by eminent people making speeches, that we should cultivate the habit of thinking of what we are doing. The precise opposite is the case. Civilization advances by extending the number of operations which we can perform without thinking about them. Operations of thought are like cavalry charges in a battle—​they are strictly limited in number, they require fresh horses, and must only be made at decisive moments. (1911, 61) Meanwhile, as these researchers of various stripes used the concept of automaticity to illuminate habit, skill, and (perhaps a bit grandly) the progress of history itself, psychologists interested in understanding social cognition deployed the same concept in quite a different way. Richard Shiffrin and Walter Schneider’s twin papers (1977) on controlled and automatic information processing are sometimes cited as the origin of contemporary dual-​process theories of the mind. Their focus was on distinguishing the controlled search for information from the automatic detection of patterns (in, e.g., strings of digits and letters). Notably, though, Shiffrin and Schneider’s papers received the most uptake in dual-​process theories of social cognition, in particular in research on the automaticity of stereotyping and prejudice (see, e.g., Dovidio and Gaertner, 1986; Smith and Lerner, 1986; see Frankish and Evans, 2009, for discussions). One of the core ideas here was that, just as skilled typists can find the location of letter keys without effort or attention once they have

  Reber (1989) called this implicit learning a form of tacit knowledge.

32

Int roduc tion

19

“overlearned” the location of the keys, many social judgments and behaviors are the result of repeated exposure to common beliefs about social groups. The seminal work of Russell Fazio and colleagues showing that attitudes about social groups can be activated automatically was influenced by research in cognitive psychology like Shiffrin and Schneider’s. Fazio’s (1995) “sequential priming” technique measures social attitudes by timing people’s reactions (or “response latencies”) to ster­ eotypic words (e.g., “lazy,” “nurturing”) after exposing them to social group labels (e.g., “black,” “women”). Most people are significantly faster to identify a word like “lazy” in a word scramble after being exposed to the word “black” (compared with “white”). A faster reaction of this kind is thought to indicate a relatively automatic association between “lazy” and “black.” The strength of this association is taken to reflect how well learned it is. Here, too, the core idea—​implicit learning understood in terms of automaticity—​ gives rise to structurally similar research on the virtues and vices of spontaneity. What follows, then, constitutes a hypothesis. The hypothesis is that we can come to have a better understanding of the virtues and vices of spontaneity by thinking of both as reflecting the implicit mind.

3.  The Roadmap Two chapters, following this one, are dedicated to each of the book’s three sets of central questions—​the nature of the implicit mind; the relationship of the implicit mind to the self; and the ethics of spontaneity. I describe each chapter below (§3.1–​ §3.3). In short, I argue in Chapters 2 and 3 that paradigmatic spontaneous inclinations are causally explained by “implicit attitudes.” I argue that implicit attitudes, properly understood, constitute a significantly broader class than is often described in the social psychological literature. On my view, implicit attitudes are not simply likings or dislikings outside agents’ conscious awareness and control. Chapters 2 and 3 develop my account of implicit attitudes. Then, in Chapters 4 and 5, I argue that paradigmatic spontaneous actions are “ours,” in the sense that they reflect upon us as agents. I develop an account of actions that are “attributable” to agents in this sense, based on the notion that actions are attributable to agents when the person cares—​in a broad sense—​about the intentional objects of her action. I then argue that in paradigmatic cases of spontaneity, agents care about the intentional objects of their implicit attitudes. I then go on to situate this claim with respect to questions about moral responsibility. In Chapters 6 and 7, I consider the ethics of implicit attitudes. In central cases, for both practical and conceptual reasons, we cannot simply deliberate our way to having more ethical inclinations and dispositions to act spontaneously. Instead, I argue, we must cultivate ethical implicit attitudes through practice and training. I  review the literature on self-​regulation and implicit attitude change, and provide an “aerial map” of empirically supported techniques for

Introduction

20

improving these states. Finally, in Chapter 8, I offer a short conclusion, noting what I take to be the book’s most significant upshots as well as key unanswered questions, and in the Appendix, I describe measures like the IAT in more detail and discuss challenges facing IAT research, as well as challenges facing psychological science more broadly.

3.1 Mind I begin in Chapter 2 with a description of the cognitive components of the mental states that are implicated in paradigmatic cases of spontaneous action. I describe four components: the perception of a salient Feature in the ambient environment; the experience of bodily Tension; a Behavioral response; and (in cases of success) a felt sense of Alleviation.33 States with these “FTBA” components causally explain many of our spontaneous inclinations. Identifying these components, inter alia, draws bounds around the class of spontaneous actions with which I’ll be concerned. First, I  characterize the perception of salient features in the environment in terms of their “imperatival quality.” Features direct agents to behave in a particular way immediately, in the sense that an imperative—​for example, “Heads up!”—​ commands a particular response. I offer an account of how ambient features of the environment can be imperatival in this way. Second, I argue that the feelings that are activated by an agent noticing a salient feature in the environment paradigmatically emerge into an agent’s awareness as a subtle felt tension. I describe this feeling of tension as “perceptual unquiet.” Felt tension in this sense can, but does not necessarily, emerge into an agent’s focal awareness. I describe the physiological correlates of felt tension, which are explicable in terms of the processes of low-​level affect that play a core role in guiding perception. Third, I argue that tension in this sense inclines an agent toward a particular behavior. This is why it is “tension” rather than simply affect; it is akin to feeling (perhaps subtly, perhaps strongly) pulled or pushed into a particular course of action. At this stage in the discussion I do not distinguish between actions, properly speaking, and behavior (but see Chapter 5). The important claim at this point is that particular features and particular feelings are tightly tied to particular behaviors. They are, as I discuss later, “co-​activating.” Features, tensions, and behaviors “cluster” together, in other words, and their tight clustering provides much of their explanatory power. The fourth component of FTBA states is “alleviation.” When a spontaneous action is successful, felt tension subsides and the agent’s attention is freed up for the next task. Alleviation obtains when an action is successfully completed, in other words, and it doesn’t when the agent isn’t successful. My account of this process of alleviation is rooted in theories   My account of FTBA states is most directly inspired by Gendler’s (2008a,b) account of the RAB—​Representational-​Affective-​Behavioral—​content of “alief.” See Chapter 3. I originally presented a version of this account of FTBA states with Alex Madva in Brownstein and Madva (2012b). 33

Int roduc tion

21

of “prediction-​error” learning. The way in which tension is alleviated or persists helps to explain how an agent’s dispositions to act in spontaneous or impulsive ways change—​and potentially improve—​over time. After describing the components of FTBA states in Chapter  2, I  discuss their place in cognitive architecture in Chapter 3. Are they reflexes, mere associations, beliefs, or “aliefs?” Taking a functional approach, I distinguish their place in cognitive architecture from each of these possibilities. I argue that FTBA states represent a sui generis kind of mental state: implicit attitudes. I outline the defining feature of implicit attitudes, which is that their F-​T-​B-​A components are co-​activating. This leads these states to be arational, in the sense that they are not suitable for integration into patterns of inference-​making (Levy, 2014; Madva, 2012, 2016b). Nevertheless, I argue that implicit attitudes can provide defeasible normative guidance of action. I develop this claim in terms of what Hannah Ginsborg (2011) has called “primitive normativity.”

3.2 Self How should we relate to our own implicit minds? This is a hard question given that implicit attitudes are unlike ordinary “personal” states like beliefs, hopes, and so on. But implicit attitudes are also not mere forces that act upon us. This ambiguity renders questions of praise, blame, and responsibility for spontaneity hard to assess. For example, do people deserve blame for acting on the basis of implicit biases, even when they disavow those biases and work to change them? Analogous questions are no less pressing in the case of virtuous spontaneity. When the athlete or the artist or the ethical phronimos performs well, she often seems to do so automatically and with little self-​understanding. Recall Walter Payton’s statement that he “just acts” on the field. Payton illuminates the way in which some spontaneous actions seem to flow through us, in a way that seems distinct from both “activity” and “passivity” in the philosophy of action. In Chapter  4, I  adopt an attributionist approach to the relationship between action and the self. Attributionism is broadly concerned with understanding the conditions under which actions (or attitudes) reflect upon the self.34 Attributionist theories typically argue that actions can reflect upon the self even when those actions are outside an agent’s control, awareness, and even, in some cases, reasons-​ responsiveness. This makes attributionism well suited to the idea that spontaneous action might reflect upon who one is. I argue for a “care-​based” conception of attributionism, according to which actions that reflect upon the self are those that reflect upon something the agent cares about. More specifically, I  argue for an affective account of caring, according to which cares are tightly connected to dispositions to

  My focus will be on attributability for actions, not attitudes as such.

34

Introduction

22

have particular kinds of complex feelings. To care about something, on this view, is to be affectively and motivationally tethered to it. To care about the Philadelphia Phillies, for instance, is to be disposed to be moved in various ways when they win or lose. My care-​based account of attributability is very inclusive. I argue that a great many of our actions—​including those caused by our implicit attitudes—​reflect upon our cares. The result is that implicit attitudes are indeed “ours,” and as such they open us to “aretaic” appraisals—​evaluations of us in our capacity as agents. It is important to note that my focus in Chapter 4 is not on making a metaphysical claim about the ultimate nature of the self. The self composed of one’s cares is not a thing inside one’s body; it is not the Freudian unconscious. Rather, it is a concept to be used for distinguishing actions that are mine, in the attributability sense, from actions that are not mine. My use of the term “self” will therefore depart from classical philosophical conceptions of the self, as found in Hume, for instance. Moreover, in the sense I will use it, the self is typically far from unified. It does not offer a conclusive “final say” about who one is. I clarify the relationship of the self in this sense to what some theorists call the “deep self.” The upshot of Chapter 4 is that many more actions, and kinds of action, open us to aretaic appraisal than other theorists have suggested. Spontaneous actions that conflict with what we believe and intend to do, that unfold outside our focal awareness and even outside our direct self-​control, still signal to others what kinds of people we are. Chapter 5 puts these claims into dialogue with received theories of attributionism and responsibility. What does it mean to say that we are open to praise and blame for actions that we can’t control? What are the implications of thinking of the self as fundamentally disunified? In answering these kinds of questions, I respond to potential objections to my admittedly unusual conception of actions that reflect on the self and situate it with respect to more familiar ways of thinking about agency and responsibility.

3.3 Ethics In the broadest terms, Chapters  2 and 3 offer a characterization of the implicit mind, and Chapters 4 and 5 argue that the implicit mind is a relatively “personal” phenomenon, in the sense that it reflects upon us as agents. Chapters 6 and 7 then investigate the ethics of spontaneity by considering both what works to change our implicit attitudes and how to best conceptualize the most effective approaches. In Chapter 6, I argue that deliberation is neither necessary nor always warranted in the effort to improve the ethical standing of our implicit attitudes. In part this stems from the fact that often we cannot deliberately choose to be spontaneous. In some cases, this is obvious, as the irony of the Slate headline “Hillary Clinton Hatches Plan to Be More Spontaneous” makes clear.35 Even in one’s own life,   See http://​www.slate.com/​blogs/​the_​slatest/​2015/​09/​08/​ hillary_​clinton_​reboot_​the_​nyt_​ reports_​she_​will_​show_​morehumor_​and_​heart.html. 35

Int roduc tion

23

without Clintonesque political scheming, planning to be spontaneous won’t work. In order to enjoy the sense of freedom and abandon that can come from being spontaneous, one can’t make a plan to be spontaneous next Thursday at 2:15 p.m. This won’t work because deliberative planning to be spontaneous is often self-​ undermining. In cases like this, spontaneity is what Jason D’Cruz (2013) calls “deliberation-​volatile.” One’s reasons to make spontaneous choices (e.g., dropping one’s work and going for a walk) are volatile upon deliberation; once deliberated upon, they degrade as reasons for action. I expand upon D’Cruz’s account of deliberation-​volatility and show it to be relevant to many cases of actions involving implicit attitudes. I also consider the role of deliberation in combating unwanted implicit biases. Chapter 7 develops an alternative: in order to know when and how to trust our implicit minds, and to minimize the risk of acting irrationally or immorally, we have to cultivate a “feel” for acting spontaneously. This notion risks a regress, however. Question: “How do I know whether to trust my gut right now?” Answer: “You have to trust your gut about whether to trust your gut,” and so on indefinitely. Without a deliberative route to safely acting spontaneously, it may seem that we are stuck in this regress. The aim of Chapter 7 is to help us dig our way out of it. Repurposing terms from Daniel Dennett (1989), I consider characterizing the self-​improvement of our implicit attitudes as a way of taking the “intentional stance,” the “physical stance,” or the “design stance” toward ourselves. Roughly, these mean treating our implicit attitudes as if they were things to be reasoned with, things to be manipulated as physical objects, or things to be re-​engineered. Because implicit attitude change in fact requires a hybrid of all three of these approaches, I coin a new term for the most effective strategy. In attempting to improve our implicit attitudes, we should adopt the habit stance. This means treating these mental states as if they were habits in need of (re)training. I provide an architecture of the most empirically well-​ supported techniques for (re)training our spontaneous inclinations and automatic responses. The techniques I  discuss are culled from both psychological research on self-​regulation—​including the self-​regulation of implicit bias, health behavior, addiction, and the like—​and from research on coaching and skill acquisition. After discussing these techniques, I consider broad objections to them, in particular the worry that adopting the habit stance in some way denigrates our status as rational agents.

4.  Looking Forward Spontaneity is a pervasive feature of human decision-​making and action, and many scholars interpret it in ominous terms. For example, in a review article, Julie Huang and John Bargh (2014) propose understanding individual human agents as vessels of independently operating “selfish goals.” These goals operate spontaneously

Introduction

24

when we encounter the right cues, and they do not require an agent’s awareness or endorsement. Huang and Bargh draw from some of the same research I discussed earlier, but cast it in terms that sever the sprigs of human action from human agents. They focus on studies, as they describe them, that highlight “external influences that override internal sources of control such as self-​values and personality” and models that “[eliminate] the need for an agentic ‘self ’ in the selection of all behavioral and judgmental responses” (2014, 122–​123). One way to summarize this is to say, borrowing an apt phrase from Kim Sterelny (2001), that we are “Nike organisms.” Much of what we do, we just do. This is not to say that our actions are simple or divorced from long processes of enculturation and learning. But when we act, we very often act spontaneously. One question at the heart of this book is whether being Nike organisms is thoroughly ominous in the way that Huang and Bargh and many others suggest. A broad account of spontaneity—​focused on both its virtues and vices—​resists this kind of ominous interpretation. The result is a book that is pluralist in spirit and strategy. It is pluralist about what makes a particular kind of mental state a potentially good guide for action. One way to put this is that mental states can be “intelligent” without displaying the hallmarks of rational intelligence (such as aptness to inferential processing and sensitivity to logic, as I discuss in Chapter 3). It is also pluralist about what makes an action “mine” and about the conditions of praise and blame for actions. On the view I develop, the self may be conflicted and fractured, because we often care about incompatible things. Folk practices of praise and blame mirror this fact. And, finally, the book is pluralist about sound routes to ethical action. The sorts of self-​cultivation techniques I discuss are thoroughly context-​bound; what works in one situation may backfire in another. This means that there may be no substantive, universally applicable principles for how to cultivate our spontaneous inclinations or for when to trust them. But this does not foreclose the possibility of improving them. Overall, this pluralism may make for a messy story. Nevertheless, the payoffs are worthwhile. No one (to my knowledge) has offered a broad account of the structure of implicit attitudes, how they relate to the self, and how we can most effectively regulate them.36 This account, in turn, contributes to our progress on a number of pressing questions in the philosophical vicinity, such as how to conceptualize implicit/​automatic/​unconscious/​“System 1”-​type mental systems and how to appropriately praise and blame agents for their spontaneous inclinations. Most broadly, it promises to demonstrate how we might enjoy the virtues of spontaneity while minimizing its vices.

  Thus while I will consider many friendly and rival theories to the various parts of my account, there is no rival theory to consider to the overall view I present. 36

Int roduc tion

25

The progress I  make can be measured, perhaps, along two concurrent levels, one broad and the other narrow.37 The broad level is represented by my claim that understanding spontaneity’s virtues and vices requires understanding what I  call the implicit mind. The narrow level is represented by my core specific claims about implicit attitudes, their place in relation to the self, and the ethics of spontaneity. I hope that these narrow claims promote the broad claim. However, it’s possible that I’m right on the broad level, even if some of the specific views I advance turn out to be mistaken, for either conceptual or empirical reasons (or both). I’ll be satisfied by simply moving the conversation forward here. The concept of the implicit mind is here to stay, which makes the effort of trying to understand it worthwhile.

  I borrow this broad-​and-​narrow framework for thinking about the promise of a philosophical project from Andy Clark (2015). 37

PA RT   O N E

MIND

2

Perception, Emotion, Behavior, and Change Components of Spontaneous Inclinations

In 2003, near the Brackettsville Station north of the Rio Grande, a writer for the New  Yorker named Jeff Tietz followed US Border Patrol agent Mike McCarson as he “cut sign” across the desert. “Cutting sign” means tracking human or animal movement across terrain. McCarson’s job was to cut sign of people trying to cross the desert that separates Mexico from the United States. His jurisdiction covered twenty-​five hundred square miles. To cover that much land, McCarson had to move quickly and efficiently. Tietz describes his experience: Ultimately, I began to see disturbance before I’d identified any evidence. A piece of ground would appear oddly distressed, but I couldn’t point to any explicit transformation. Even up close, I couldn’t really tell, so I didn’t say anything. But I kept seeing a kind of sorcerous disturbance. It didn’t seem entirely related to vision—​it was more like a perceptual unquiet. After a while, I pointed to a little region that seemed to exude unease and asked McCarson if it was sign. “Yup,” he said. “Really?” “Yup,” McCarson said. McCarson experienced this phenomenon at several additional orders of subtlety. In recalcitrant terrain, after a long absence of sign, he’d say, “There’s somethin’ gone wrong there.” I’d ask what and he’d say, “I don’t know—​just disturbance.” But he knew it was human disturbance, and his divinations almost always led to clearer sign. Once, we were cutting a cattle trail—​grazing cows had ripped up the sign, which had been laid down with extreme faintness—​and McCarson pointed to a spot and said, “I’m likin’ the way this looks here. I’m likin’ everything about this.” He perceived some human quality in a series of superficial pressings no wider than toadstools, set amid many hoof-​compressions of powerfully similar sizes and colors and depths. I could see no aberration at all, from five inches or five feet: it

29

Mind

30

was a cow path. But McCarson liked some physical attribute, and the relative arrangement and general positioning of the impressions. Maybe he could have stood there and parsed factors—​probably, although you never stop on live trails—​but he wouldn’t have had any words to describe them, because there are no words. (Tietz, 2004, 99). Cutting sign isn’t entirely spontaneous. McCarson’s skill is highly cultivated and, moreover, it is deployed in service of an explicit (and perhaps objectionable) goal.1 Yet Tietz’s description of McCarson highlights key features of unplanned, on-​the-​ fly decision-​making. In particular, the description contains four features that point toward the cognitive and affective components of the mental states that I will argue are distinctive of the implicit mind. First, McCarson “sees” what to do in virtue of extremely subtle signs in the environment, like barely visible pressings in the dirt. Moreover, he has minimal, if any, ability to articulate what it is he sees or what any particular sign means. This does not mean that McCarson’s perceptual expertise is magic, despite the implication of Tietz’s term “sorcerous disturbance.” McCarson’s is not another myth of the chicken-​sexer, whom once upon a time philosophers thought could tell male from female chicks through some act of seeming divination. Rather, McCarson notes clues and sees evidence, but he does so on an order of magnitude far greater than almost anyone else. Second, McCarson’s perceptual expertise is affective, and in a distinctive way. He seems to “see by feeling,” saying nothing more than that he “likes” the way something in the terrain looks. Like the cues McCarson notices in the environment, however, these action-​guiding feelings are extremely subtle. They are a far cry from full-​blown emotions. Tietz’s term “perceptual unquiet” captures this nicely. On seeing the right kind of disturbance, McCarson seems simply pulled one way or the other. This experience of being pulled one way or the other leads to the third feature of spontaneity that this vignette illuminates. McCarson’s particular perceptual and affective experiences are tied to particular behavioral reactions. On the one hand, McCarson just reacts, almost reflexively, upon seeing and feeling the right things. On the other hand, though, his reactions are anything but random. They are coordinated and attuned to his environment, even though McCarson never stops to “parse factors.” That is, McCarson cuts sign nondeliberatively, yet expertly. This is made possible by the fourth key feature, which is illuminated by Tietz’s own experience of seeing sign. On the fly, spontaneous action involves distinctive ways of learning. McCarson’s expertise has been honed over years through feedback from trial and error, a process the beginning of which Tietz just barely experiences.   I find McCarson’s skill impressive, and, as I discuss, it exemplifies features of the implicit mind. However, I find the way he uses this skill—​to enforce the immigration policies of the United States by hunting desperate people as if they were a kind of prey—​deeply unsettling. 1

Perception , Emotion , B ehav ior, and   Chang e

31

My account of the implicit mind begins with a description of these four components of unplanned spontaneous inclinations. These are (1)  noticing a salient Feature in the ambient environment; (2) feeling an immediate, directed, and affective Tension; (3) reacting Behaviorally; and (4) moving toward Alleviation of that tension in such a way that one’s spontaneous reactions can improve over time. Noticing a salient feature (F), in other words, sets a relatively automatic process in motion, involving co-​activating particular feelings (T) and behaviors (B) that either will or will not diminish over time (A), depending on the success of the action. This temporal interplay of FTBA relata is dynamic, in the sense that every component of the system affects, and is affected by, every other component.2 Crucially, this dynamic process involves adjustments on the basis of feedback, such that agents’ FTBA reactions can improve over time. By describing these components, I carve off the kinds of spontaneous actions they lead to from more deliberative, reflective forms of action. The kinds of spontaneous actions with which I’m concerned, in other words, paradigmatically involve mental states with the components I describe here. These components, and their particular interrelationships, make up a rough functional profile. I do not offer what is needed for this conclusion in this chapter alone. In this chapter, I describe the FTBA components of spontaneous inclinations. These are the psychological components of the phenomenon of interest in this book, in other words. I describe how they interact and change over time. I also ground these descriptions in relevant philosophical and psychological literature, noting alternative interpretations of the phenomena I describe. I do not, however, offer an argument in this chapter for their psychological nature. I do this in the next chapter, where I argue that these FTBA components make up a particular kind of unified mental state, which I call an implicit attitude. It could be, given the description I give in this chapter alone, that the FTBA relata represent a collection of co-​occurring thoughts, feelings, and behavior. The argument against this possibility—​that is, the argument for the claim that these FTBA components make up a unified mental state—​comes in the next chapter, where I locate states with these components in cognitive architecture. This and the next chapter combined, then, give the argument for a capacious conception of implicit attitudes as states that have these FTBA components.3

  Clark (1999) offers the example of returning serve in tennis to illustrate dynamic systems: “The location[s]‌of the ball and the other player (and perhaps your partner, in doubles) are constantly changing, and simultaneously, you are moving and acting, which is affecting the other players, and so on. Put simply . . . [in dynamic systems] . . . ‘everything is simultaneously affecting everything else’ (Port and Van Gelder, 1995, 23).” 3   For ease of exposition, I will occasionally in this chapter distinguish states with FTBA components from an agent’s reflective beliefs and judgments. I beg the reader’s indulgence for doing so, as my argument that states with FTBA components are not beliefs comes in Chapter 3. 2

32

Mind

The distinction between spontaneous and deliberative attitudes is certainly rough, and there are ways in which these FTBA relata are affected by agents’ deliberative judgments, beliefs, and so on, and vice versa (i.e., these reflective states are also affected by our implicit attitudes).4 But it is also true, I think, that this distinction between spontaneous and deliberative attitudes is fundamental to the kinds of creatures we are. In defending his own dual-​systems theory, but also dichotomous approaches to understanding the mind in general, Cushman offers a helpful political analogy: There is no sharp dividing line between Republican and Democrat. Multiple subdivisions exist within each group, and compromise, collaboration, and areas of ideological agreement exist between the two groups. So, on the one hand, it would overstate the case to claim that the American political landscape is characterized by exactly two well-​defined ideologies that interact exclusively in competition. But, on the other hand, without distinguishing between the two political parties it would be impossible to understand the [sic] American politics at all. So it goes with dual-​systems theories of learning and decision-​making. (2013, 282) While I do not focus on dual-​systems theories as such, I do think that it would be nearly impossible to understand the human mind without distinguishing between our spontaneous inclinations and dispositions, on the one hand, and our more deliberative and reflective attitudes, on the other.5 This and the next chapter combined aim to capture the distinctiveness of the first of these fundamental features of human minds, the unplanned and immediate thoughts, feelings, and actions that pervade our lives.

1. Features Features are properties of the objects of perception that make certain possibilities for action attractive. When something is seen as a feature, it has an imperatival quality. Features command action, acting as imperatives for agents, in a sense I try to clarify in this section. In the next section (§2), I discuss the crucial affective element of this command. Here I aim to do three things. First, I briefly clarify what I mean by saying that agents perceive stimuli in the ambient environment in an imperatival 4   See Fridland (2015) for a thoughtful discussion of the penetration of spontaneous and automatic features of the mind by reflective states and vice versa. 5   The FTBA components I describe clearly share key elements with so-​called System I processes. Should my account of spontaneous thought and action turn out, inter alia, to clarify dual-​systems theories, so much the better.

Perception , Emotion , B ehav ior, and   Chang e

33

way (i.e., perceive stimuli as features). In other words, I characterize the role of features, which is to tie perception closely to action (§1.1). Second, I argue that stimuli in the ambient environment are registered as features in virtue of the agent’s goals and cares, as well as the context (§1.2). Third, I consider what it is like, in perceptual experience, to encounter features (§1.3).

1.1  The Role of Features as Action-​Imperatives When McCarson cuts sign, or Benes looks at his cut finger, or the museumgoer looks at the big painting, what does each of them see? In one sense, the answer is simple: one sees twigs; the other, blood; and the third, paint on canvas. But these agents’ visual experiences have an important significance. They are not significant in the way that Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason is a significant book or in the way that my birthday is a significant day for me. Rather, the twigs and blood and paint are significant in the sense that they seem to command a particular action for these agents in these contexts. Compared with other bits of grass and dirt, where “nothing’s gone wrong,” bits of disturbance immediately compel McCarson to head in their direction. Compared with the sight of his other, nonlacerated fingers, the mere sight of Benes’s cut finger screams “danger!” Compared with other smaller paintings, the big one seems to push the museumgoer away from it. In this sense, features are significant because they act like imperatives, in the way that saying “heads up!” commands a particular behavioral response. To gain clarity on this idea, one can contrast “spectator-​first” and “action-​first” theories of perception (Siegel, 2014). According to spectator-​first theories, the fundamental role of perception is to give the agent a view of what the world is like.6 These theories conceive the perceiver as a spectator, primarily and fundamentally observing the world. The contents of perception, on this kind of view, are descriptive. (By “content,” I mean what the agent’s mind represents in virtue of being in some token perceptual state. For spectator theories of perception, the contents of perceptual experience describe what the world is like.) According to action-​first theories, the function of perception either includes, or is primarily, to guide action.7 Sometimes action-​first theories of perception posit particular kinds of mental states, states that are said to simultaneously describe how the world is and direct action. Various accounts have been offered, including Andy Clark’s (1997) “action-​oriented” representations, Ruth Millikan’s (1995, 2006)  “pushmi-​pullyu” representations, and Sterelny’s (1995) “coupled” representations. These approaches suggest that perception is both for describing the world and guiding action. Other approaches separate these roles into different functional systems, such as David Milner and Melvyn

  See Peacocke (1995), Byrne (2009), and Siegel (2010).   See Noë (2006), Kelly (2005, 2010), Nanay (2013), and Orlandi (2014).

6 7

34

Mind

Goodale’s (1995, 2008) division between the ventral informational stream, which is said to inform descriptive visual experience (i.e., what the world is like) and the dorsal informational stream, which is for guiding motor action. (See footnote 13 for brief discussion of this view.) I have no horse in the race between spectator-​first and action-​first theories, at least to the extent that these theories debate the fundamental role of perception (i.e., to describe the world or to guide action). But I do believe that action-​oriented perception—​or what I call perception with imperatival quality—​exists. There are two questions that this more minimal claim that perception can have an imperatival  quality must answer. First, in virtue of what do elements of the ambient environment become features for agents? That is, what ties perceptual experiences to specific behavioral responses? Second, what is it like, in perceptual experience, to encounter features (i.e., to perceive things in an imperatival way)? I take it that answering these questions adds support to the claim—​supported elsewhere via arguments from neural architecture (Millner and Goodale, 1995, 2008), phenomenology (Kelly, 2005, 2010), and parsimony in philosophical theories of perception (Nanay, 2013)—​that perception is sometimes imperatival. Both questions come into focus in work on the nature of inclination by Tamar Schapiro (2009), from whom I  borrow the term “imperatival perception.” She writes: Suppose all the objects in my world have little labels on them telling me what I  ought to do in response to them. My bed says “to-​be-​slept-​in,” and my chair says “to-​be-​sat-​upon.” All the radios say “to-​be-​turned-​ on.” . . . [But t]his is different from seeing the object and then seeing an imperative attached to the object. When I am inclined, my attention is necessarily drawn to certain features of the object that appear to me as practically salient. If I have an inclination to turn on radios, this must involve seeing radios as to-​be-​turned-​on in virtue of certain features of radios and of the action . . . [and such] features [must be] practically salient from the perspective of one who has this disposition. (2009, 252) Schapiro suggests that objects in an agent’s ambient environment command action when they are “practically salient.” I unpack this idea in §1.2, focusing on agents’ goals and cares, as well as on the context. Schapiro also suggests that seeing things in an imperatival way does not necessarily mean literally seeing action-​imperatives, as if beds and radios had little labels affixed to them indicating “to-​be-​slept in” and “to-​be-​turned-​on.” Instead, Schapiro suggests that it is in the nature of inclination to direct attention, such that seeing something in an imperatival way means being drawn to attend to features of that thing that are relevant to the agent. This is a claim, as I take it, about the perceptual experience of seeing things in an imperatival way. I consider this in §1.3.

Perception , Emotion , B ehav ior, and   Chang e

35

1.2  Practical Salience One way to grasp the idea of “practical salience” is to compare ordinary with abnormal cases, in which agents seem to see everything in an imperatival way. This phenomenon is known as “utilization behavior” (UB; also known as bilateral magnetic apraxia). UB is a neurological disorder that causes people to have trouble resisting an impulse to utilize objects in their visual field in ways that would be appropriate in other situations. Upon seeing a bed, for example, a UB patient may have trouble resisting an impulse to pull the sheets down and get into it, even if the bed isn’t her own and it’s the middle of the day. Or a UB patient might see a radio and feel immediately inclined to turn it on. One way to understand UB is that it severs the connection between perception and what’s relevant to the agent’s current tasks (i.e., what is practically salient to her). In other words, too much is significant, and thus salient, for the UB patient. In the ordinary case, these connections make it so that only particular features are imperatival for us. The question, then, is why some stimuli become practically salient to agents while others don’t. One way to interpret this would be in terms of spatial perspective. In this sense, only agents standing in a certain physical orientation to the objects in their perceptual field—​to twigs and radios and paintings—​will see them as imperatival. While this may be true—​a second museumgoer already standing far away from the big painting won’t be compelled to step back—​it clearly won’t work to explain other cases. Another possibility is that objects become imperatival in virtue of being connected to the agent’s evaluative perspective. In this sense, only agents who take turning on radios or stepping back from paintings to be a good thing to do in particular contexts will see these objects as imperatival. But this doesn’t seem like an adequate interpretation either. It doesn’t do justice to the perceptual quality of features, in which the imperative to act seems to precede judgment. It also would be difficult to understand a case like Benes’s in this way, since he does not think that his fearful reaction is a good one. A better option is to say that features are imperatival in virtue of a connection to an agent’s goals, cares, and context. Imagine that the museumgoer is looking for the restroom. She has a desire to find it, and thus adopts the goal of finding it. In virtue of this goal, the restroom sign may become a feature in her perceptual field. The sign will become salient, and she’ll respond immediately upon seeing it, perhaps by turning whichever way it points rather than ambling aimlessly. Notice, though, that neither the goal nor the desire to find the restroom is necessary for the sign to become a feature for the museumgoer. She might be ambling aimlessly when the sight of the sign catches her eye, making her realize that she has to go. In this case, it seems clear that the museumgoer doesn’t have the goal of finding the restroom until she sees the sign. And it also seems wrong to say that she has occurrent, or even standing desires, to find the restroom. Rather, she is disposed to encounter the restroom sign as imperatival (in virtue of having a full bladder). In Chapter 4, I develop an

36

Mind

account of cares as dispositions in a related sense. The relevant point here, though, is that the museumgoer’s noticing the sign arises in virtue of some practical connection she has to it, through her desires, her goals, or, even in the absence of these, her dispositional cares. If she is not so connected to the sign in a practical sense, she will likely not notice it at all or she’ll see it in barer representational terms (i.e., it won’t be imperatival).8 Context also plays a key role in determining whether and when stimuli become features for agents. In a chaotic space, the museumgoer may be less likely to notice the restroom sign. If she is with small children, who frequently need to go, she might be more likely to notice it. These sorts of contextual effects are pervasive in the empirical literature. Indirect measures of attitudes, like the IAT, are highly context-​sensitive (e.g., Wittenbrink et al., 2001; Blair, 2002; see the discussion in Chapter 7). I return to this example in more depth in §5.9

1.3  Perceptual Content I’ve defined features as properties of the objects of perception that make certain possibilities for action attractive. I’ve suggested that the element of features that makes certain possibilities for action attractive is their imperatival perceptual quality. And I’ve proposed that perceptual objects come to be imperatival for an agent in virtue of the agent’s goals, cares, and context. But what is it like to perceive things in an imperatival way? Ecological psychologists—​led by J. J. Gibson—​attempt to answer this question by providing a theory of “affordances.” The affordances of an environment are “what it offers the animal, what it provides or furnishes, either for good or ill” (Gibson, 1979, 127). By “offers the animal,” Gibson means the possibilities for action that appear salient to a perceiving creature. For example, terrestrial surfaces, Gibson 8   These observations are consistent with findings that there are tight interactions between the neural systems subserving “endogenous” attention—​attention activated in a top-​down manner by internal states like goals and desires—​and “exogenous” attention—​attention activated in a bottom-​up matter by environmental stimuli. See Corbetta and Shulman (2002) and Wu (2014b). Note also that Erik Rietveld and Fabio Paglieri (2012) present evidence suggesting that UB is the result of damage to the neural regions subserving endogenously driven attention. This, too, suggests that in the ordinary case features become imperatival for agents in virtue of connections between stimuli and agents’ goals and cares (due to interaction between the neural systems subserving endogenous and exogenous attention). 9   Jennifer Eberhardt and colleagues make a similar point in discussing the ways in which implicit bias affects perception, writing that “bidirectional associations operate as visual tuning devices by determining the perceptual relevance of stimuli in the physical environment” (2004, 877). See §5 for more on FTBA states and implicit bias. By “bidirectional,” Eberhardt means that social groups and concepts prime each other. For example, exposure to black faces increases the perceptual salience of crime-​ related objects, and exposure to images of crime-​related objects also increases the perceptual salience of black faces (Eberhardt et al., 2004). For a fascinating discussion of the neural implementation of the way in which task-​relevant intention affects the perception of features, see Wu (2015).

Perception , Emotion , B ehav ior, and   Chang e

37

wrote, are seen as “get-​underneath-​able” or “bump-​into-​able” relative to particular animals (1979, 128). What-​affords-​what depends on the creature perceiving the affordance. A rock that is get-​underneath-​able to a mouse is not get-​underneath-​ able to a person, although it may be step-​over-​able. In my earlier examples, the blood on Benes’s finger might be seen as to-​be-​fled-​from, while the big painting might be seen as to-​be-​stepped-​back-​from for the museumgoer. This generates a proposal: features are perceived as affordances. What it is like to perceive things in an imperatival way is what it is like to perceive things as to-​be-​φed. Features are akin to affordances in two senses. First, theories of affordances are clearly focused on the action-​guiding role of perception. Ecological psychologists argue that we don’t represent couches and balls and holes in the ground as “just there” as if we were spectators viewing the world from a detached perspective. Rather, we see couches as affording sitting, balls as affording throwing, and, for animals of a certain size and flexibility, holes in the ground as affording hiding. Moreover, theories of affordances usually stress the spontaneity of actional perception. Environments are sufficiently rich to directly provoke behavior, without the mediating work of inferences, beliefs, computations, or other sorts of “mental gymnastics,” Anthony Chemero (2009) argues. However, I refrain from arguing that features are perceived as affordances, for two reasons. First, I do not accept many of the claims theorists make about affordances, such as their perceptibility without mental computation. Second, affordances are usually characterized as properties, not of the objects of perception, but rather of various relations between agents and those objects.10 Affordances are often described as action-​possibilities, such that seeing the big painting means seeing something like “back-​up-​ability.” In contrast, on my view, features are properties of the objects of perception, not properties of the actions made salient by those objects. My claim is about the perception of the big painting as to-​be-​backed-​away-​ from, not about a perception of the back-​up-​ability of big paintings. With these clarifications in hand, what is it like to perceive things as to-​be-​φed? A central feature of this kind of perceptual experience, on my view, is that it involves “rich” properties. Rich properties of perceptual experience are any properties other than color, texture, spatial relation, shape, luminance, and motion—​the so-​called thin properties of perceptual experience (Siegel and Byrne, 2016). (I restrict my discussion here to visual perceptual experience.) Examples of rich properties that may be part of visual experience are age (i.e., being old or young), emotions (e.g.,   Thomas Stoffregen (2003), for example, argues that affordances are not just embedded “in” environments; they are also properties of “animal-​environment systems.” Chemero (2009) claims that affordances are relations between aspects of agents, which he calls “abilities,” and features of “whole” situations (which include agents). Michael Turvey and colleagues (1981) suggest that affordances are dispositional properties of objects complemented by dispositional properties of agents, which they call “effectivities,” which are in turn explained by niche-​specific ecological laws. 10

Mind

38

looking angry), and kinds (e.g., being a person or a bird). Rich property theorists hold that we perceive these properties themselves, that is, not just by way of perceiving thin properties. For example, we may see a face as angry, rather than judging or inferring anger from the shape, motion, and so on of the face. There are several reasons to think that rich properties are part of perceptual experience.11 These include the fact that the rich properties view is consistent with ordinary perceptual phenomenology, whereas the thin properties view must explain how agents get from being presented solely with properties like shape, motion, and the like to seeming to see anger in a face. The rich property view also appears to be supported by research in developmental psychology suggesting that infants perceive causality (Carey, 2009). Finally, the rich property view appears to explain perceptual learning, the effect of which is that things look differently to you (in vision) if you’ve learned about them. It is plausible to think that a curveball, for example, looks one way to a Major League Baseball batter and another way to a novice at the batting cage. And, further, it seems plausible that this difference is due to the way in which the pitch looks hittable (or not), not due to changes in thin properties alone. Perceptual learning is apropos in vice cases of spontaneity too, where, for example, the color of a person’s skin comes to be automatically associated with certain traits. These associations are culturally learned, of course, and the explanatory burden would seem to be on the thin property view to explain how when blackness, for example, becomes salient, it does so only through certain thin properties coming to be salient. The rich property of features is the way in which they are perceived as to-​be-​φed. Some theorists suggest that perceiving things in roughly this way—​as imperatival—​ precludes the possibility that we ever see things descriptively. Imperatives exhaust perceptual experience, on this view. According to what I’ll call “Exhaust,” when you see the restroom sign, you don’t see any thin properties like rectangular or white and red. Instead, all that is presented in your perceptual experience is the action-​directing content of the sign. Your experience is of something like a force compelling you to head in the direction of the bathroom. Dreyfus’s (2002a,b, 2005, 2007a,b) influential interpretation of “skilled coping” seems to subscribe to Exhaust. On Dreyfus’s view, which he in turn derives from Maurice Merleau-​Ponty (1962/​2012), at least some kinds of action entail perceiving nothing but action-​directing attractive and repellent forces. For example, Dreyfus writes, consider a tennis swing. If one is a beginner or is off one’s form one might find oneself making an effort to keep one’s eye on the ball, keep the racket perpendicular to the court, hit the ball squarely, etc. But if one is expert at the game, things are going well, and one is absorbed in the game, what   I  present the following considerations—​which are drawn largely from Siegel and Byrne (2016)—​as prima facie reasons to support the rich properties view. For developed arguments in favor of this view, see Siegel (2010) and Nanay (2011). 11

Perception , Emotion , B ehav ior, and   Chang e

39

one experiences is more like one’s arm going up and its being drawn to the appropriate position, the racket forming the optimal angle with the court—​an angle one need not even be aware of—​all this so as to complete the gestalt made up of the court, one’s running opening, and the oncoming ball. One feels that one’s comportment was caused by the perceived conditions in such a way as to reduce a sense of deviation from some satisfactory gestalt. But that final gestalt need not be represented in one’s mind. Indeed, it is not something one could represent. One only senses when one is getting closer or further away from the optimum. (2002b, 378–​379) As I interpret Dreyfus, his claim is that when one is coping intelligently with the features of the environment that are relevant to one’s tasks—​following signs, opening doors, navigating around objects—​one’s attention is absorbed by an action-​guiding feeling indicating whether things are going well or are not going well. This feeling exhausts perceptual experience and keeps one on the rails of skilled action, so to speak. What Dreyfus crucially denies, as I understand him, is any role to representational content, at least in skillful action-​oriented perception, that describes the world as being a certain way. Dreyfus claims that one only senses one’s distance from the “optimum gestalt.”12 Exhaust is not entailed by my description of features. To perceive something as to-​be-​φed does not preclude seeing that thing as a certain way. To see the painting as to-​be-​backed-​away-​from does not preclude seeing it as rectangular, for example. Moreover, while I do not want to deny that Exhaust describes a possible experience, in which one is so absorbed in an activity that all one experiences are deviations and corrections from a gestalt, I do not think Exhaust offers an informative description of the perceptual content of paradigmatic cases of spontaneous activity. The basic   Of course, Dreyfus doesn’t think that the expert tennis player could play blindfolded. My interpretation of his view is that ordinary thin perceptual properties are registered in some way by the agent, but not represented in perceptual experience. I take Dreyfus’s view to be consistent with the “Zombie Hypothesis,” according to which perception-​for-​action and perception-​for-​experience are distinct (see footnote 13). But this is my gloss on Dreyfus and not his own endorsement. Dreyfus is, however, quite clear about eschewing all talk of representations in explaining skilled action (which may leave his view at odds with some formulations of the Zombie Hypothesis). His claim is not just that agents don’t represent the goal of their action consciously, but that the concept of a representation as it is typically understood in cognitive science is explanatorily inert. For example, the first sentence of Dreyfus (2002a) reads, “In this paper I want to show that two important components of intelligent behavior, learning, and skillful action, can be described and explained without recourse to mind or brain representations” (367). What I take Dreyfus to mean, in this and other work (though I note that he is not always consistent), is that in skilled action, perception is saturated by action-​imperatives, and action-​ imperatives are conceptually distinct from mental or neural representational states (explicit or tacit) that could be understood as indicating that things are thus-​and-​so. In this sense, Dreyfus would use the term “content” differently from me, given that I defined perceptual content earlier in terms of mental representations. 12

40

Mind

properties of disturbance presumably look like something to McCarson. For example, a twig will look brown rather than purple. This something, though perhaps not consciously accessible to McCarson, has accuracy conditions, such that McCarson’s perceptual experience is accurate if the twig really is brown and not purple. Others have elaborated this criticism against Exhaust (e.g., Pautz, 2010; Siegel, 2010, 2014). I also think that Exhaust faces the difficult challenge of explaining what it is like, in perceptually rich phenomenological terms, to experience deviations and corrections from a gestalt.13 Minimally, my account of features is not committed to anything like Exhaust. A second crucial issue is whether positing rich contents in perceptual experience entails the penetration of perception by cognitive states (beliefs, intentions, etc.). It doesn’t. Features are perceived as imperatival in perceptual experience. But this could have a variety of causal origins, some of which would count as instances of cognitive penetration and some of which wouldn’t. Consider the view that our goals and intentions shift even the thin properties of visual experience. According to “Shift,” a hill that we plan to climb will look steeper than a hill that we intend to paint a picture of, for example. Shift is an anti-​modular theory of perception. Perceptual properties such as distance and height are said to change given the agent’s cognitive and emotional states. Shift is championed by, among others, Dennis Proffitt and colleagues, who claim to have shown that hills look steeper to people wearing heavy backpacks (Bhalla and Proffitt, 1999); distances look farther to people who are asked to throw a heavy ball, compared with a light one (Witt et al., 2004); balconies look higher to acrophobes than to non-​acrophobes (Stefanucci and Proffitt, 2009); and so on. Proffit and colleagues take these results to vindicate Gibsonian ecological psychology. “We have expanded on Gibson’s work to show that perceiving one affordance as opposed to another changes the perceived metric properties of the environment,” Jessica Witt and Proffitt (2008, 1490) write. According to Shift, actions and plans for action are cognitive penetrators, even of

13   Note what might be considered a spin-​off of Exhaust, that whatever content there is in imperatival perception plays no role in guiding action. Consider briefly Milner and Goodale’s (1995, 2008) influential dual-​streams account of vision, according to which visual processing is divided into two kinds, the ventral stream that informs conscious visual experience and the dorsal stream that directs motor action. Originally, Milner and Goodale supported a strong dissociation of the two streams. This entails what is known as the Zombie Hypothesis (Koch and Crick, 2001; Wu, 2014a): the dorsal stream provides no information contributing to conscious visual experience. Persuasive arguments have been given against the Zombie Hypothesis, however, and Milner and Goodale themselves have backed off from it, recognizing that the ventral and dorsal streams are, to some extent, integrated (Wu, 2014a). What this suggests is that at the level of physical implementation of visual processing, directive information for action in the dorsal stream influences what the objects of visual perception appear to be like, that is, the way vision describes them as being. Assuming the neural locations of the ventral and dorsal streams are correct, then the physical location of integration of information from the two streams might help settle the question of what gets represented in action-​oriented perception.

Perception , Emotion , B ehav ior, and   Chang e

41

thin—​and so presumably rich too—​properties of perception. The museumgoer’s restroom sign will look bigger or smaller depending on what the agent is doing or planning to do. But as Chaz Firestone and Brian Scholl (Firestone, 2013; Firestone and Scholl, 2014, 2015) have shown, many of the experimental findings cited by defenders of Shift are consistent with rival interpretations that do not involve cognitive penetration. The core ambiguity in Shift is in distinguishing cases of change within perceptual processes from cases of change due to changing inputs into perception. For example, as Firestone and Scholl (2015) argue, shifts in attention can account for many examples of apparent shifts in perceptual experience. Consider viewing a Necker cube, the appearance of which can change depending on one’s intentions (i.e., one can choose to see which cube appears in the foreground of the image). Some have taken this to be a clear instance of the penetration of low-​level visual properties by a higher-​order cognitive state (namely, one’s intentions). But as Firestone and Scholl point out, citing Mary Peterson and Bradley Gibson (1991) and Thomas Toppino (2003), changes in the Necker cube’s appearance are actually driven by subtle changes in attention, in particular by which corner of the cube one attends to. These shifts in attention provide different input into perceptual processing. This discovery preserves the boundary between perception and cognition and undermines Shift. Firestone and Scholl convincingly reinterpret many of the findings taken to support Shift in this way.14 The upshot is that positing rich contents in perception—​like the perception of features—​is orthogonal to the question of whether perception is penetrated by cognition.15 What I accept from Shift is the broad idea that actions and action plans change agents’ perceptual experiences. Moreover, and more specific to my thesis, actions and action plans shape the imperatives in perceptual experience (i.e., the φ in things being seen as to-​be-​φed), for example, as the museumgoer looks for the restroom. But I take it that in some cases seeing things as imperatival might be due to changes in attention, in other cases to perceptual judgment, and perhaps in other cases to genuine cognitive penetration. But nothing depends, for me, on this last possibility being true. I have suggested that perceiving features involves the perceptual experience of things as to-​be-​φed. This is a rich property of perceptual experience. I have argued

  Firestone and Scholl show that some of the experiments taken to support Shift have thus far failed to replicate. But Firestone and Scholl (2015) also report many successful replications, which they then reinterpret in terms that do not support Shift. 15   To establish an instance of cognitive penetration, one must hold constant the object being perceived, the perceiving conditions, the state of the agent, and the agent’s attentional focus (Macpherson, 2012). For an elaboration of the claim that one can accept a rich theory of perceptual content without thereby being committed to cognitive penetration or anti-​modularism, see Siegel and Byrne (2016), Toribio (2015), and Newen (2016). 14

Mind

42

that this claim does not deny a role for descriptive content in perceptual experience, pace Exhaust. And I have also argued that this claim does not entail a claim about the cognitive penetration of perception. What remains to be seen, though, is how perceiving features is tied to behavior. For it is one thing to see the big painting as commanding a particular response and another to actually feel commanded to respond in that way. Why, for example, does seeing blood as to-​be-​fled-​from make Benes flee? I now argue that, in paradigmatic cases of spontaneous behavior, affect plays a crucial role.

2. Tension Tension refers to the affective component of states with FTBA components, but it is not a blanket term for any emotion. Tension has two key characteristics: (1) it is “low-​level”; and (2) it is “geared” toward particular behavioral responses. The term “perceptual unquiet”—​used by Tietz to describe the affective quality of McCarson’s perceptual experience—​captures the low-​level affective quality of tension. The museumgoer sees things in a way that are not quite right, or as McCarson says, “There’s somethin’ gone wrong there.” This is a kind of “unquiet” in the sense that things seem out of equilibrium.16 In the context of discussing intuitive decision-​making about how much money to give to charity, Railton describes a similar phenomenon: Such spontaneous affective reactions might be no more articulate than a stronger positive feeling toward giving aid in one kind of case as opposed to another, or a stronger negative feeling toward failing to give. Such a summative positive or negative “intuitive sense,” of greater or lesser strength, perhaps colored by one or another emotion, is typical of the way implicit simulation and evaluation manifest themselves in consciousness. Over the course of experience, we acquire a “feel” for the things we know, and an increasingly sensitive and effective “feel” for that which we know well. (2015, 36) Note that Railton describes these spontaneous affective reactions as comparatively more strongly positive or more strongly negative. These two vectors—​strength and valence—​are crucial for determining the action-​guiding “meaning” of a perceived feature. First, consider the valence of a felt tension. While the person who feels an immediate inclination to give to charity after seeing images of starving children in impoverished countries experiences a positive imperative—​“Give!”—​the museumgoer, by contrast, experiences a negative imperative—​“Back up!” In this   See Kelly (2005) for discussion of motor action and perception being drawn toward equilibrium.

16

Perception , Emotion , B ehav ior, and   Chang e

43

context, positive and negative are not moral terms, but rather are more closely akin to approach and avoid tendencies. Second, consider the strength of a felt tension. The museumgoer might feel only the slightest unease, perhaps in the form of a barely noticed gut feeling.17 This unease might not enter into her focal awareness, but she feels it nevertheless, in just the way that one can be in a mood—​feeling grumpy or excitable or whatever—​without noticing it.18 Tension in this sense is marked by an array of bodily changes in an agent’s autonomic nervous system, including changes in cardiopulmonary parameters, skin conductance, muscle tone, and endocrine and immune system activities (Klaassen et al., 2010, 65; Barrett et al., 2007). These changes in the agent’s body may be precipitating events of full-​fledged emotions, but they need not. They are most likely to become so in jarring or dangerous situations, such as standing on glass-​bottomed platforms and facing diseased blood. It is an open empirical question when, or under what conditions, felt tensions emerge into focal awareness. One possibility is that this emergence is tied to a degree of deviation from ordinary experience. When the features one encounters are ordinary, one may be less likely to notice them explicitly. Perhaps the degree to which one notices them is proportional to the degree to which they are unexpected. It is also important to note that affective and action-​directive felt tensions need not be the product of an evaluative judgment or be consistent with an agent’s evaluative judgments. The museumgoer likely has no commitment to the correctness of a claim that stepping back from the big painting is the correct thing to do.19 A candy bar in the checkout lane of the grocery store might call to you, so to speak, pulling you to grab it, despite your judging that you don’t want to buy it. The dissociation of felt tension and evaluative judgment can go in the other direction too. You might think that spoiling yourself a little with a spontaneous impulse purchase is a good idea, but feel no inclination to buy the candy bar.20 Research by Lisa Feldman Barrett can be understood as exploring the processes involved in the unfolding of felt tension. She argues that all visually perceived   James Woodward and John Allman (2007) propose that von Economo neurons (VENs), which are found in humans and great apes but not in other primates, may be integral in the processing underlying these experiences. They write, “The activation of the serotonin 2b receptor on VENs might be related to the capacity of the activity in the stomach and intestines to signal impending danger or punishment (literally ‘gut feelings’) and thus might be an opponent to the dopamine D3 signal of reward expectation. The outcome of these opponent processes could be an evaluation by the VEN of the relative likelihood of punishment versus reward and could contribute to ‘gut feelings’ or intuitive decision-​ making in a given behavioral context” (2007, 188). 18   On unconscious affect, see Berridge and Winkielman (2003) and Winkielman et al. (2005). 19   These affective states are also typically nonpropositional, and so differ from the concept-​laden emotional evaluations that Richard  Lazarus (1991) calls “appraisals.” See Colombetti (2007) and Prinz (2004); see also Chapter 4. 20   I take this example from Susanna Siegel (2014). 17

44

Mind

objects have “affective value” and that learning to see means “experiencing visual sensations as value added” (Barrett and Bar, 2009, 1327). Value is defined in terms of an object’s ability to influence a person’s body, such as her breathing and heart rate (Barrett and Bar, 2009, 1328). Objects can have positive or negative value, indicating an approach or avoid response. In a novel way, Barrett’s research extends models of associative reward-​learning—​in which the brain assigns values to actions based on previous outcomes—​to the role of affect in visual perception. In short, when features of the environment become salient, the brain automatically makes a prediction about their value for us by simulating our previous experience with similar features (see §4). Barrett calls these predictions “affective representations” that shape our visual experiences as well as guide immediate action.21 In her words: When the brain detects visual sensations from the eye in the present moment, and tries to interpret them by generating a prediction about what those visual sensations refer to or stand for in the world, it uses not only previously encountered patterns of sound, touch, smell and tastes, as well as semantic knowledge. It also uses affective representations—​prior experiences of how those external sensations have influenced internal sensations from the body. Often these representations reach subjective awareness and are experienced as affective feelings, but they need not. (Barrett and Bar, 2009, 1325) The two roles of affective representation—​enabling object recognition and stimulating immediate action—​occur in virtue of integration of sensory information in the orbitofrontal cortex (OFC). The two functional circuits of the OFC are tied to the dorsal and ventral streams for information processing.22 While the medial OFC, which is tied to the dorsal stream, “crafts an initial affective response” to a perceived feature, the lateral OFC integrates information from the other senses in order to create a unified experience of an object in context. Or as Barrett and Moshe Bar (2009, 1330) describe these two roles: The medial OFC estimates the value of gist-​level representations. A small, round, object might be an apple if it is resting in a bowl on a kitchen counter, associated with an unpleasant affective response if the perceiver does not enjoy the taste of apples, a pleasant affective response if he or she is an apple lover and is hungry, and even no real affective change in an apple lover who is already satiated. The medial OFC not only realizes 21   Note that this picture of affective representation does not necessarily entail cognitive penetration of perception. For discussion of the relationship between predictive coding, reward learning, and cognitive penetration, see Macpherson (2016). 22   See footnote 13.

Perception , Emotion , B ehav ior, and   Chang e

45

the affective significance of the apple but also prepares the perceiver to act—​to turn away from the apple, to pick it up and bite, or to ignore it, respectively.23 Barrett’s claim that all visually perceived objects have affective value is consistent with work on “micro-​valences,” or the low-​level affective significance with which perceived entities can be tagged. Sophie Lebrecht and colleagues (2012) also propose that valence is an intrinsic component of all object perception. On their view, perceptions of “everyday objects such as chairs and clocks possess a micro-​valence and so are either slightly preferred or anti-​preferred” (2012, 2). Striking demonstrations of micro-​valences are found in social cognition, for example, in a demonstration of the evaluative significance of stereotypes in Natasha Flannigan et al. (2013). They find that men and women who are perceived in counterstereotypical roles (e.g., men nurses, women pilots) are “implicitly bad”; that is, the sheer fact that these stimuli are counterstereotypical leads individuals to implicitly dislike them.24 My claim, however, is not that all perception is affect-​laden. An ultimate theory of perception should clarify what role affect does and does not play in object recognition and action initiation. I cannot provide such a theory. It is clear that ordinary cases of explicit dissociation between affect and perception, such as seeing the candy bar but having no desire for it, don’t cut strongly one way or the other on the question of the role of affect in perception. For the view of Barrett and colleagues is that “the affect-​cognition divide is grounded in phenomenology” (Duncan and Barrett, 2007); thus even apparently affectless perception may be affectively laden after all. Other cases of dissociation may be harder to explain, though. Patients with severe memory deficits due to Korsakoff ’s syndrome, for example, appear to retain affective reactions to melodies that they have previously heard, even if they can’t recognize those melodies; similarly, while they cannot recall the biographical information about “good” and “bad” people described in vignettes, they prefer the good people to the bad people when asked twenty days later ( Johnson et al., 1985).25 In this critical vein, it seems unclear, on the basis of the claim that there is no such thing as affectless perception, how an agent who has “no real affective response” to an apple because she is satiated (as Barrett and Bar describe in the earlier quote), recognizes the object as an apple. For my purposes, what I take Barrett and colleagues’ research to offer is a plausible account of how specific affective values can combine with specific features   For more on “affective force,” see Varela and Depraz (2005, 65).   This and other findings regarding evaluative stereotypes are inconsistent with the view that “implicit stereotypes” and “implicit prejudices” represent separate constructs, reflecting separate mental processes and neural systems (Amodio and Devine, 2006, 2009; Amodio and Ratner, 2011). See Madva and Brownstein (2016) for critique of this view. See also §5. 25   Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for suggesting this example. 23 24

Mind

46

in the environment to instigate specific behavioral responses. What a perceptual sensation means to the agent—​what sort of action guidance or imperative it might generate—​may be created, as Barrett and Bar say, using feedback from previously encountered patterns of sound, touch, smell, taste, semantic knowledge, and previous affective representations. The point is not that perception must work this way. The point is that this offers a way to explain the imperatival quality of perceived features. More specifically, it helps to show how features do not generate merely generic feelings—​mere liking or disliking—​but, rather, particular feelings of tension, which are geared toward particular actions. Benes’s blood, for example, elicits an embodied reaction of fear that repels him from the scene, much as the skywalker’s fear repels her from the walkway. The same is true of the museumgoer, whose feelings of tension compel her to back up, not just to move around in any direction. This “directedness” of felt tensions is apparent in research on implicit bias too. For example, Brandon Stewart and Payne (2008) found that racial weapon bias could be reduced when people rehearsed the plan to think the word “safe” upon seeing a black face. This is, on its face, both a semantically relevant and a highly affect-​laden word to think in this context (in contrast to the more cognitive terms “quick” and “accurate,” which failed to reduce weapon bias). This suggests that the potential for affect to influence weapon bias is not via a generic dislike, as if people would be more likely to “shoot” anything they disliked. A more relevant emotion is clearly fear. Thinking the word “safe” likely activates both thoughts and feelings that interfere with the association of black men with weapons.26 I will have more to say about theories of emotion later, in particular in Chapter 4. Here I  mean only to characterize the kind of low-​level affective force that paradigmatically (on my view) accompanies the perception of salient features in the ambient environment. These relata—​perceived Features and felt Tension—​are closely tied to particular Behavioral responses.

3. Behavior Perceived features and felt tensions set a range of anatomical and bodily reactions in motion, including limb movements, changes in posture, and vocalizations. In this context, behavior refers to motor activity, rather than mental action. The anatomical and bodily reactions to features and tension I describe feed into not only the explicit behavior of people like Benes, museumgoers, skywalkers, and the like, but also into marginal actions, like nonverbal communicative acts. I consider whether the motor

  I take this point about weapons bias from Madva and Brownstein (2016).

26

Perception , Emotion , B ehav ior, and   Chang e

47

routines set in motion by perceived features and felt tension rise to the level of full-​ fledged action in Chapters 4 and 5.27 It is clear, though, that the ordinary bodily changes and movements associated with the action-​guiding states of agents in these cases are, at least minimally, integral parts of coordinated response patterns.28 The perceptual and affective components of agents’ automatic states in these cases are oriented toward action that will reduce their subtle feelings of discomfort. Upon seeing the big painting, the museumgoer feels that something is not quite right and moves in such a way as to retrieve equilibrium between herself and her environment.29 Agents’ spontaneous behavioral reactions, in other words, are typically oriented toward the reduction of felt tension. I call this state of reduced tension “alleviation” (§4). In a crude functional sense, alleviation is akin to the process whereby a thermostat kicks the furnace off. The temperature that has been set on the thermostat is the optimum point for the system, and deviations from this point trigger the system to pull the temperature back toward the optimum, at which point the system rests. Alleviation is the “resting point” with respect to spontaneous action. The particular bodily changes and motor routines that unfold in a moment of spontaneity are coordinated to reach this point, which is signaled by the reduction of felt tension (i.e., a returning to perceptual quiet, so to speak). When this point is reached, the agent is freed to engage in other activities and motor routines. The thermostat analogy is inapt, however, because the interactions of FTB relata are temporally extended and influence each other reciprocally. The salience of a perceived feature of the environment influences the duration and vivacity of tension, 27   As I do not distinguish in this chapter between behavior and action, I also do not distinguish between mental activity and mental action. In Chapters 4 and 5, I address the conditions under which behavior reflects upon the character of an agent. This is distinct from—​albeit related to—​the basic conditions of agency. To foreshadow: I intend my account of actions that reflect on the character of an agent to cover both motor and mental action. But here, in §3, I restrict my discussion to motor reactions to perceived features and felt tension. 28   Woodward and Allman (2007) argue that insular cortex is the prime input into this process. They write, “Just as the insula has the capacity to integrate a large array of complex gustatory experience into visceral feelings leading to a decision to consume or regurgitate, so fronto-​insular cortex integrates a vast array of implicit social experiences into social intuitions leading to the enhancement or withdrawal from social contact” (2007, 187). 29   Rietveld (2008) captures the directedness of action-​guiding tension by distinguishing what he calls “directed discontent” from “directed discomfort.” Directed discontent—​which Rietveld derives from an analysis of Ludwig Wittgenstein (1966)—​is characterized by affective experiences of attraction or repulsion that unfold over time and are typically not reportable in propositional form (Klaassen et al., 2010, 64). States of directed discontent are typically accompanied immediately by perceptions of opportunities for action (or affordances). Directed discomfort, by contrast, characterizes a “raw, undifferentiated rejection” of one’s situation, which does not give the agent an immediate sense of adequate alternatives (Rietveld, 2008, 980). The kind of affect I am describing is akin to directed discontent, not directed discomfort.

48

Mind

which in turn influences the strength of the impulse to act. The salience of features and vivacity of tension is itself influenced by how the agent does act. For example, the degree of salience of Benes’s blood would be influenced by the state of his goals and cares; if he had just finished watching a fear-​inducing news report about HIV, the sight of his own blood might dominate his attention, setting in motion a strongly aversive feeling. This pronounced sense of tension would cause him to feel a relatively stronger impulse to act. How he acts—​whether he grabs a nearby towel to stanch the bleeding from his cut or whether he screams and rushes to the sink—​will affect the duration of his tension, and in turn will affect the degree to which the blood continues to act as an action-​imperative to him. Similarly, the museumgoer who is distracted, perhaps by overhearing a nearby conversation, may be slower to step back from the large painting, in which case the impulse to step back may persist. Or the museumgoer who encounters the large painting in a narrow hallway may be unable to step far enough back, thus needing to find other ways to reduce her felt tension, perhaps by turning around to ignore the painting or by moving on to the next one. Conflicts in behavioral reactions to felt tensions are possible too. The frightened moviegoer who simultaneously covers her eyes with her hands but also peeks through spread fingers to see what’s happening may be reacting to two opposed felt tensions. How these conflicting tensions are (or are not) resolved will depend on the success of the agent’s behavioral reaction, as well as the changing stimuli in the theater.30 Thus while the bodily movements and readjustments involved in spontaneity may be relatively isolated from the agent’s reflective beliefs and judgments, they constantly recalibrate as FTB relata dynamically shift in response to one another over tiny increments of time. This is the process I describe as Alleviation.

4. Alleviation States with FTBA components modify themselves by eliminating themselves. In response to perceived features and felt tensions, agents act to alleviate that tension by changing their bodily orientation to the world. Gordon Moskowitz and 30   I thank an anonymous reviewer for this last example. The same reviewer asks about the case of people who are drawn to the feeling of tension. Horror movie aficionados, for example, seem to enjoy a kind of embodied tension, as perhaps do extreme sports junkies and daredevils. While the psychology of agents like these is fascinating, I take them to be outliers. Their inclination toward felt tension illuminates the paradigmatic case in which agents’ spontaneous behavioral reactions are aimed at reducing felt tension. I also suspect that, in some cases at least, agents like these make explicit, unspontaneous decisions to put themselves in a position in which they will feel extreme tension (e.g., making a deliberative decision to skydive). They might then represent an interesting case of discordance between spontaneous and deliberative inclinations. See Chapter 6 for discussion of such cases.

Perception , Emotion , B ehav ior, and   Chang e

49

Emily Balcetis (2014) express a similar notion when talking about goals more broadly (and offering a critique of Huang and Bargh’s [2014] theory of “selfish goals”): [G]‌oals are not selfish but instead suicidal. Rather than attempting to preserve themselves, goals seek to end themselves. To be sure, goals are strong; they remain accessible as time passes (Bargh et al. 2001) and do not dissipate if disrupted (e.g., Zeigarnik 1927/​1934). However, goal striving decays quickly after individuals attain their goals (e.g., Cesario et al. 2006; Förster et al. 2007; Martin & Tesser 2009; Moskowitz 2002; Moskowitz et al. 2011; Wicklund & Gollwitzer 1982). That is, goals die once completed. They do not seek to selfishly propagate their own existence, but instead seem compelled to work toward self-​termination and, in so doing, deliver well-​being and need-​ fulfillment. (2014, 151) In this sense, states with FTBA components are suicidal. How does this work? As behavior unfolds, one’s felt sense of rightness or wrongness will change in turn, depending on whether one’s initial response did or did not alleviate the agent’s sense of tension. These feelings suggest an improvement in one’s relation to a perceived environmental feature or a relative failure to improve. The temporal unfolding and interplay between behavior and tension can be represented as a dynamic feedback system. It is a dynamic system in the sense, as I have said, that every component of the system affects, and is affected by, every other component. It is a feedback system in the sense that, ceteris paribus, the agent’s spontaneous inclinations change and improve over time through a process of learning from rewards—​reduced tension, enabling the agent to notice new features and initiate new behavior—​and punishments—​persisting tension, inhibiting the agent’s ability to move on to the next task. Feelings of (un)alleviated tension feed back into further behavior, as one continues to, say, crane one’s neck or shift one’s posture in order to get the best view of the painting. This concept of dynamic feedback is crucial for two reasons: (1) it shows how states with FTBA components improve over time; and (2) as a result of (1), it shows how these states guide value-​ driven action spontaneously, without requiring the agent to deliberate about what to do. These states are self-​alleviating. Research in computational neuroscience illuminates how spontaneous inclinations like these may change and improve over time, both computationally and neurologically. I  refer to “prediction-​error” models of learning (Crockett, 2013; Cushman, 2013; Huebner, 2015; Seligman et  al., 2013; Clark, 2015). Later I’ll describe two distinct mechanisms for evaluative decision-​making: “model-​based” and “model-​free” systems (§4.1). My aim is not to provide anything like a comprehensive account of these systems, but rather to suggest that model-​free systems in particular provide a compelling framework for understanding how spontaneous inclinations self-​alleviate (i.e., change and improve over time without guidance from

Mind

50

an agent’s explicit goals or beliefs) (§4.2).31 This is not to say, however, that model-​ free learning is invulnerable to error, shortsightedness, or bias (§4.3). Indeed, the abilities and vulnerabilities of model-​free learning make it a compelling candidate for the learning mechanisms underlying both the virtues and vices of our spontaneous inclinations.

4.1  Model-​Based and Model-​Free Evaluative Learning Model-​based evaluative learning systems produce maplike representations of the world.32 They represent the actions that are available to an agent, along with the potential outcomes of those actions and the values of those outcomes. This constitutes what is often called a “causal model” of the agent’s world. In evaluating an action, a model-​based system runs through this map, calculating and comparing the values of the outcomes of different choices, based on the agent’s past experiences, as well as the agent’s abstract knowledge. A simple example imagines a person navigating through a city, computing and comparing the outcomes of taking one route versus another and then choosing the fastest route to her destination. The agent’s internal map of the city comprises a causal model of the agent’s action-​relevant “world.” This model can also be thought of as a decision tree. Running through the “branches” of a decision tree is what many commonly refer to as “reasoning” (Cushman, 2013).33 That is, model-​based systems are thought to subserve the process in which agents consider the outcomes of various possible actions, and compare those outcomes, in light of what the agent cares about or desires. This sort of reasoning is inherently prospective, since it requires projecting into the likely outcomes of hypothetical actions. For this reason, model-​based systems are sometimes referred to as “forward models.” In contrast, a model-​free system computes the value of one particular action, based on the agent’s past experience in similar situations. Model-​free systems enable value-​based decision-​making without representing complex maplike causal links between actions and outcomes. Essentially, model-​free systems compute the value of one particular action, without modeling the “world” as such. The computation is done on the basis of a comparison between the agent’s past experience in similar situations and whether the current action turns out better or worse than expected. For example, a model-​free system can generate a prediction that turning left at a familiar corner will or will not be valuable to the agent. The system   As I have already mentioned, my argument for why these processes do not issue in beliefs themselves comes in Chapter 3. 32   Parts of this section are adapted from Brownstein (2017). 33   I am indebted to Cushman for the metaphor of navigating through the city. Note that there are, of course, important differences between maps and decision trees. Thanks to Eliot Michaelson for pointing this out. 31

Perception , Emotion , B ehav ior, and   Chang e

51

does this based on calculations of the size of any discrepancy between how valuable turning left was in the past and whether turning left this time turns out better than expected, worse than expected, or as expected. Suppose that in the past, when the agent turned left, the traffic was better than she expected. The agent’s “prior” in this case for turning left would be relatively high. But suppose this time, the agent turns left, and the traffic is worse than expected. This generates a discrepancy between the agent’s past reinforcement history and her current experience, which is negative given that turning left turned out worse than expected. This discrepancy will feed into her future predictions; her prediction about the value of turning left at this corner will now be lower than it previously was. Model-​free systems rely on this prediction-​error signaling, basing new predictions on comparisons between past reinforcement history and the agent’s current actions. While there is no obvious folk-​psychological analogue for model-​free processing, the outputs of this system are commonly described as gut feelings, spontaneous inclinations, and the like.34 This is because these kinds of judgments do not involve reasoning about alternative possibilities,35 but rather they offer agents an immediate positive or negative sense about what to do. It is important to note a distinction between two views about these kinds of learning systems. A “single-​system” view claims that all mental functioning can be (or ultimately will be) explained via these mechanisms, including deliberative reasoning, conscious thought, and so on. This seems to be what Clark (2015) thinks. By contrast, a “multiple-​system” view (Crockett, 2013; Cushman, 2013; Railton, 2014; Huebner, 2016) aims to show how different mechanisms for evaluative learning underlie different kinds of behavior and judgment. The single-​system view is more ambitious than the multiple-​system view. I adopt the latter. Proponents of multiple-​system views disagree about how many systems there are, but they agree that, in Daniel Gilbert’s words, “there aren’t one.” For example, in the domain of social cognition, Cushman (2013) holds that a prediction-​error system subserves representations of actions, but not of outcomes of actions. For example, recall the work of Cushman and colleagues (2012) on pretend harmful actions, discussed in Chapter 1. This research shows that people find pretend harmful actions, like smacking a toy baby on a desk, more aversive than analogous 34   It is important to note that while model-​free processing involves mental representations of the expected outcomes of actions, it is not necessary that these representations be propositionally structured or otherwise formatted in belief-​like ways. Indeed, some view prediction-​error models as comprising a “store” of practical know-​how, only on the basis of which we are able to form states like beliefs and intentions. Railton, for example, argues that “it is thanks to our capacity for such nonpropositional, bodily centered, grounded mental maps and expectations that we are able to connect human propositional thought to the world via de re and de se beliefs and intentions” (2014, 838). Of course, this view of the relationship between model-​free processing and belief depends upon what one takes beliefs to be. I address this issue in Chapter 3. 35   But see §4.2 for a discussion of model-​free systems and counterfactual reasoning.

52

Mind

harmless actions, like smacking a broom on a desk. Cushman (2013) suggests that the key difference between these scenarios is that the first triggers model-​free representations of a harmful action, regardless of its consequences, while the second does not trigger model-​free representations of a harmful action, thus enabling agents to represent the action’s outcome. Swinging something perceived as lifelike (i.e., a toy baby), in other words, carries a negative value representation—​a “gist”-​ level impression—​which has been refined over time via prediction-​error feedback. Swinging something perceived as an object doesn’t carry this kind of negative value representation. This enables the broom-​smacking to be represented in terms of its outcome. Representations of outcomes, on Cushman’s view, are model-​based. These representations resemble models of decision trees, on the basis of which different actions, and the values of their outcomes, can be compared.36 Model-​based systems are often described as flexible, but computationally costly, while model-​free systems are described as inflexible, but computationally cheap. Navigating with a map enables flexible decision-​making, in the sense that one can shift strategies, envision sequences of choices several steps ahead, utilize “tower of Hanoi”–​like tactics of taking one step back in order to take two more forward, and so on. But this sort of navigation is costly in the sense that it involves computing many action–​outcome pairs, the number of which expand algorithmically even in seemingly simple situations. On the other hand, navigating without a map, on the basis of information provided by past experiences for each particular decision, is comparatively inflexible. Model-​free systems enable one to evaluate one’s current action only, without considering options in light of alternatives or future consequences. But navigating without a map is easy and cheap. The number of options to compute are severely constrained, such that one can make on-​the-​fly decisions, informed by past experience, without having to consult the map (and without risking tripping over one’s feet while one tries to read the map, so to speak). It is important not to oversell the distinction between model-​free and model-​ based learning systems. There is increasing evidence to suggest mutual interaction.37 But if one accepts the aforementioned rough distinction—​that model-​based systems are flexible but costly and that model-​free systems are inflexible but cheap—​ then one might be disinclined to think that model-​free learning provides an apt framework for the mechanisms underlying the process of alleviation. For it is this process, ex hypothesi, that accounts for the persistent recalibration and improvement over time of spontaneous inclinations. An inflexible system for evaluative 36   My aim is not to endorse Cushman’s view per se, but to illustrate how a multiple-​systems view explains various kinds of judgment and behavior in terms of multiple mechanisms for evaluative learning. 37   See Kishida et al. (2015) and Pezzulo et al. (2015) for evidence of information flow between model-​free and model-​based evaluative learning systems. Kenneth Kishida and colleagues, for example, offer evidence of fluctuations in dopamine concentration in the striatum in response to both actual and counterfactual information.

Perception , Emotion , B ehav ior, and   Chang e

53

learning seems like a bad model for the process I have called alleviation. But, pace the common characterization of model-​free learning systems as dumb and inflexible, there is reason to think that this kind of system can support socially attuned, experience-​tested, and situationally flexible behavior.

4.2  Model-​Free Learning and Self-​Alleviation Evidence for the adaptive improvement over time of model-​free learning systems is found across varied domains of activity. Statistical competence, for example, has been traced to model-​free learning mechanisms (Daw et al., 2011).38 Findings like these are consistent with wide-​ranging research suggesting that agents’—​even nonhuman agents’—​spontaneous judgments are surprisingly competent at tracking regularities in the world (e.g., Kolling, 2012; Preuschoff et al., 2006). Kielan Yarrow and colleagues (2009) combine this with research on motor control to understand expertise in athletics. They focus on experts’ ability to make predictive, rather than reactive, decisions, on the basis of values generated for particular actions. It is relatively uncontroversial, however, to say that model-​free learning helps to explain the competencies of spontaneous judgment and behavior in cases in which the relevant variables are repeatedly presented to the agent in a relatively stable and familiar environment. In cases like batting in baseball, this repeated presentation of outcomes in familiar situations enables the agent to update her predictions on the basis of discrepancies between previous predictions and current actions. But what about cases in which an agent spontaneously displays appropriate, and even skilled, behavior in unfamiliar environments? Interpersonal social fluency, for example, requires this. Offering a comforting smile can go terribly awry in the wrong circumstance; interpersonal fluency requires deploying the right reaction in changing and novel circumstances. The question is whether model-​free systems can explain a kind of “wide” competence in spontaneous decision-​making and behavior.39 Wide competencies are not limited to a particular familiar domain of action. Rather, they can manifest across a diverse set of relatively unfamiliar environments. One reason to think that model-​free systems can subserve wide rather than narrow (context-​bound) abilities alone is that these systems can treat novel cues that are not rewarding as predictive of other cues that are rewarding. Bryce Huebner describes this process: For example, such a system may initially respond to the delicious taste of a fine chocolate bar. But when this taste is repeatedly preceded by 38   Nathaniel Daw and colleagues (2011) do find, however, that statistical learning typically involves the integration of predictions made by both model-​based and model-​free systems. To what extent the integration of these systems is necessary for statistical learning and other spontaneous competencies is an open and important empirical question. 39   So far as I  know, Railton (2014) first discussed wide competence in spontaneous decision-​ making in this sense.

Mind

54

seeing that chocolate bar’s label, the experience of seeing that label will be treated as rewarding in itself—​so long as the label remains a clear signal that there is delicious chocolate is on the way. Similarly, if every trip to the chocolate shop leads to the purchase of that delicious chocolate bar, entering the shop may come to predict the purchasing of the chocolate bar, with the label that indicates the presence of delicious chocolate; in which case entering the shop will come to be treated as rewarding. And if every paycheck leads to a trip to the chocolate shop . . . (2016, 55)40 This kind of “scaffolding” of reward prediction is known as “temporal difference reinforcement learning” (TDRL; Sutton, 1988; Cushman, 2013). It enables model-​free systems to treat cues in the environment that are themselves not rewarding, but are predictive of rewards, as intrinsically rewarding. The chocolate shop is not itself rewarding, but is predictive of other outcomes (eating chocolate) that are rewarding. (Better: the chocolate shop is predictive of buying chocolate, which is predictive of eating chocolate, which is predictive of reward.) The key point is that the chocolate shop itself comes to be treated as rewarding. The agent need not rely on a causal map that abstractly represents A leading to B, B leading to C, and C leading to D. This helps to explain how a spontaneous and socially attuned gesture like Obama’s grin might rely on model-​ free learning.41 Smiling-at-​chief-justices  See also Cushman (2013, 280).   My view is much indebted to Huebner (2016), who argues that implicit attitudes are constructed by the aggregate “votes” cast by basic “Pavlovian” stimulus–​reward associations, model-​free reward predictors, and model-​based decision trees. Pavlovian stimulus–​reward associations are distinguished from model-​free reward predictors in that the former passively bind innate responses to biologically salient rewards, whereas the latter compute decisions based on the likelihood of outcomes and incorporate predictors of predictors of rewards. The view I present here is different from Huebner’s, however, as I argue that states with FTBA components—​in particular the process of alleviation—​are best explained by model-​free learning in particular. My view is that behavior is the result of the competition between Pavlovian, model-​free, and model-​based systems. That is, behavior is the result of the combined influence of our reflexive reactions to biologically salient stimuli (which are paradigmatically subserved by Pavlovian mechanisms), our FTBA states (paradigmatically subserved by model-​free mechanisms), and our explicit attitudes (paradigmatically subserved by model-​based mechanisms). Now, this picture is surely too simplistic, given evidence of mutual influence between these systems (see footnote 37). But to accept the mutual penetration of learning systems is not tantamount to adopting the view that these systems mutually constitute FTBA states. It is one thing to say that these states paradigmatically involve model-​free learning, which is in important ways influenced by other learning systems. It is another thing to say that these states are produced by the competition between these learning systems themselves. Architecturally, my somewhat loose way of thinking is that biologically attuned reflexes are the paradigmatic causal outputs of Pavlovian mechanisms, FTBA states are the paradigmatic outputs of model-​free learning mechanism, and explicit attitudes are the paradigmatic outputs of model-​based learning mechanisms. 40 41

Perception , Emotion , B ehav ior, and   Chang e

55

d​ uring-​presidential-​inaugurations is not itself rewarding. Or, in any case, Obama did not have past experiences that would have reinforced the value of this particular action in this particular context. But presumably Obama did have many experiences that contributed to the fine-​tuning of his micro-​expressions, such that these spontaneous gestures have come to be highly adaptive. Indeed, this adaptiveness is unusually salient in Obama’s case, where he displayed a high degree of interpersonal social fluency. And yet he might have very little abstract knowledge that he should smile in situations like this one (Brownstein and Madva, 2012a). As Cushman (2013) puts it, a model-​free algorithm knows that some choice feels good, but it has no idea why. Martin Seligman and colleagues (2013) make a similar claim. In contrast to researchers who view unconscious and automatic processes as crude and shortsighted, they describe prediction-​error models as illuminating a kind of unreflective “prospection.” They write: The implicit processes of prospection we have emphasized appear to be selective, flexible, creative, and fine-​grained. They fit into a view in which subcortical affective processes are integral with cognition (Pessoa, 2008) and serve to “attune” the individual intelligently and dynamically in response to a changing environment (Ortny et  al. 1988; Reynolds & Berridge 2008; Schwartz 2002; Schwartz & Clore 2003). (2013, 126) Note that Seligman and colleagues say that this learning process attunes individuals to changing environments. This is saying more than that prediction-​error learning attunes agents to previously encountered regularities in the environment. Consider the museumgoer, whose impulse to step back from the large painting isn’t fixed to any one particular painting. Any painting of sufficient size, in the right context, will trigger the same response. But what counts as sufficient size? Does the museumgoer have a representation of a particular square footage in mind? Perhaps, but then she would also need representations of metric units tied to behavioral routines for paintings of every other size too, not to mention representations of size for every other object she encounters in the environment, or at least for every object that counts as a feature for her. This does not seem to be how things work. Instead, as the museumgoer learns, she becomes more sensitive to reward-​predicting stimuli, which over time can come to stand in for other stimuli. The key point is that prediction-​error models of learning like these help to show how states with FTBA components can improve over time.42 Experiences of tension initiate coordinated responses directed toward their own alleviation. In turn, token

  This and the paragraphs following in this section are adapted from Brownstein and Madva (2012b). 42

56

Mind

experiences of (un)alleviation contribute to a gradual “fine-​tuning” of affective-​ behavioral associations to specific types of stimuli. This tuning process can happen rapidly or slowly. Consider Aaron Zimmerman’s (2007) example of Hope, who continues to look for the trash can under the sink even after she replaced it with a larger bin by the stove. The first, rapid type of change is visible just after Hope’s automatic impulses drive her to the wrong place. A salient feature of Hope’s environment (F: “coffee grounds!”) induces tension (T: “yuck!”) and behavioral reactions (B: “dispose under sink!”), but the response misfires and her feelings persist unalleviated (A: “still yuck!”). This state of un-​alleviation represents a discrepancy between Hope’s expectation about the location of the bin—​of which she may or may not be aware—​and the outcome of her action, which failed to eliminate her FTBA state. These unresolved feelings in turn automatically activate further responses (“Not a trash can!” “Argh!” “Move to the stove!” “Ah, garbage dispensed”). The immediacy and vivacity of these responses depend upon the size of the discrepancy between her expectations and the outcome of her behavioral response. Large discrepancies between expectations and outcomes will cause tension to persist; small discrepancies will lead to diminished tension; and no discrepancy will lead to alleviation. Her automatic reactions to these discrepancies, in the form of affective and motor responses, are not just one-​and-​done reactions to a salient cue, but integrally related components that work in concert to guide her toward alleviation and that in turn update her priors and act as a teaching signal for future automatic reactions. In cases of slower change, an agent’s sense of (un-​)alleviation in one context will contribute to the degree of tension she feels toward related actions in the future. This will strengthen or weaken the associative connections that obtain between perceptions of salient features, experiences of tension, initiation of motor routines, and new experiences of (un-​)alleviation. In this way, better or worse responses in particular situations guide agents toward better and better responses to further tensions over time. This is true even when no apparent belief revision is necessary. While Hope’s beliefs about the trash can’s location update immediately, she need not have, and may be unable to form, accurate beliefs about the different amounts of force required to toss out coffee grounds, banana peels, and peach pits (though perhaps she should be composting these anyway). The improvement in her ability to navigate through the kitchen efficiently rather than awkwardly is due to her gradually self-​modifying FTBA states. Her visceral sense of frustration when she errantly tosses some of the coffee grounds on the floor instead of in the bin will, ceteris paribus, make her less likely to repeat the mistake in the future.

4.3  Model-​Free Learning and Failure Seligman and colleagues (2013) name four related reasons for thinking that prediction-​error learning can support wide competence in spontaneous decision-​ making. First, these systems enable agents to learn from experience, given some

Perception , Emotion , B ehav ior, and   Chang e

57

prior expectation or bias. Second, they enable prior expectations to be overcome by experience over time, through the “washing out” of priors. Third, they are set up such that expected values will, in principle, converge on the “real” frequencies found in the environment, so that agents really do come to be attuned to the world. And fourth, they adapt to variance when frequencies found in the environment change, enabling relatively successful decision-​making in both familiar and relatively novel contexts. Of course, our spontaneous inclinations can get things wrong. One kind of failure can occur within the dynamics of FTBA relata. Suppose a friend leans in to whisper something important. The whisperee might rightly perceive the inward lean as an action-​imperative but under-​or overreact affectively, by being coldly indifferent or disconcertingly solicitous. That would be a failure of feeling excessive or deficient tension, or of one’s tension having the wrong valence. Alternatively, the whisperee might feel tension in the right way but under-​or overcompensate behaviorally, by leaning in too little to hear the secret or leaning in so close that she bumps heads with the whisperer. Yet another possibility for error arises even if the whisperee feels the right kind of tension and responds with an appropriate behavioral adjustment, but fails to feel the right alleviation. She might continue to fidget awkwardly after finding the optimal posture for listening to the whisperer. The whisperee can fail in any of these respects even when all of the conditions were right for her impulse to reduce her feelings of tension appropriately (even when the conditions were, as Gendler [2008b] and Huebner [2009] would say, stable and typical).43 Similarly, if one restrains one’s behavior in some way, the sense of tension will, ceteris paribus, persist. The persistent force of unalleviated feelings is evident in how the skywalker continues to shiver and tremble while restraining the impulse to flee or how the museumgoer might feel if she encountered the large painting in a narrow hallway that prevented her from stepping back. It is possible that when tension persists it has the potential to affect a person’s thoughts and behavior in various problematic ways. One speculative possibility is that unalleviated FTBA states contribute to the Zeigarnik Effect, which describes the way in which agents experience intrusive thoughts and feelings when they do not complete a task or activity (Zeigarnik, 1927/​1934). Hope might decide to leave the coffee grounds on the floor to clean up another time, but if she does so, she might feel hurried later on, as if she had too many items to cross off her list for the day. A second possibility is that unalleviated FTBA states contribute to experiences of vague and undirected anxiety, of the sort described by writers from Jean-​Paul Sartre (1956/​1993) to David Foster Wallace (2011). Sometimes tension lingers in our experience and seems to detach from any particular task. Metaphorically, we just can’t figure out what the

  This possibility of FTBA states failing even in stable and typical environments distinguishes them from rote reflexes. See Chapter 3. 43

Mind

58

analogue to stepping back from the large painting should be.44 Perhaps repeated failures to alleviate tension are additive, leading to a kind of (physiological and/​or metaphorical) hypertension. Other kinds of failure reflect conflicts with agents’ reflective values and/​or with moral goods. As Huebner (2009, 2016) emphasizes, these learning systems will be only as good as the environment in which they are trained.45 Prediction-​error learning is vulnerable to small and unrepresentative samples of experience. A person who lives in a world in which most high-​status jobs are held by men and most low-​status jobs are held by women is likely to come to implicitly associate men with concepts like competence, leadership, authority, and so on. This association will likely be reinforced by experience, not (rapidly or slowly) undermined by it. Similar outcomes will happen in the case of merely perceived environmental regularities, for example, when a person is bombarded with images in the media of black or Arab men acting in violent ways. In cases like these, agents’ spontaneous social inclinations may still be thought of as attuned to the social world, but to the wrong features of it. I consider the significance of these kinds of successes and failures in Chapter 3, where I  argue that states with paradigmatic FTBA components are implicit attitudes, a sui generis kind of mental state. My aim here has been to describe a plausible model of the evaluative learning system underlying the process of alleviation, that is, the process through which our spontaneous inclinations change over time and (sometimes) attune us to the realities and demands of the local environment.

5.  Two Case Studies I summarize my case for the FTBA components of paradigmatic spontaneous inclinations by considering two examples: skilled athletic action and implicit bias. Imagine an expert tennis player in the midst of playing a point. At the right moment she notices a salient feature, perhaps the underspin and arc of an opponent’s dropshot, and reacts immediately (F: “dropshot!”). In virtue of her goal of winning the point, the opponent’s shot is perceived as imperatival, indicating to her not just low-​level properties such as spin and arc, but an action-​oriented command to charge the net. This command is tied to her perception of the shot through a felt tension pulling the player toward the net (T: “get there!”), just as a deep shot will repel the player backward (T: “get back!”). Perhaps the contents of her perception are swamped by the imperative (although I doubt it; see discussion of Exhaust in §1.3); perhaps they shift depending on whether the dropshot is gettable or too good (as per Shift); or perhaps they shift only because of a change in her attention. Any of these is consistent with my account, and none are required by it. The   Thanks to Daniel Kelly for suggesting this metaphor.   But this is not to say that intra-​individual differences don’t exist or don’t matter.

44 45

Perception , Emotion , B ehav ior, and   Chang e

59

player’s behavioral reaction to these features and tensions—​a hard charge in the case of the dropshot—​is, as I  emphasized, highly context-​sensitive. If she is up 40–​love, the player’s felt tension might be relatively anemic, thus diminishing the imperatival force of the dropshot, considering that she cares little about the point. By comparison, at four games all and deuce in the third set, the dropshot will likely trigger explicit tension, which the player is almost sure to notice explicitly, as she is immediately inclined to give it everything she has. In other contexts, as in the museumgoer case, the player’s goals and cares might be revealed to her through these reactions; she might find herself charging harder than she realized or dogging it when she believes she ought to be playing her hardest. In all of these cases, the successes and failures of the player’s reaction feed back into future FTBA reactions. The player who overreacts to dropshots, perhaps by misperceiving the arc of the shot, feeling too much tension, or charging too hard, such that she fails to have her racquet ready to play her own shot, is left with a discrepancy between the expectation associated with these F-​T-​B reactions and the actual outcome of her response. This discrepancy will update her priors for expectations of outcomes for future reactions, in much the same way that prediction-​error learning has been shown to underlie batters’ ability to predict where pitches will cross the plate (Yarrow et al., 2009). And it will do so in a very finely individuated way, such that a love–​40 context might generate different expectations than a deuce context. In the moment, the success or failure of her responses will or will not alleviate tension, as the player either is able to move on to the next shot ( A1: “ready!”) or dwells with the feeling of having misplayed the dropshot (A2: “damn!”). Of course, the player’s improvement is not guaranteed. Her reactions may fail to self-​alleviate for a host of endogenous or exogenous reasons (as in the case of hearing someone whisper to you; see §4.3). Perhaps the player feels too much tension because she cares excessively about the point; maybe money is on the line, and her concern for it interferes with the successful unfolding of her FTBA reaction. Perhaps she cannot avoid ruminating on her fear of failure and, like Richie Tennenbaum, takes her shoes off and simply gives up on the game (but hopefully not on life too). Of course, different interpretations of this scenario are possible, some of which are rivals and some of which are simply open questions. For example, as I discussed earlier (§1.3), there are multiple possible interpretations of the perceptual content of perceived features. Likewise, there are open questions about whether some forms of perception are relatively less entwined with affect than what I have depicted, or perhaps are entirely nonaffective (§2). Other, broader strategies for understanding these cases are not consistent with my account, however. One is that the tennis player’s reaction to the dropshot can be explained in terms of a cultivated disposition to react to particular shots in particular ways. On this interpretation, there is no occurrent state, with FTBA components or otherwise, that explains her action. Another rival interpretation is that the player’s action is best explained in terms of ordinary belief–​desire psychology. On this interpretation, upon seeing the oncoming ball

60

Mind

and judging it to be a dropshot, the player forms a set of beliefs, to the effect of “That is a dropshot,” “One must charge to retrieve dropshots,” or the like, and in addition, the player forms a desire (or accesses a standing desire), to the effect of “I want to retrieve the dropshot” or “I want to win the point.” These beliefs and desires would rationalize her action, with no need of mentioning special mental states with FTBA components. These are the sort of rival interpretations of cases of spontaneity that I consider in depth in the next chapter. I don’t deny that these rival interpretations describe possible cases, but I deny that they offer the best explanation of the paradigmatic cases I’ve described. Much of the same can be said in cases involved implicit bias. Consider a professor evaluating a stack of CVs. A salient feature (F: “female name on CV!”) induces tension (T: “risky hire!”) and behavioral reactions (B: “place CV in low-​quality pile!”), which either do (A1: “next CV!”) or do not self-​alleviate (A2: “something wrong!”). Or consider a standard shooter bias case: a salient feature (F: “black face!”) induces tension (T:  “danger!”) and behavioral reactions (B:  “shoot!”), which either do (A1: “fear diminished!”) or do not self-​alleviate (A2: “still afraid!”). As in the analysis of the tennis player, there are many open questions and unsaid details here. What exactly the CV evaluator or shooter bias test participant perceives is not clear. Indirect measures like the IAT don’t typically distinguish behavior from underlying mental processes, although some suggestive evidence regarding participants’ perceptual experience exists. Using eye-​trackers, for example, Joshua Correll and colleagues (2015) found that participants in a first-​person shooter task require greater visual clarity before responding when faced with counterstereotypic targets (i.e., armed white targets and unarmed black targets) compared with stereotypic targets (i.e., unarmed white targets and armed black targets). This is suggestive that stereotypic targets are relatively imperative for these agents. The imperatival quality of the perceived feature in these trials appears to be stronger, in other words. Whether this means that the feature is easier to see, or relatively more affective, or something else is not clear from this experiment. Future research could perhaps try to replicate Correll and colleagues’ results while testing whether salient feelings of fear on stereotype-​consistent trials moderate the outcome. Such a finding would build on previous research showing that people can and do make use of their implicit biases when directed to focus on their “gut feelings” ( Jordan et al., 2007; Ranganath et al., 2008; Richetin et al., 2007; Smith and Nosek, 2011). This finding would speak to an open question in the literature on implicit bias: how putatively “cold” affectless stereotypes relate to “hot” affective prejudices. A number of researchers hold a “two-​type” view of implicit biases, that is, that there are fundamentally two kinds: implicit stereotypes and implicit evaluations (Correll et  al., 2007, 2015; Glaser, 1999; Glaser and Knowles, 2008; Stewart and Payne, 2008). On this view, a white person (for example) might have warm feelings toward black people (i.e., positive implicit evaluations) but stereotype them as unintelligent (Amodio and Hamilton, 2012). There is, however, both conceptual and empirical

Perception , Emotion , B ehav ior, and   Chang e

61

evidence against the two-​type view.46 For example, Jack Glaser (1999) and Bertram Gawronski and colleagues (2008) found that retraining implicit stereotypes changes agents’ implicit evaluations. David Amodio and Holly Hamilton’s (2012) own data reflected a difficulty participants had in associating blacks with intelligence. This suggests that, rather than tracking coldly cognitive stereotypes alone, their implicit stereotyping measure tracks the insidious and plainly negative stereotype that black people are unintelligent. This negative evaluative stereotype combines the perception of perceived features with particular affective responses in order to induce action; a salient feature (F: “black face!”) induces tension (T: “danger!”) and specific behavioral reactions (B: “shoot!”). Research supports similar conclusions in the case of biased CV evaluations. Dan-​Olof Rooth and colleagues, for example, found that implicit work-​performance stereotypes predicted real-​world hiring discrimination against both Arab Muslims (Rooth, 2010) and obese individuals (Agerström and Rooth, 2011) in Sweden. Employers who associated these social groups with laziness and incompetence were less likely to contact job applicants from these groups for an interview. In both cases, measures of evaluative stereotypes were used, and these predicted hiring discrimination over and above explicit measures of attitudes and stereotypes. As in the case of the tennis player, these co-​activating responses will vary with agents’ cares and context. Joseph Cesario and Kai Jonas (2014) find, for example, differential effects of priming white participants with the concept “young black male” depending on the participants’ physical surroundings and how threatening they perceive black males to be. Using as an outcome measure the activation of fight versus flight words, they compared the effects of the prime on participants who were seated in an open field, which would allow a flight response to a perceived threat, with the effects of the prime on participants seated in a closed booth, which would restrict a flight response. Cesario and Jonas write: Consistent with predictions, we found that the relative activation of fight-​ versus escape-​related words differed as a function of whether participants were in the booth or the field and the degree to which participants associated blacks with danger. When participants were in the booth, the more they associated black males with danger, the greater the activation of fight-​ related words. In the open field, however, the more participants associated black males with danger, the more they showed increased activation of escape-​related words. (2014, 130)47 46   See Madva and Brownstein (2016) and brief discussion in the Appendix. “One-​type” theorists hold that only one type of implicit mental state exists (Greenwald et al., 2002; Gawronski and Bodenhausen, 2006, 2011). Different one-​type theories conceptualize the relationship between stereotypes and affect within implicit mental states in different ways. 47   For more on the context sensitivity of implicit mental states, see Chapter 7.

Mind

62

I discuss in the Appendix how findings like these speak to concerns about the predictive validity of indirect measures of attitudes—​like the IAT—​as well as to broader concerns about replicability in psychological science. The point here is that familiar implicit biases are activated and affect agents’ behavior in the way that is paradigmatic of our spontaneous inclinations. This is true, too, of the ways in which implicit biases change over time, incorporating successes and failures through the feedback processes of alleviation. “Success” and “failure” are tricky notions in this context, however. Within the narrow terms of model-​free learning, an agent’s spontaneous reaction to a situation will be successful when her expectations match the outcome of her actions and her feelings of felt tension subside, thus eliminating the FTBA response (§§4.2 and 4.3). A boy who holds gender–​math stereotypes and who also lives in an environment that appears to confirm these stereotypes—​for example, he might go to a school in which no girls take or succeed in math classes, because of implicit or explicit social norms, long-​standing discriminatory organizations of career paths, and so on—​may automatically think of his father and not his mother when he needs help with his math homework. In this context, this reaction will be rewarded, updating and strengthening the boy’s prior association of males with math. The boy’s reaction might not be successful as well, and in (at least) two different senses. His FTBA reaction might go awry, as in the whispering case. He might misperceive a crucial detail of the math problem, or over-​or underreact affectively, or fail to behave at all. But in the second, more weighty sense in this context, his FTBA reaction might be (or is!) an epistemic and moral failure. His mother might be better suited to helping him with his math homework than his father. More broadly, his spontaneous reaction fails to track the truth about women’s mathematical ability as well as the overriding reasons to treat people with equal respect.48 I discuss the relationship between successful FTBA reactions and moral goods in Chapter 7. Finally, as I said in the case of the tennis player, there are rival interpretations on offer of the aforementioned claims. The potentially most threatening ones to my account interpret implicit biases in entirely different ways than I have, for example, as ordinary beliefs rather than as implicit associations. I address these rival interpretations in the next chapter.

  Regarding his epistemic failure, I am assuming that the boy’s gender–​math association is generalized to women’s innate mathematical ability. His gender–​math association could be thought of as accurate, if applied more narrowly to the girls and women in his town, contingent on their being raised in this particular environment. But implicit attitudes aren’t sensitive to contingencies like this, as I discuss in Chapter 3. Regarding the boy’s moral failure, I am here assuming a kind of moral realism, such that his FTBA reactions are morally problematic regardless of his explicit moral beliefs. 48

Perception , Emotion , B ehav ior, and   Chang e

63

6. Conclusion The descriptions given in this chapter are meant to show how a range of seemingly disparate examples of spontaneity can be identified in terms of their FTBA components. I have not yet given an argument that these components are structured in a unified way. I do so in the next chapter, where I consider cognitive architecture. I now turn to my argument that states with co-​activating FTBA components constitute implicit attitudes. They are not akin to physiological reflexes, mere associations, beliefs (whether conscious or nonconscious, truth-​tracking or modular), or traits of character. While they share a number of properties with what Gendler (2008a,b) calls “aliefs,” implicit attitudes are different in crucial respects from these too.

3

Implicit Attitudes and the Architecture of the Mind

In the preceding chapter, I  argued that paradigmatic spontaneous inclinations are characterized by four components:  (1) noticing a salient Feature in the ambient environment; (2) feeling an immediate, directed, and affective Tension; (3) reacting Behaviorally; and (4) moving toward Alleviation of that tension, in such a way that one’s spontaneous reactions can improve over time. In this chapter, I argue that these co-​activating FTBA reactions make up a unified and sui generis mental state, which I call an implicit attitude. After making some clarifying remarks about terminology, I begin by ruling out more mundane possibilities. First, I argue that implicit attitudes are not basic stimulus-​response reflexes (§1). Nor are they mere mental associations that are explainable in terms of the laws of spatiotemporal contiguity (§2). Neither are they best understood as beliefs or as traits (§§3 and 4). While they are closest to what Gendler calls “aliefs,” implicit attitudes are distinct from these as well (§5). I conclude the chapter by offering considerations that favor interpreting them as a unified mental kind (§6). I call the sui generis type of mental state implicated in paradigmatic spontaneous action an “implicit attitude” for several reasons. I began Chapter 1 by talking about “instincts,” as in “gut instincts,” but these terms are imprecise and also have the connotation of being innate. The kind of state under discussion here is, by contrast, strongly affected by social learning. Another option, following Schapiro (Chapter 2), would be to call this kind of state an “inclination.” This has the benefit of simplicity, but its simplicity comes at the cost of leaving out—​to my ear at least—​ any sense of the temporally unfolding quality of states with FTBA components. Inclinations as such might change over time, but not as a result of becoming more attuned to feature(s) of the world. Another option is “mental habits” or, perhaps better, “habitudes,” which one might define as something like multitrack habits1   I use this term in the way that theorists of virtue use it, to describe patterns of action that are durable and arise in a variety of contexts, and are also connected to a suite of thoughts, feelings, etc. (e.g., Hursthouse, 1999). 1

64

Implicit Attit ud e s and the A rchitec t ure o f the   Mind

65

with cognitive and affective components.2 I discuss limitations of this dispositional approach in §4. While I’ll argue that implicit attitudes are sui generis, I  don’t mean to suggest that I’ve discovered anything radically new about the mind or am positing a category that must be included in a “final theory” of the mind.3 The history of Western philosophy is suffused with discussion of the relationship between, on the one hand, animal spirits, appetite, passion, association, habit, and spontaneity and, on the other hand, reason, deliberation, reflection, belief, and judgment.4 Implicit attitudes are sui generis in the sense that they don’t fit neatly into any one of these familiar categories. But they fit naturally within this long history of dichotomous ways of thinking of the mind and represent, inter alia, a proposal for understanding key commonalities among the phenomena variously called passion, habit, and so on.5 In calling states with FTBA components implicit attitudes, I  draw upon the relevant empirical literature on social cognition. While there is no clearly agreed-​ upon definition of implicit attitudes in this literature, this term stems from what “attitudes” are understood to be in psychology, paired with a general sense of what it means for a mental state to be “implicit.” In psychology, attitudes are preferences (or “likings” and “dislikings”). This is, of course, different from the understanding of attitudes in philosophy, which usually refers to states with propositional content (e.g., beliefs). “Implicitness,” in psychology, is generally taken to mean outside of awareness and control. So implicit attitudes are thought to be, roughly, unconscious preferences that are difficult to control. My use of the term “implicit attitudes” is broader. In contrast to the typical usage in the psychological literature (as well as much of the relevant philosophical literature), I skirt the issues of awareness and control. Or, rather, I skirt these issues in this chapter. I  address them in subsequent chapters, where I  consider

2   See Railton (2011) for discussion of “habitudes.” Pierre Bourdieu’s “habitus” presents a related option. Bourdieu defines the habitus as being composed of “[s]‌ystems of durable, transposable dispositions, structured structures predisposed to function as structuring structures, that is, as principles which generate and organize practices and representations that can be objectively adapted to their outcomes without presupposing a conscious aiming at ends or an express master of the operations necessary in order to attain them” (1990, 53). While I think Bourdieu’s concept of habitus has much to offer, I decline to adopt it, largely because I think it is too wedded to Bourdieu’s broader sociological theories. 3   See Gendler (2008b, 557, n 5) for a similar point about the sui generis nature of alief. 4   See Evans and Frankish (2009) for more on this history. 5   Neil Levy (2014, 2016) argues that we cannot answer questions about the implicit mind—​for example, whether we are responsible for implicit biases—​by consulting our intuitions, because the way the implicit mind works is radically foreign to the perspective of folk psychology. While I am sympathetic with this point and think that our intuitions about implicit attitudes are likely to be challenged by empirical facts, I find more continuity between empirical research and folk psychology than Levy does.

Mind

66

the relationship between implicit attitudes and the self, and the ethics of spontaneity. But in this chapter, where my focus is on psychological architecture, I focus elsewhere. Awareness and control can be understood as conditions under which implicit attitudes sometimes operate. Instead of focusing on these conditions, my aim is to provide an account of the psychological nature of implicit attitudes.6 Moreover, while there is research on the role of implicit cognition in relatively banal contexts like brand preferences (e.g., Coke vs. Pepsi), by far the greatest focus in the field is on pernicious and unwanted biases. One often sees the terms “implicit attitudes” and “implicit bias” used interchangeably. This is perhaps the most obvious sense in which my use of the term “implicit attitudes” is broader than the stand­ ard usage. My focus is on the explanatory role of implicit attitudes in the context of both the virtues and vices of spontaneity. With these caveats in mind, I now move on to consider where to locate implicit attitudes in the architecture of the mind. Given that these states are activated relatively automatically when agents encounter the relevant cues, one possibility is that they are basic stimulus-​response reflexes.

1. Reflexes One sense of “reflex” describes involuntary motor behavior.7 In this context, involuntariness often means “hard-​wired.” For example, infants’ “primary reflexes”—​ such as the palmar grasp reflex and the suckling reflex—​are present from birth (or before) and then disappear over time. Some somatic reflexes that are present at birth, like the pupillary reflex, don’t disappear over time, while others not present at birth emerge through development, such as the gag and patellar reflexes. All of these reflexes are “hard-​wired” in the sense that they involve no social learning. They are, however, involuntary to various degrees. While infants will suckle at any stimuli with the right properties, adults can control their somatic reflexes, albeit indirectly. To control the patellar reflex, one can wear a stiff leg brace that prevents one’s leg from moving. To control the pupillary reflex, one can put dilation drops in one’s eyes. This suggests that involuntariness alone is not sufficient for carving reflexes off from non-​reflexes. Better are the following four properties. Reflexes are (1)  instantaneous, taking very little time to unfold. They are (2) involuntary, not in a grand sense that threatens free will, but in the local sense

  See Payne and Gawronski (2010) for similar ideas.   A different sense of “reflex” is used in physiology, in which “reflex arcs” describe the neural pathways that govern autonomic and somatic processes. These pathways are reflexive in the sense that they are physically located outside the brain. It is not this sense of reflexes that I have in mind when considering whether and how implicit attitudes are reflex-​like states. What makes these states potentially reflex-​like has little to do with their physical implementation in (or outside of) the brain. 6 7

Implicit Attit ud e s and the A rchitec t ure o f the   Mind

67

that they are relatively isolated from the agent’s intentions, goals, or desires.8 Note the term “relatively.” Reflexes are not isolated from an agent’s intentions and so on in the sense that one’s intentions are utterly powerless over them. As I said, while one cannot directly prevent one’s pupil from constricting in bright light, one can put hydroxyamphetamine drops in one’s eyes to force the iris dilator muscles to relax. A related way to put this is that reflexes are (3) relatively isolated from changes in context. To put it bluntly, the patellar reflex doesn’t care if it’s morning or night, if you’re alone or in the company of others. When the right nerve is thwacked, the response unfolds. Of course, on a very capacious interpretation of context, one could construe leg braces and hydroxyamphetamine drops as elements of the context that affect how a reflex unfolds (or doesn’t). But in the narrower sense I mean it, contextual factors affect behavioral events when they bear some relationship to the meaning of the event for the agent. This need not be a conscious relation, nor one involving the agent’s beliefs. Moderation by context can mean that some feature of the situation is related to the agent’s goals or cares. Finally, reflexes are (4) ballistic. Once a reflexive reaction starts, it unfolds until it’s complete (unless its unfolding is otherwise prevented). Implicit attitudes display some of these characteristics. They are instantaneous, in the sense that they unfold rapidly, and they are involuntary, in the sense I just described namely, that they can be initiated without being intended, planned, or the like. However, implicit attitudes are neither isolated from the agent’s context nor are they ballistic.9 Recall that agents are constantly confronted by myriad stimuli, many of which could in principle stand as features for them. The large painting stands as a feature for the museumgoer, but the light switch on the wall, ceteris paribus, doesn’t. Benes’s blood sets off his reaction, but someone else’s blood probably wouldn’t. This is because the restroom sign and Benes’s own blood are connected to the agent’s relevant goals or cares, as I discussed in Chapter 2 (also see Chapter 4). Paradigmatic cases of reflexive behavior lack this connection. Much as in the case of reflexes, implicit attitudes are set in motion more or less instantaneously and automatically when the agent encounters particular stimuli. But which stimuli set them in motion has everything to do with other elements of the agent’s psychology (her goals, cares, and her past value-​encoding experiences). While the skywalker’s knee-​knocking and quivering might persist despite her beliefs, she does stay on the Skywalk after all. Similarly, while implicit biases are recalcitrant to change by reason or willpower   Of course, I haven’t said anything to convince a determinist that free will is unthreatened in these cases. All I mean is that reflexes are involuntary in a sense distinct from the one raised by questions about free will. 9   For a broadly opposing view, focused on understanding intuitions as primitive and relatively automatic “alarm signals” that paradigmatically lead us astray, both prudentially and normatively, see Greene (2013). 8

68

Mind

alone, they are not altogether isolated from agents’ explicit attitudes and are in fact quite malleable (see Chapters 6 and 7). Psychological research on implicit attitudes also demonstrates that these states are highly affected by context. Both physical and conceptual context cues shape the way in which they unfold.10 For example, Mark Schaller and colleagues (2003) show that the relative darkness or lightness of the room in which participants sit shifts scores on implicit racial evaluations across several indirect measures, including the IAT.11 Conceptual elements of context influence implicit attitudes primarily in light of perceived group membership and social roles. Jamie Barden and colleagues (2004), for example, varied the category membership of targets by presenting the same individual in a prison context dressed as a prisoner and dressed as a lawyer, and found that implicit evaluations of the person dressed as a prisoner were considerably more negative. Similarly, Jason Mitchell and colleagues (2003) showed that implicit evaluations of the same individual—​Michael Jordan—​depended on whether the individual was categorized by race or occupation. The agent’s own emotional state also affects the activation of implicit attitudes. Nilanjana Dasgupta and colleagues (2009) found that participants who were induced to feel disgust had more negative evaluations of gay people on an IAT, although their implicit evaluations of Arabs remained unchanged. However, participants who were induced to feel anger had more negative evaluations of Arabs, while their evaluations of gay people remained unchanged.12 Context similarly influences other cases. Being on the Skywalk on a blustery day might increase a typical tourist’s aversive reaction, while taking a stroll when the wind is perfectly still might make things slightly more tolerable. Finally, implicit attitudes are not ballistic. This is because they involve dynamic feedback learning, which enables the agent’s behavior to adjust on the fly as her tension is or is not alleviated and as circumstances change. Some reflexes similarly shift and adjust, such as pupillary dilation in a room with the lights being turned off and on. But there is no learning going on there. Each reaction of the iris dilator muscles to the brightness of the room is independent of the others. Moreover, the dilator muscles will find the optimum point unless interrupted by further stimuli. In the case of spontaneous action, however, the agent’s reaction is a reaction to felt tension, and its alleviation (or lack of alleviation). The distance-​stander adjusts how far she stands from her interlocutor in respect of her feelings of tension and alleviation. This is an integrated and ongoing process, not a series of one-​and-​done reflexive reactions. This process is, as I discussed in the preceding chapter, what allows 10   W hat follows in this paragraph is adapted from Brownstein (2016). See Chapter 7 for further discussion of context and implicit attitude malleability. 11   Although I note the relatively small number of participants in this study (n = 52 in experiment 2). I note also that these results obtained only for subjects with chronic beliefs in a dangerous world. 12   See Gawronski and Sritharan (2010) for a summary and discussion of these data.

Implicit Attit ud e s and the A rchitec t ure o f the   Mind

69

implicit attitudes to improve over time—​instrumentally, epistemically, or morally, depending on the case—​and this, too, distinguishes them from mere reflexes.

2. Associations While the F, T, B, and A relata of implicit attitudes are associatively linked, these states themselves are not mere associations. By “mere” associations, I mean mental states that are activated and that change exclusively according to associative principles (Buckner, 2011). Mere associations are wholly insensitive to the meaning of words and images, as well as to the meaning of an agent’s other thoughts. They are thoroughly “subpersonal.” In the usual sense, associations are mental states that link two concepts, such as salt and pepper or donald and duck. But associations can also stand between concepts and a valence—​for example, in the association between snake and “bad”—​as well as between propositions—​for example, in the association between “I don’t want to grow up” and “I’m a Toys R Us kid.” To say that these are associations or, more precisely, to say that they have associative structure is to say that thinking one concept, like salt, will activate the associated concept, pepper.13 Why does this happen? In these examples, it is not typically thought to be because the subject has a structured thought with content like “Salt and pepper go together.”14 The proposition “Salt and pepper go together” reflects the way an agent takes the world to be. Propositions like this often express one of an agent’s beliefs. An association of salt with pepper, however, simply reflects the causal history of the agent’s acquisition of the concepts salt and pepper. More specifically, it reflects what Hume (1738/​1975) called contiguity: salt and pepper (either the concepts or the actual substances) were frequently paired together in the agent’s learning history, such that every time, or most times, the agent was presented with salt, she was also presented with pepper. Eric Mandelbaum (2015b) distinguishes between mental states with propositional and associative mental structure this way:  “Saying that someone has an associative thought green/​toucan tells you something about the causal and temporal sequences of the activation of concepts in one’s mind; saying that someone has the thought there is a green toucan tells you that a person is predicating greenness of a particular toucan.” Hume’s other laws of associative learning—​resemblance and cause and effect—​similarly produce mental associations (i.e., mental states with associative structures). These ways of coming to associate concepts, or concepts with valences, are well known to be exploited by behaviorist theories of learning.   See Mandelbaum (2015b) for discussion of associative structure, compared with associative theories of learning and thinking. 14   For an exception, see Mitchell et al. (2009). 13

Mind

70

Behavioral evidence tends to be a poor tool for determining which mental states are structured associatively. One approach is to focus on how states change over time. Propositional states are thought to change in virtue of the meaning of words or images. This is because there are specific relations between the constituents of propositional states (Levy, 2014). If I  believe that “salt and pepper go together,” I have placed the constituents of this thought—​salt and pepper—​together in virtue of some meaningful relation (e.g., that they are well-​paired seasonings). One would expect this state to change upon encountering thoughts or images that are relevant to this relation (e.g., the thought that tarragon complements salt better than pepper). This can be thought of as “content-​driven” change. Content-​driven changes are evident when a mental state changes in virtue of the content of some other mental state (Levy, 2014).15 Here’s another example: I might go from the thought that “I don’t need a hat today” to the thought that “I need a hat today” in virtue of acquiring the belief that “it’s cold outside.” My thought about needing a hat counts as content-​ driven if it is true that it changed in virtue of the meaning of the thought “It’s cold outside.” My hat-​attitude counts as content-​driven, in other words, and therefore isn’t a mere hat–​cold association, if it demonstrates sensitivity to the meaning of my, or others’, thoughts about the weather. Merely thinking the concept cold wouldn’t change my hat-​attitude in this case. Nor would my hat-​attitude change in virtue of the association cold–​today coming to mind, since this association doesn’t predicate the quality of coldness onto the weather today. In contrast, associations are thought to change exclusively in terms of associative principles. Traditionally, two such principles are recognized (Mandelbaum, 2015a). The first is extinction, in which one part of an associative pair is repeatedly presented without the other and the agent unlearns the association over time. The second is counterconditioning, in which the valence of an association is reversed (e.g., by frequent pairing of snake with positively valenced stimuli). Implicit attitudes appear to change in both associative and propositional ways. Implicit attitudes (in the ordinary sense) change through counterconditioning, for instance, by exposing agents to images of counterstereotypes (Blair et al., 2001; Dasgupta and Greenwald, 2001; Weisbuch et  al., 2009). This process shifts the agent’s exposure to stereotypes that in turn form the basis for associative learning through contiguity (i.e., the frequent pairing of stimuli). The literature on evaluative conditioning is vast, suggesting similar processes (Olson and Fazio, 2006). However, these same implicit attitudes also seem to be sensitive to the meaning of words and images. The context effects I  discussed earlier (§1) suggest as much. For example, Jennifer Kubota and Tiffany Ito (2014) showed that happy versus angry emotional facial expressions moderate the activation of black–​danger   This is not to say, though, that states like belief can’t change due to a change in an agent’s associations. Culinary beliefs about seasonings are surely influenced or even driven by frequency of pairings. No claim of modularity is being made here. 15

Implicit Attit ud e s and the A rchitec t ure o f the   Mind

71

implicit stereotyping. Smiling black faces elicit lower levels of implicit stereotyping of black men as dangerous compared with angry black faces (for white subjects). This change in implicit attitudes, due to changes in the perception of the emotional expression of others’ faces, appears to be driven by sensitivity to the meaning of the relationship between facial expression and danger (i.e., to the thought that people who smile are less likely to be dangerous than people who look angry).16 Other evidence for content-​driven changes in implicit attitudes stems from research on “halo” and “compensation” effects. These are adjustments along particular dimensions that reflect quite a lot of complexity in agents’ social attitudes. “Benevolent sexism” is a classic compensation effect, for example. Stereotyping women as incompetent leads to greater feelings of warmth toward them (Dardenne et  al., 2007). Perceptions of competence and feelings of warmth are sometimes inversely related like this (i.e., a compensation effect), but other times are positively related, such as when liking one’s own group leads one to think of it as more competent (i.e., a halo effect). These phenomena are found in research on implicit attitudes. Rickard Carlsson and Fredrik Björklund (2010), for example, found evidence for implicit compensation effects toward out-​groups, but not toward in-​groups. While psychology students implicitly stereotyped lawyers as competent and cold, and preschool teachers as incompetent and warm, preschool teachers implicitly stereotyped their own group as both warm and competent. Other cases that I’ve discussed display similar patterns. Consider the skywalker’s acrophobia. Exposure therapies appear to be effective for treating fear of heights. Over time, simply being exposed to the Skywalk is likely to cause the agent to cease her fear and trembling. This looks to be a case of extinguishing a high up–​ danger association by repeatedly presenting one element of the association to the agent without the other. But most exposure therapies don’t just expose the agent to one element of the associative pair without the other. Rather, most also include

16   Alternative explanations are available here, however. One is that presentation of the stimuli changes subjects’ moods, and their implicit attitudes shift in response to their change in mood. In this case, the change wouldn’t be due to sensitivity to the meaning of the relationship between facial expression and danger. (Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for suggesting this possibility.) An associative explanation is possible here as well. Gawronski and colleagues (2017) argue that multilayer neural networks involving both excitatory and inhibitory links are capable of explaining these phenomena. This is an open question for future research, one which depends upon experimental designs that can isolate changes in implicit attitudes themselves rather than changes in controlled processes that affect the activation of implicit attitudes. New multinomial “process dissociation” models, which are used for breaking down the contributing factors to performance on tests such as the IAT, are promising for this purpose. Note also that Gawronski and colleagues’ proposal regarding multilayer neural networks departs from the basic claim that I am evaluating here, which is that implicit attitudes are mere associations. So if their interpretation of this kind of experiment were to be vindicated, it wouldn’t entail that implicit attitudes are mere associations.

72

Mind

cognitive elements, such as teaching the agent to replace problematic thoughts with helpful ones. This looks to be a case of content-​driven change.17 Of course, it’s difficult, if not impossible, to tell what’s happening on a case-​ by-​case basis. Apparent content-​driven change, for example, can sometimes be explained using associative tools. This is possible, for example, in cases in which implicit attitudes appear to demonstrate “balance” and “cognitive dissonance” effects. The thought “I am a good person” (or a good–​me association), paired with the thought “Bad people do bad things” (or a bad people–​bad things association), can shift one’s assessment of something one just did from bad to good, thus “balancing” one’s identity concept with a positive self-​assessment. This sort of effect is found in implicit attitudes (Greenwald et al., 2002). Mandelbaum (2015b) argues that this sort of effect is evidence that implicit attitudes cannot be associatively structured, since it appears that these are content-​driven transitions. But Anthony Greenwald and colleagues (2002) offer a model purporting to explain precisely these balance effects in implicit cognition using associative principles. More evidence is needed to sort through these interpretations, particularly given the reliance of each interpretation on behavioral measures, which are only proxies for changes in the attitudes themselves. That implicit attitudes appear to change in both content-​driven and associative ways is suggestive of my claim that these states are sui generis. All I hope to have shown so far, though, is that these states are not mere associations, in the strong sense that they are implemented exclusively by associative structures.18 Implicit attitudes are sensitive to the meaning of words and images. Does this mean that they are sensitive to the meaning of words and images in the way that beliefs paradigmatically are?

3. Belief In all of the cases I’ve discussed, it’s clear that agents have many beliefs about what they’re doing that are relevant to explaining their actions. Benes believes that HIV is carried in blood; the skywalker believes that she really is suspended over the Grand Canyon; athletes believe that they are trying to score goals and hit winners; and 17   See Chapter 7 for more on cognitive therapies. Of course, acrophobia is complex, involving not only implicit attitudes, but also explicit reasoning. One possibility is that the counterconditioning involved in exposure therapy shifts the agent’s implicit attitude, while the cognitive elements of therapy affect the agent’s beliefs. This leaves open the possibility that the agent’s implicit attitude is functioning in a merely associative way, that is, in response to counterconditioning alone and not in response to the meaning of one’s desired thoughts about heights. More research is needed in order to learn how these kinds of interventions actually work, as I mentioned in footnote 16 as well. See also Chapter 6. 18   I give more detail in §3 about hypothesized conditions under which changes in attitudes are in fact content-​driven changes.

Implicit Attit ud e s and the A rchitec t ure o f the   Mind

73

so on. On closer inspection, though, in many of these cases, agents seem to lack crucial beliefs about what they’re doing, or even seem to have mutually contradictory beliefs. Ask the museumgoer what the optimal distance from which to view an 8′ × 18′ painting is, and your question will likely be met with a puzzled stare.19 And Benes’s and the skywalker’s behaviors seem to conflict with other of their beliefs. These agents seem to believe one thing—​that my own blood can’t infect me with a disease I already have, or that I am safe on the glass platform—​but their behavior suggests otherwise. These cases raise questions about belief-​attribution—​that is, about determining what agents really believe—​and questions about belief-​ attribution depend in turn on questions about what beliefs are. So one way to determine whether implicit attitudes are beliefs is to consider whether the kinds of action in which they are implicated are explainable in terms of the agents’ beliefs. On the one hand, beliefs are something like what one takes to be true of the world.20 On the other, beliefs are also thought to guide action, together with one’s desires and ends. Belief-​attribution in the case of spontaneous and impulsive action becomes tricky on the basis of these two roles that states of belief are traditionally thought to play in the governance of thought and action. Many people can relate to the feeling of having beliefs but failing to live by them, particularly when they act spontaneously or impulsively. One potential explanation for this is that beliefs are truth-​taking but not necessarily action-​guiding. This explanation would be consist­ ent with a truth-​taking view (a), given the following interpretive options in cases of apparent belief–​behavior discord: (a) A truth-​taking view, which attributes beliefs on the basis of agents’ reflective judgments and avowals (Gendler, 2008a,b; Zimmerman, 2007; Brownstein and Madva, 2012b)21 (b) An action-​guiding view, which attributes beliefs on the basis of agents’ spontaneous actions and emotions (Hunter, 2011) (c) A context-​relative view, which takes both judgment and action to be relevant to belief-​attribution, and attributes to agents beliefs that vary across contexts (Rowbottom, 2007) (d) A contradictory-​belief view, which takes both judgment and action to be independently sufficient for belief-​attribution, and attributes to agents contradictory

  My point is not that beliefs must be articulable, but that an agent lacking an articulable answer to a question like this offers prima facie reason to suspect that the agent lacks the relevant belief. 20   See Gilbert (1991) for a psychological discussion of belief. See Schwitzgebel (2006/​2010) for a review of contemporary philosophical approaches to belief. The following presentation and some of the analysis of interpretive options for belief-​attribution are adapted from Brownstein and Madva (2012b). 21   By judgment, I mean what the agent takes to be true. While judgments are typically tied to avowals, I do not define judgment (or belief) in terms of avowals. See footnote 19. 19

Mind

74

beliefs (Egan, 2008; Gertler, 2011; Huddleston, 2012; Huebner, 2009; Muller and Bashour, 2011) (e) An indeterminacy view, which takes neither judgment nor action to be independ­ ently sufficient, and attributes to agents no determinate belief at all, but rather some “in-​between” state.22 Each of these views fits more naturally with some cases than others, but (a), the truth-​ taking view, which attributes belief on the basis of agents’ reflective judgments and avowals, outperforms the alternatives in paradigmatic cases. First consider (b)–​(e) in the context of the skywalker case. Proponents of (b), the action-​guiding view, which attributes belief on the basis of agents’ spontaneous actions and emotions, would have to argue that the skywalker merely professed, wished, or imagined the platform to be safe. But in this case, if the skywalker simply professed, wished, or imagined the platform to be safe, and thus failed to believe that the platform was safe, she would have to be clinically ill to decide to walk on it. Harboring any genuine doubt about the platform’s safety would keep most people from going anywhere near it. Perhaps some agents venture onto the Skywalk in order to look tough or to impress a date. In this case, perhaps the agent does indeed believe that the platform is only probably safe and yet walks onto it anyway, due to the combination of some other set of beliefs and desires. But this explanation can’t be generalized.23 Are the skywalker’s beliefs just (c) unstable across contexts? While it is surely the case that agents’ beliefs sometimes flip-​flop over time, the skywalker seems to treat the platform as both safe and unsafe in the same context. Perhaps, then, she (d) both believes and disbelieves that the Skywalk is safe. But in attributing contradictory beliefs to her in this case, one seems to run up against Moore’s paradox, in the sense that one cannot occurrently endorse and deny a proposition.24 Is the skywalker then   This sketch of the possible responses is drawn from Eric Schwitzgebel (2010), who points out that a similar array of interpretive options arises in the literature on self-​deception (see Deweese-​Boyd, 2006/​2008). Also see Gendler (2008a,b) for some discussion of historical predecessors of these contemporary views. 23   See Gendler (2008a, 654–​656). Another possibility, consistent with the action-​guiding view, is that the skywalker believes both that the platform is safe and that the platform is scary to experience. But this seems to posit unnecessary extra beliefs in the skywalker’s mental economy. The skywalker’s fear and trembling do not seem to be a reaction to a belief that being on the platform is scary. Rather, they seem to be a reaction to being on the platform. In other words, it seems likely that the skywalker does indeed believe that the platform is scary to experience, but this belief seems to be a result of the skywalker’s fear-​inducing experience, not a cause of it. Thanks to Lacey Davidson for suggesting this possibility. 24   I  take slight liberty with Moore’s paradox, which more accurately identifies a problem with asserting P and asserting disbelief in P. I take it that at least one reason this is problematic is that these assertions suggest that the agent occurrently believes and disbelieves the same thing. And this causes problems for belief-​attribution; it seems impossible to know what the agent believes or it seems that the agent doesn’t have a relevant belief. One might avoid Moore’s paradox by positing unconscious 22

Implicit Attit ud e s and the A rchitec t ure o f the   Mind

75

(e) in an irreducibly vague state of “in-​between belief ” (Schwitzgebel, 2010)? While problems associated with vagueness are ubiquitous and apply as much to ascriptions of belief and desire as they do to ascriptions of tallness and baldness, any positing of “in-​between” states seems to defer those problems rather than solve them.25 Why not draw the distinctions as precisely as we can and just acknowledge that there are outliers? Another problem facing the contradictory-​belief (d) and indeterminacy (e) views is imagining how one could reasonably distinguish between them, a task comparable to distinguishing the view that a person is both tall and not tall from the view that the person is neither tall nor not tall. What could, in this context, be evidence for one over another? The truth-​taking view (a) countenances the fact that the safety of the Skywalk is both what the agent judges to be true all things considered and what guides the agent’s intentional decision to walk across it. At the same time, her emotional responses and behavioral inclinations “go rogue.” The difference between her explicit judgment and intentional decision, on the one hand, and her affective-​behavioral inclinations, on the other, can be seen in the way that she would or would not react to information. No amount of data about the Skywalk’s weight-​bearing load capacities or the number of visitors who haven’t fall through the platform is likely to still one’s knocking knees and racing heart. Yet the slightest credible report indicating that the platform isn’t safe would cause the skywalker to revise her beliefs and get the hell off the platform immediately. Affective-​behavioral states like the skywalker’s are, in this sense, irredeemably yoked to how things perceptually seem to the agent, independ­ ently of whether she has ample reason to judge that the seeming is misleading.26 Such “seemings” should not be confused with beliefs, as Yuri Cath points out: We should not confuse mere seemings with beliefs. Even if one knows that the two lines in a Müller-​Lyer figure are of the same length, it will still seem to one that they differ in length. And as Bealer (1993) has pointed out, the same point applies not only to perceptual but also to intellectual seemings, [sic] it can still seem to one that the naïve axiom of set theory is true even

contradictory beliefs. See below for unconscious belief approaches. But see also Huddleston (2012) and Muller and Bashour (2011).   For more on the indeterminacy view (e), see §4. See also Zimmerman (2007, 73–​75).   Chirstopher  Peacocke (2004, 254–​257) similarly endorses what he calls the “belief-​independence” of emotional responses, citing Gareth Evans’s (1982, 123–​124) discussion of the belief-​independence of perception (evident in perceptual illusions like the Müller-​Lyer illusion). While Peacocke (2004) seems to defend (a), the truth-​taking view of belief, he is sometimes cited as a defender of (b), an action-​guiding view, because of his (1999, 242–​243) discussion of a case akin to aversive racism. It is natural to interpret Peacocke’s considered position as privileging the role of judgment in belief attribution, while acknowledging that in some cases so many of an agent’s other decisions and actions may fail to cohere with her reflective judgments that it would be wrong to attribute the relevant belief to her. 25 26

Mind

76

though one does not believe that it is true, because one knows that it leads to a contradiction. (2011, 124) Further reasons to support the truth-​taking view of belief stem from common reactions to dispositionally muddled agents.27 Although we might judge the skywalker to be phobic or lacking in (some ideal form of) self-​control, we would not impugn her with ignorance or irrationality. The skywalker is met with a different kind of reaction than one who both believes and disbelieves P. The same considerations apply to other relevant cases. Proponents of the action-​ guiding view (b) with respect to cases of implicit bias would have to argue that an agent’s egalitarian values aren’t really reflective of her beliefs. Perhaps in some cases this is true. Perhaps some agents just say that they believe, for instance, that men and women are equally qualified for a lab-​manager position, but don’t really believe it. But in many cases this is implausible. Activists and academics who have spent their entire careers fighting for gender and racial equity have implicit biases. These agents clearly genuinely believe in egalitarianism (broadly understood). As in the case of the skywalker, these genuine beliefs also guide agents’ intentional actions. One might, for instance, attend diversity trainings or read feminist philosophy. Similarly, the concerns I  raised earlier about the context-​relative (c), contradictory-​belief (d), and indeterminacy (e) views obtain here too, regardless of whether the target behavior is the skywalker’s trembling or the biased agent’s prejudiced evaluations of CVs. This leaves the truth-​taking view (a) again. Here, too, the way in which the agent in question reacts to information is crucial. Paradigmatic implicit biases are remarkably unaffected by evidence that contradicts them (see discussion below of Tal Moran and Yoav Bar-​Anan [2013] and Xiaoqing Hu et al. [2017]). Just as in the skywalker’s case, implicit biases are yoked to how things seem to an agent, regardless of what the agent judges to be true. But this is too quick, one might argue, given the evidence that beliefs can be unconscious, automatic, and unresponsive to an agent’s reflective attitudes and deliberations (Fodor, 1983; Gilbert, 1991; Egan, 2008, 2011; Huebner, 2009; Mandelbaum 2011). This evidence suggests a picture of “fragmented” or “compartmentalized” belief that supports the contradictory-​belief view (d) in the kinds of cases under discussion. Andy Egan offers a helpful sense of what a mind full of fragmented beliefs looks like. “Imagine two machines,” he suggests. Both do some representing, and both do some acting on the basis of their representations. One is a very fast, very powerful machine. It keeps all of its stored information available all of the time, by just having one big, master representation of the world, which it consults in planning all of its

  See Zimmerman (2007).

27

Implicit Attit ud e s and the A rchitec t ure o f the   Mind

77

behavior. It also updates the single representation all at once, to maintain closure and consistency: as soon as it starts representing P, it stops representing anything incompatible with P, and starts representing all of the consequences of P. It’s just got one, always-​active, instantly-​updated representation of the world. The other machine is a smaller, slower, less impressive machine. It can’t hold a lot of information in its working memory. So it divides up its store of information about the world into lots of little representations, and calls up different ones at different times to guide particular bits of its behavior. Not all of its information is available to it all the time, or for every purpose, and so it sometimes fails to act on things that, in some sense or other, it “knows” or “believes.” Since its information about the world is divided into many different representations, updates to one representation don’t always percolate all the way through the system. Sometimes this machine “learns” that P, but fails to erase all of its old representations of things that are incompatible with P. Sometimes it represents that P (in one representational item), and that if P then Q (in another representational item), but fails to represent that Q, since the two representational items don’t communicate with one another in the right sort of update-​inducing way. (2008, 48–​49) A fragmented mind is like the second machine, and “we are, of course, machines of the second kind,” Egan writes. If this is correct, then perhaps implicit attitudes may be just one kind of belief, which guide particular bits of behavior but fail to respond to the rest of what the agent knows and believes. Our minds are like the second machine, but this doesn’t necessarily support a contradictory-​belief (d) interpretation of the present cases (i.e., that paradigmatic implicit attitudes are beliefs). As I’ve presented them, implicit attitudes are belief-​ like. They encode risk, reward, and value. They update in the face of an agent’s changing experiences and have the potential to provide normative guidance of action (see §6). And they reflect some connection to an agent’s practical concerns (i.e., her goals and cares). However, beliefs as such have additional properties.28 Most central among these is the way in which beliefs communicate and integrate inferentially with one another and with other mental states.

  R ailton makes a similar point in arguing that soldiers who are skilled in fearing the right things—​in “picking up” signs of danger—​express belief-​like states that are not, nevertheless, just as such beliefs: “Well-​attuned fear is not a mere belief about the evaluative landscape, and yet we can speak of this fear, like belief, as ‘reasonable,’ ‘accurate,’ or ‘justified.’ It thus can form part of the soldier’s ‘practical intelligence’ or ‘intuitive understanding,’ permitting apt translation from perception to action, even when conscious deliberation is impossible and no rule can be found” (2014, 841). 28

78

Mind

One conception of this property is that beliefs are “inferentially promiscuous” (Stich, 1978). This is the idea that any belief can serve as a premise for a huge array of other possible beliefs. For example, my belief that it’s sunny outside today (S) can lead me inferentially to believe just about anything else (X), so long as I infer that if S then X.29 The action-​guiding representations involved in the cases I’ve described don’t appear to display this property. Considering the skywalker’s rogue affective-​behavioral reactions as premises in an inference works only in a very restricted sense, namely, as premises of the inference that she should get off the platform. These states are “inferentially impoverished.” This is akin to what Stephen Stich (1978, 515) says about subdoxastic states: it is not that inferences obtain only between beliefs; rather, it is that the inferential capacities of subdoxastic states are severely limited. Stich writes that there is a “comparatively limited range of potential inferential patterns via which [subdoxastic states] can give rise to beliefs, and a comparatively limited range of potential inferential patterns via which beliefs can give rise to them” (1978, 507). (Of course, Stich is not describing implicit attitudes. He is describing subdoxastic states generally. My claim is that implicit attitudes are paradigmatically subdoxastic in this way. While I accept that human minds are fragmented in the way Egan describes, I am arguing that those fragments that deserve to be considered beliefs have properties, such as inferential promiscuity, which paradigmatic implicit attitudes lack.) In discussing the difference between subdoxastic states and beliefs proper, Neil Levy (2014) similarly draws upon the concept of inferential impoverishment. He argues that states that count as beliefs must demonstrate the right systematic patterns of inference in response to the semantic content of other mental states. For example, a person’s implicit associations of men with leadership qualities might shift upon hearing a persuasive argument about the history of sexism, and this would appear to show that the implicit association is shifting because the agent has inferred, in a rationally respectable way, the conclusion. But implicit attitudes demonstrate this kind of inference pattern in only a “patchy” way, according to Levy. The shifts in attitude do not necessary last long or persist outside the context in which the persuasion manipulation was applied. This suggests that they aren’t beliefs. Earlier I discussed some ways in which implicit attitudes are responsive to the meaning of words and images (e.g., in exhibiting halo and compensation effects; see §2). But sometimes implicit attitudes are demonstrably unresponsive to prompts in “intelligent” ways. Moran and Bar-​Anan (2013), for example, presented participants with a neutral stimulus (drawings of alien creatures in various colors) that either 29   By inferences, I mean transitions between mental states in which the agent in some way takes the content of one state (e.g., a premise) to support the content of another (e.g., a conclusion). I take this to be roughly consistent with Crispin Wright’s view that inference is “the formation of acceptances for reasons consisting of other acceptances” (2014, 36). For discussion of a comparatively less demanding conception of inference than the one I use here, see Buckner (2017).

Implicit Attit ud e s and the A rchitec t ure o f the   Mind

79

started or stopped a pleasant or unpleasant sound.30 When asked directly, participants unsurprisingly reported that they preferred the drawings that started pleasant sounds and stopped unpleasant sounds to the drawings that started unpleasant sounds and stopped pleasant sounds. But when participants’ attitudes toward the drawings were assessed using an IAT, their implicit preferences merely reflected co-​ occurrence. That is, their implicit attitudes simply reflected whether the drawings co-​occurred with the pleasant or the unpleasant sound. Their implicit attitudes did not seem to process whether the drawing started or stopped the sound. Even more striking are results from Hu and colleagues (2017), who showed that implicit attitudes appear to fail to process the difference between the words “causes” and “prevents.” Participants were shown pairings of pharmaceutical products and information about positive or negative health outcomes. They were also explicitly told that some of the products cause the outcome and some of the products prevent the outcome. Again, when asked directly, participants unsurprisingly favored the products that they were told cause positive health outcomes and those that prevent negative health outcomes. But their implicit evaluations didn’t show this pattern. Instead, they simply reflected whether the products were paired with positive or negative outcomes, regardless of whether they were told that the product caused or prevented the outcome. Results like these seem to support Levy’s contention that implicit attitudes integrate into respectable patterns of inference only in a “patchy” way. Can anything be said about the conditions under which integration occurs in the right ways, compared with when it doesn’t? Alex Madva (2016b) has proposed more specific conditions—​which he calls “form-​sensitivity”—​according to which states that do and do not respect systematic patterns of inference can be identified. Madva’s view is also developed as an account of the structure of implicit attitudes. Form-​ sensitivity has two necessary conditions. First, a mental state is form-​sensitive only if it responds to other states with different form differently. For example, a form-​ sensitive state will respond to P and not-​P differently, but a state that fails to be form-​sensitive might treat P and not-​P similarly. In this example, sensitivity to negation stands in for sensitivity to the logical form of a state with semantic content. A wealth of evidence suggests that spontaneous reactions are driven by form-​ insensitive states in this way (e.g., Wegner 1984; Deutsch et al., 2006; Hasson and Glucksberg, 2006). For example, similar implicit reactions can be elicited by priming people with the words “good” and “not good.” Madva’s second condition is that a mental state is form-​sensitive only if it responds to other states with similar form similarly. According to this condition, a form-​sensitive state will respond to “I will Q, if I see P” in the same way as it will respond to “If I see P, I will Q.” These two   I note the relatively small number of participants in Moran and Bar-​Anan’s (2013) study. I take the conceptual replication of this study in Hu et al. (2017), discussed in the next paragraph, as some reason for placing confidence in these findings. 30

Mind

80

conditional statements have the same logical form; they mean the same thing. But there are cases in which it appears that implicit attitudes treat statements with minor differences in form like this differently. This is particularly the case in the literature on “implementation intentions,” or “if–​then plans.”31 These sorts of plans appear to respond to semantically identical but syntactically variable formulations differently. For example, in a shooter bias scenario, rehearsing the plan “I will always shoot a person I  see with a gun” appears to have different effects on one’s behavior than does rehearsing the plan “If I see a person with a gun, then I will shoot” (Mendoza et al., 2010). These points touch on the ongoing “associative” versus “propositional” debate in research on implicit social cognition. Findings such as those reported by Moran and Bar-​Anan (2013) and Hu et al. (2017) have been taken to support the associative view, which is most prominently spelled out in the “Associative-​Propositional Evaluation” model (APE; Gawronski and Bodenhausen, 2006). Meanwhile, research I discussed in the preceding section, suggesting that implicit attitudes process the meaning of propositions, has been taken to support the propositional view (e.g., Mitchell et al., 2009; De Houwer, 2014). One reason this debate is ongoing is that it is unclear how to interpret key findings. For example, Kurt Peters and Gawronski (2011) find that the invalidation of evaluative information doesn’t produce dissociation between implicit and explicit evaluations when the invalidating information is presented during encoding. This suggests that implicit attitudes are processing negation in the way that Madva (2016b) suggests they don’t. But when the invalidating information is presented after a delay, implicit and explicit attitudes do dissociate. This complicates both the associative and propositional pictures. And it does so in a way that suggests that neither picture has things quite right.32 In my view, this supports Levy’s contention that while implicit attitudes integrate into patterns of inference in some ways, they don’t do so in ordinary and fully belief-​like ways. Alternatively, one might bypass the claim about the difference between inferentially promiscuous and inferentially impoverished states by adopting a radically expansive view of belief.33 The theory of “Spinozan Belief Fixation” (SBF), for example, argues that minds like ours automatically believe everything to which they are exposed (Huebner, 2009; Mandelbaum 2011, 2013, 2014, 2015b). SBF rejects the claim that agents are capable of evaluating the truth of an idea before believing or disbelieving it. Rather, as soon as an idea is encountered, it is believed. Mandelbaum (2014) illustrates SBF vividly: it proposes that one cannot entertain or consider or imagine or even encounter the proposition that “dogs are made out of paper” without immediately and unavoidably believing that dogs are made out of paper. Inter alia, SBF provides a doxastic interpretation of implicit biases, for as soon as one   See Chapter 7 for more in-​depth discussion of implementation intentions.   See Gawronski, Brannon, and Bodenhausen (2017) for discussion. 33   W hat follows in this paragraph is adapted from Brownstein (2015). 31 32

Implicit Attit ud e s and the A rchitec t ure o f the   Mind

81

encounters, for example, the stereotype that “women are bad at math,” one putatively comes to believe that women are bad at math. The automaticity of believing according to SBF explains why people are likely to have many contradictory beliefs. In order to reject P, one must already believe P (Mandelbaum, 2014). Proponents explain the unintuitive nature of SBF by claiming that most people think they have only the beliefs that they consciously know they have. So, for example, a scientifically-informed person  presented with the claim that dinosaurs and humans walked the earth at the same time will both believe that dinosaurs and humans walked the earth at the same time and that dinosaurs and humans did not walk the earth at the same time, but they will only think they have the latter belief because it is consistent with what they consciously judge to be true. But this doesn’t go far enough in explaining the unintuitive nature of SBF. At the end of the day, SBF requires abandoning the entire normative profile of belief. It scraps the truth-​taking role of belief altogether. This in turn means that there is no justified epistemic difference between believing P and considering, testing, or rejecting P. For when we reject P, for instance, we come to believe not-​P, and according to SBF we will have done so just upon encountering or imagining not-​P. SBF asks a lot in terms of shifting the ordinary ways in which we think about belief and rationality. More familiar conceptions of belief don’t shoulder nearly so heavy a burden. If one accepts some existing account of belief that preserves belief ’s two principal roles—​of action-​guiding and truth-​taking—​then it appears that the truth-​taking view (a) of belief-​attribution in the case of spontaneous and impulsive action is still preferable to the other options. If the truth-​taking view is best, then these actions are not most persuasively explicable in terms of agents’ beliefs, since the agents’ affective and behavioral reactions in these cases don’t reflect what they take to be true. The upshot of this is that implicit attitudes are not beliefs.

4. Dispositions In §3, I cited Eric Schwitzgebel (2010) as a defender of the indeterminacy view. This view takes neither judgment nor action to be independently sufficient for belief-​attribution. Instead, in cases of conflict between apparent belief and behavior, this view attributes to agents no determinate belief at all, but rather an “in-​between” state. Schwitzgebel (2010) explicitly calls this state “in-​between belief.” This follows from Schwitzgebel’s (2002, 2010) broader account of attitudes, in the philosophical sense, as dispositions. All propositional attitudes, on this view—​beliefs, intentions, and so on—​are broad-​based multitrack dispositions. To believe that plums are good to eat, for example, is to be disposed to have particular thoughts and feelings about eating plums and to behave in particular ways in particular situations. These thoughts, feelings, and behaviors make up what Schwitzgebel calls a “dispositional profile.” You are said to have an attitude, on this view, when your dispositional

82

Mind

profile matches what Schwitzgebel (2013) calls the relevant folk-​psychological ster­ eotype. That is, you are said to have the attitude of believing that plums are good to eat if you feel, think, and do the things that ordinary people regard as broadly characteristic of this belief. This broad dispositional approach to attitudes—​particularly to the attitude of belief—​is hotly contested (see, e.g., Ramsey, 1990; Carruthers, 2013). One core challenge for it is to explain away what seems to be an important disanalogy between trait-​based explanations of action and mental state–​based explanations of action. As Peter Carruthers (2013) points out, traits are explanatory as generalizations. To say that Fiona returned the money because she is honest is to appeal to something Fiona would typically do (which perhaps matches a folk-​psychological stereotype for honesty). But mental states are explanatory as token causes (of behavior or other mental states). To say that Fiona returned the money because she believes that “honesty is the best policy” is to say that this token belief caused her action. Schwitzgebel’s broad dispositional approach seems to elide this disanalogy (but for replies see Schwitzgebel, 2002, 2013). In §3, I noted several challenges this approach faces specifically in making sense of cases of conflict between apparent belief and behavior. One challenge is that the broad dispositional approach seems to defer the problem of belief-​attribution rather than solve it. Another is that it underestimates the intuitive weight of avowals, for example, in the case of a social justice activist who explicitly decries racism but nevertheless holds implicit racial biases. It seems appropriate to attribute the belief that racism is wrong to her (which is not the same as saying that she is blameless; see Chapters 4 and 5). In addition, because this approach takes folk-​psychological stereotypes as foundational for attitude-​ascription, it must be silent on cases in which folk-​psychological stereotypes are lacking. This is precisely the case with implicit attitudes. Our culture lacks a stereotypical pattern of thought, feeling, and action against which an agent’s dispositional profile could be matched. Earlier I noted that implicit attitudes are a version of what have historically been called animal spirits, appetite, passion, association, habit, and spontaneity, but there is no obvious folk-​ psychological stereotype for these either. The problem with the dispositional approach, in this context, is that it ultimately tells us that we cannot attribute an implicit attitude to an agent, not at least until ordinary people recognize an implicit attitude to have signature features. But in some cases, I think, science and philosophy can beat folk psychology in attitude-​ ascription. Consider by analogy the question of ascribing beliefs to nonhuman animals. As Carruthers (2013) puts it, there is good (scientific) reason to think that apes share some basic concepts with human beings, concepts like grape and ground. And so there is good reason to think that apes have the capacity to believe that “there is a grape on the ground.” But my sense is that there is no discernible folk-​ psychological stereotype for belief-​attribution in apes. Here it seems obvious that folk psychology is outperformed by science and philosophy for attitude-​ascription.

Implicit Attit ud e s and the A rchitec t ure o f the   Mind

83

Schwitzgebel’s is not the only dispositional approach to theorizing the nature of implicit attitudes. According to Edouard Machery (2016), attitudes in the psychological sense are dispositions. He retains a mental state account of propositional attitudes, according to which states like beliefs can occur and are realized in brain states. But attitudes in the psychological sense—​likings or dislikings—​are multitrack dispositions, akin to personality traits, on Machery’s view. They do not occur and are not realized in the brain (though they depend in part on brain states). Machery argues that there are various bases that together comprise an attitude. These include feelings, associations, behavior, and propositional attitudes like beliefs. Indirect measures like the IAT, on this picture, capture one of the many psychological bases of the agent’s overall attitude. Explicit questionnaire measures capture another psychological basis of the agent’s attitude, behavioral measures yet another basis, and so on. An important upshot of this view is that there are no such things as implicit attitudes. The reason for this is that the view asserts that attitudes are traits, and traits (like being courageous or honest) do not divide into implicit and explicit kinds. A concept like “implicit courageousness” is meaningless, Machery argues. Rather, associations between concepts—​which may be implicit in the sense of unconscious or difficult to control—​are simply one of the bases of an attitude, as are low-​level affective reactions and the like. One challenge for Machery’s version of the trait view is the ubiquity of dissociations between agents’ propositional attitudes, implicit associations, affective reactions to stimuli, and behavior. If these are dissociated, then the agent lacks the attitude in question. For example, on Machery’s view, a person who believes that men and women are equally competent for a job, but associates men with competence on an IAT, fails to display a multitrack disposition and thus fails to have a relevant attitude. The putative bases of their attitude are dissociated. This would be akin to a person who speaks highly of honesty but implicitly associates dishonesty with herself (and perhaps also fails to act honestly). Such a person would fail to display the multitrack trait of honesty (or dishonesty). Because dissociations between thoughts, feelings, and behavior are ubiquitous (cf. Chapter 1), it will be rare to find agents who have attitudes. This is an unwelcome result if the concept of attitude is to play a role in our understanding of human thought and action. Moreover, one of the central premises of Machery’s trait view rests on the claim that various indirect measures dissociate. For example, there are only weak relations between the IAT and variations of evaluative priming (Sherman et al., 2003). Machery argues that if implicit attitudes were a distinct kind of mental state, then we should expect different measurement tools for assessing them to be more strongly correlated with each other. The trait view doesn’t predict close relations between these various measures, on the other hand, because rather than tapping into one kind of mental state—​an implicit attitude—​they are said to tap into various psychological bases of an agent’s attitude. But there are plausible

Mind

84

alternative explanations for the correlational relations between indirect measures. Bar-​Anan and Brian  Nosek (2014) find that correlations between seven of the most commonly used indirect measures are highly content-​specific.34 Correlations are weak for self-​esteem, for example, moderate for race, and strong for politics. This mirrors the content-​specific relations between direct and indirect attitude measures. That is, correlations are strongest between direct and indirect political attitude measures and are weakest between direct and indirect self-​esteem attitude measures. Bar-​Anan and Nosek (2014, 683) suggest that this may be due to the complexity of the attitude target. The concept self is multifaceted, while a concept like republican or democrat is comparatively univocal. If this is right, then the variability between indirect attitude measures is no threat to the standard mental state view of implicit attitudes. Such variability is content-​ rather than measure-​specific, and for predictable reasons (i.e., the complexity of the attitude target). In a related vein, Machery appeals to other apparent weaknesses in measures of implicit attitudes in support of his trait view. For example, the test-​retest stability of the IAT is relatively low (r  =  .5–​.6; Gschwendner et  al., 2008). This means that the same person taking the IAT at two different times is relatively likely to have different results. This is consistent with the high context-​sensitivity of implicit attitudes (see §1.2 in Chapter 2 and the discussion in Chapter 7). Machery argues that this context-​sensitivity is predicted by the trait picture but not by the mental state picture. But this is debatable. Some models of implicit attitudes, which take them to be mental states, make specific predictions about the contexts in which token attitudes will and will not be activated (see, e.g., Tobias Gschwendner et al. [2008]—​who demonstrate conditions under which the test-​retest validity of the IAT is significantly boosted—​and Cesario and Jonas’s [2014] “Resource Computation Framework,” both of which I discuss in the Appendix). The same goes for Machery’s claim that measures like the IAT are poor predictors of behavior and that this is predicted by the trait picture but not the mental state picture. A  full sweep of the literature on implicit attitude measurement does not suggest that the IAT is altogether a poor predictor of behavior. Just how to interpret the predictive power of the (certainly imperfect) IAT is a matter of current debate.35

  Bar-​Anan and Nosek use several criteria: “internal consistency, test-​retest reliability, sensitivity to known-​groups effects, relations with other indirect measures of the same topic, relations with direct measures of the same topic, relations with other criterion variables, psychometric qualities of single-​ category measurement, ability to detect meaningful variance among people with nonextreme attitudes, and robustness to the exclusion of misbehaving or well-​behaving participants” (2004, 682). See the Appendix for definitions and discussion. 35   See the Appendix. 34

Implicit Attit ud e s and the A rchitec t ure o f the   Mind

85

5. Alief If implicit attitudes are not reflexive processes, mere associations, beliefs, or dispositional traits, what are they? Perhaps they are what Gendler (2008a,b, 2011, 2012) calls “aliefs.” More primitive than belief, an alief is a relatively inflexible disposition to react automatically to an apparent stimulus with certain fixed affective responses and behavioral inclinations (Gendler 2008b, 557–​60). While aliefs are said to dispose agents to react to stimuli in particular ways, aliefs are not proposed to be dispositions in the sense of traits of character. Rather, they are proposed to be a genuine mental state, one that deserves to be included in the taxonomy of the human mind. In Gendler’s parlance, a firm believer that superstitions are bogus may yet be an abiding aliever who cowers before black cats and sidewalk cracks. An agent may be sincerely committed to anti-​racist beliefs, but simultaneously harbor racist aliefs. Indeed, Gendler proposes the concept of alief in order to make sense of a wide swath of spontaneous and impulsive actions. She goes so far as to argue that aliefs are primarily responsible for the “moment-​by-​moment management” of behavior (2008a, 663). Moreover, she proposes an account of the content of alief in terms of three tightly co-​activating Representational, Affective, and Behavioral components. This account of the RAB content of alief is clearly closely related to my description of implicit attitudes.36 I will elaborate on the similarities between my account of implicit attitudes and alief later. However, I will also argue that implicit attitudes are not aliefs.37 Gendler proposes the notion of alief in order to elucidate a set of cognitive and behavioral phenomena that appear to be poorly explained by either an agent’s beliefs (in concert with her desires) or her mere automatic reflexes. She writes: We often find ourselves in the following situation. Our beliefs and desires mandate pursuing behaviour B and abstaining from behaviour A, but we nonetheless find ourselves acting—​or feeling a propensity to act—​in A-​like ways. These tendencies towards A-​like behaviours are highly recalcitrant, persisting even in the face of our conscious reaffirmation that B-​without-​A

36   Note that Gendler uses the term “content” in an admittedly “idiosyncratic way,” referring to the suite of RAB components of states of alief and leaving open whether aliefs are propositional or conceptual, as well as insisting that their content in some sense includes “affective states and behavioral dispositions” (2008a, 635, n. 4). This is a different usage of the term “content” than I deployed in Chapter 2. 37   Although it would not be far off to say that what I  am calling implicit attitudes are aliefs but that my characterization of alief differs from Gendler’s. In previous work (Brownstein and Madva, 2012a,b), I have presented my view as a revised account of the structure of alief. Ultimately, I think this is a terminological distinction without much substance. “Alief ” is a neologism after all, and Gendler is notably provisional in defining it. What matters ultimately is the structure of the state.

86

Mind

is the course of action to which we are reflectively committed. It seems misleading to describe these A-​like behaviours as fully intentional: their pursuit runs contrary to what our reflective commitments mandate. But it also seems wrong to describe them as fully reflexive or automatic: they are the kinds of behaviours that it makes sense—​at least in principle—​to attribute to a belief–​desire pair, even though in this case (I argue) it would be mistaken to do so. (2012, 799) Aliefs are, Gendler argues, relations between an agent and a distinctive kind of intentional content, with representational, affective, and behavioral (or RAB) components. They involve “a cluster of dispositions to entertain simultaneously R-​ish thoughts, experience A, and engage in B” (2008a, 645). These components are associatively linked and automatically co-​activating. On the Skywalk, for instance, the mere perception of the steep drop “activates a set of affective response patterns (feelings of anxiety) and motor routines (muscle contractions associated with hesitation and retreat)” (2008a, 640). The RAB content of this alief is something like “Really high up, long long way down. Not a safe place to be! Get off!” (2008a, 635). Likewise, the sight of feces-​ shaped fudge “renders occurrent a belief-​discordant alief with the content: ‘dog-​feces, disgusting, refuse-​to-​eat’ ” (2008a, 641). Aliefs share an array of features. Gendler writes: To have an alief is, to a reasonable approximation, to have an innate or habitual propensity to respond to an apparent stimulus in a particular way. It is to be in a mental state that is . . . associative, automatic and arational. As a class, aliefs are states that we share with non-​human animals; they are developmentally and conceptually antecedent to other cognitive attitudes that the creature may go on to develop. Typically, they are also affect-​laden and action-​generating. (2008b, 557) It should be clear that my description of the components of implicit attitudes in Chapter 2 is indebted to Gendler’s formulation of alief. In particular, I have retained the ideas that the states in question—​whether they are aliefs or implicit attitudes—​ dispose agents to respond automatically to apparent stimuli with certain affective responses and behavioral inclinations and that these states can be relatively insensitive to what agents themselves take to be definitive evidence for or against a particular response. One of the promises of Gendler’s account of alief is that it represents a proposal for unifying philosophical belief-​desire theories of mind and action with contemporary dual-​systems cognitive psychology. Most dual-​systems theories suggest that fast, associative, and affective processes—​so-​called System 1—​are developmentally antecedent to slow, inferential, and/​or cognitive processes—​System 2. And most dual-​systems theories also suggest that human beings share at least some elements

Implicit Attit ud e s and the A rchitec t ure o f the   Mind

87

of System 1 processes with nonhuman animals.38 Crudely, the suggestion would be, then, that System 1 produces aliefs while System 2 produces beliefs. As Uriah Kriegel notes, this connection would then provide important explanatory unity in the sciences of the mind: Given the prevalence of dual-​process models in cognitive science, another model positing a duality of causally operative mechanisms in a single cognitive domain, a belief-​producing mechanism and an alief-​producing mechanism, integrates smoothly into a satisfyingly unified account of human cognition and action. Indeed, if we hypothesize that the alief-​producing mechanism is one and the same as Sloman’s associationist system and the belief-​producing mechanism one and the same as his rationalist (“rule-​ based”) system, the explanatory unification and integration of empirical evidence and firm conceptual underpinnings becomes extraordinarily powerful. (2012, 476) But as formulated, I do not think the concept of alief can fulfill the promise of integrating belief-​desire psychology with the dual-​systems framework. One reason for this is based on a concern about dual-​systems theorizing. It is hard to find a list of core features of System 1 states or processes that are not shared by some or many putative System 2 states or processes. As in Hume’s example of hearing a knock on the door causing me to believe that there is someone standing outside it, beliefs can be formed and rendered occurrent automatically, without attention, and so on.39 This may not be an insurmountable problem for dual-​systems theorists.40 Regardless, there is a broader interpretation of Kriegel’s point about integrating the concept of alief with dual-​systems theorizing. What is more broadly at stake, I think, is whether the concept of alief is apt in the full suite of the virtues and vices of spontaneity. Does alief—​as formulated—​provide a satisfying account of the psychology of both poles of spontaneity? Note how this is not an exogenous demand I  am putting to the concept of alief. Rather, it follows from Gendler’s formulation of the concept. If aliefs are causally implicated in much of moment-​ to-​moment behavior, then they must be operative in both Gendler-​style cases of 38   For reviews of dual-​systems theories, see Sloman (1996) and Evans and Frankish (2009). In the popular press, see also Kahneman (2011). 39   Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pushing me to clarify this and for reminding me of the example. See Mandelbaum (2013) for a discussion. 40   Jonathan Evans and Keith Stanovich (2013) respond to counterexamples like this by presenting the features of System 1/​2 as “correlates” that should not be taken as necessary or sufficient. On the value of setting out a list of features to characterize a mental kind, see Jerry Fodor’s (1983) discussion of the nine features that he claims characterize modularity. There, Fodor articulates a cluster of traits that define a type of mental system, rather than a type of mental state. A system, for Fodor, counts as modular if it shares these features “to some interesting extent.”

Mind

88

belief-​discordant alief and in ordinary forms of norm-​concordant and even skilled automaticity. Several commentators have pointed out how alief seems poised to explain cases of reasonable and apparently intelligent, yet spontaneous and unreflective behavior. Of “Gendler cases” (e.g., the Skywalk), Greg Currie and Anna Ichino write: Notice that Gendler cases are by and large characterised by their conservativeness; they are cases where behaviour is guided by habit, often in ways which subvert or constrain the subject’s openness to possibilities. There is a class of human behaviours at the opposite extreme: cases where, without the mediation of conscious reasoning or exercise of will, we generate creative solutions to practical or theoretical problems. Creative processes involve unexpected, unconventional and fruitful associations between representations and between representations and actions—​without the subjects generally having access to how that happens. We suggest that both creative and habitual processes are triggered by an initial representation—​ not always specifiable at the personal level and sometimes occurring beyond conscious will—​that leads, through a chain of barely conscious associations, to various other states, the last of which can be either another representative state or an action. While in Gendler cases the associations lead to familiar patterns of thought and behaviour, in creative processes they lead to unpredictable, novel outcomes. Paradigmatic instances of those outcomes—​jazz improvisations, free dance/​speech performances—​ are unlikely to derive from some kind of (creative) conceptual representation, since they exceed in speed and fineness of grain the resources of conceptual thought. (2012, 797–​798) While Currie and Ichino suggest that automaticity is implicated in creative action, Jennifer Nagel (2012) argues in a related vein that our “gut responses” can, in some cases, be “reality-​sensitive,” and perhaps sometimes be even more sensitive to reality than our conscious explicit judgments. Nagel cites the “Iowa Gambling Task” (Bechara et al., 1997, 2005) as an example.41 This is a task in which participants are presented with four decks of cards and $2,000 in pretend gambling money. The participants must choose facedown cards, one at a time, from any of the decks. Some cards offer rewards and some offer penalties. Two of the decks are “good” in the sense that choosing from them offers an overall pattern of reward, despite only small rewards offered by the cards at the top of the deck. Two of the decks are “bad”; picking from them gives the participant a net loss, despite large initial gains. The interesting finding, Nagel notes, is that it takes subjects on average about eighty   See Lewicki et al. (1987) for a related experiment.

41

Implicit Attit ud e s and the A rchitec t ure o f the   Mind

89

card turns before they can say why they prefer to pick from the good decks. But after about fifty turns, most participants can say that they prefer the good decks, even if they aren’t sure why. And, most strikingly, after about only twenty turns, while most participants do not report having any reason for distinguishing between the decks (i.e., they don’t feel differently about them and say that they don’t see any difference between them), most participants do have higher anticipatory skin conductance responses before picking from the bad decks. This suggests that most participants have some kind of implicit sensitivity to the difference between the decks before they have any explicit awareness that there is such a difference. Nagel takes this to mean that agents’ putative aliefs—​represented outwardly by a small change in affect (and measured by anticipatory skin conductance)—​may be, in some cases, more sensitive to reality than their explicit beliefs. Gendler concedes in reply to these commentators that alief-​like processes may be implicated in creative and reality-​sensitive behavior, and thus seems to allow room for “intelligent aliefs” (2012, 808). This is not a surprising concession, given Gendler’s earlier claim that “if alief drives behavior in belief-​discordant cases, it is likely that it drives behavior in belief-​concordant cases as well” (2008a, 663). Gendler understandably emphasizes vivid cases of belief-​discordance—​skywalkers and fudge-​avoiders and implicitly biased agents—​because these are the cases in which an agent’s aliefs are forced into the light of day. These cases are a device for the presentation of alief, in other words. But Gendler’s claim that alief is primarily responsible for the moment-​to-​moment management of behavior entails that these states ought to be attuned to changes in the environment and be implicated in (some forms of) intelligent behavior. While “conservative” aliefs—​like those implicated in the behaviors of skywalkers, fudge-​ avoiders, and the like—​are pervasive, they don’t dominate our moment-​to-​moment lives. Mostly agents more or less cope successfully with the world around them without constantly doing combat with gross conflicts between their automatic and reflective dispositions. We move closer to see small objects and step back from large ones in appropriate contexts; we extend our hands to shake when others offer us theirs (in some cultures); we frown sympathetically if someone tells us a sad story and smile encouragingly if the story is a happy one; and so on. Ordinary successful coping in cases like these requires rapid and efficient responses to changes in the environment—​exactly those features of alief that one would expect. If aliefs are responsible for the moment-​to-​moment management of behavior, then these states must be sufficiently flexible in the face of changing circumstances and attuned to subtle features of the environment to drive creative, reality-​sensitive, intelligent behavior. The deeper concern is not about Gendler’s emphasis on particular kinds of cases, that is, cases of norm-​and belief-​discordant automaticity. The deeper concern is that the RAB structure of alief cannot make sense of putative intelligent aliefs. It

Mind

90

cannot do so because it lacks a mechanism for dynamic learning and internal feedback, in short, what I called “alleviation” in Chapter 2. Another related concern about Gendler’s formulation of alief stems from what I will call the “lumpiness” question. Gendler argues that aliefs are a unified mental kind. The RAB components are operative, as she says, “all at once, in a single alief ” (2008b, 559). But why make the strong claim that alief represents a distinct kind of psychological state rather than a set of frequently co-​occurring appearances or beliefs, desires, and behaviors?42 Why say, for example, that the skywalker has a singular occurrent alief—​as Gendler does—​with content like “Really high up, long long way down. Not a safe place to be! Get off!” rather than something like a co-​occurring representation of being high up, a feeling of being in danger, and a response to tremble and perhaps flee? What is the value, as Nagel (2012) asks, of explaining action in terms of “alief-​shaped lumps?” Gendler’s answer is that aliefs are “lumpy” in a way that reflective states like beliefs are not. Belief–​desire–​action trios are composites that can be combined in any number of ways (in principle). One way to see this is to substitute a different belief into a common co-​occurrence of a belief, desire, and action (Gendler, 2012). For instance, around noon each day I may experience this belief–​desire–​ action trio: I believe that cheese is reasonably healthy for me; I desire to eat a healthy lunch; I make a cheese sandwich. Should I overhear on the radio, however, just as I am reaching in the fridge, that the kind of cheese I have is definitively linked to an elevated risk for cancer and will soon be banned by the FDA, and I have credence in the source of the information, it is likely that I’ll avoid the cheese and eat something else. If the acquisition of a new belief changes my behavior on the spot like this, then I  know that this particular composite of a belief, desire, and action is, as Gendler puts it, psychologically contingent. By contrast, no new belief, it seems, will immediately eliminate the skywalker’s fear and trembling. The skywalker’s representations (“high up!”), feelings (“not safe!”), and behavior (“get off!”) are too tightly bound, forming a fairly cohesive lump, as it were. This reply to the lumpiness question is partly successful. It offers a clear criterion for marking the alief–​belief distinction:  the constituent RAB relata of alief automatically co-​activate, while ordinary beliefs, feelings, and behavior do not (they are “psychologically continent” or, as Gendler also puts it, “fully combinatoric”). In a related sense, Gendler’s reply to the lumpiness question provides a test of sorts for determining when this criterion is met. Provide a person with some evidence that runs contrary to her putative alief and see what happens. If it interrupts the automatic co-​activation of the RAB relata, as in the case of the cheese sandwich, then this was not an alief-​guided action.

  See Nagel (2012), Currie and Ichino (2012), and Doggett (2012).

42

Implicit Attit ud e s and the A rchitec t ure o f the   Mind

91

But several open questions remain. The first is how and why the presentation of “evidence” affects the agent in such a way as to mark the alief–​belief divide. On a broad interpretation, evidence might just refer to any information relevant to the agent. But on this interpretation, an evidence-​insensitive state would seem inherently uncreative and unresponsive to changing environments. It would by definition be incapable of playing a role in the cases of virtuous spontaneity discussed by critics like Currie and Ichino (2012) and Nagel (2012). Moreover, it is clear that the presentation of evidence that contradicts agents’ beliefs sometimes utterly fails to dislodge their attitude. Something more specific has to be said about the conditions under which evidence does and does not affect the agent’s occurrent mental states and her related affective and behavioral reactions. Finally, Gendler’s reply to the lumpiness question relies on the idea that the RAB relata of alief automatically co-​activate. But what properties does the process of co-​activation have? Do all putative aliefs co-​activate in the same way?

6.  Implicit Attitudes Implicit attitudes are conceptual cousins of aliefs. But understanding implicit attitudes as states with FTBA components offers the better formulation for capturing the psychological structure of our spontaneous inclinations. This represents, inter alia, a step forward on the question of whether implicit attitudes are a distinctive mental kind. Here I summarize and highlight the key features of implicit attitudes that favor this view. The first is that the FTBA relata of implicit attitudes, as I  described them in Chapter 2, are apt in cases of both the virtues and vices of spontaneity. Alleviation, in particular, describes how implicit attitudes are capable of dynamic learning and revising in the face of internal and external feedback. I also described in Chapter 2 how the process of alleviation can fail, such that one’s spontaneous inclinations can run afoul of either one’s reflective beliefs or the normative demands of the environment. This feature of implicit attitudes situates them to provide an account of how our spontaneous inclinations can guide much of moment-​to-​moment behavior. Second, in contrast to the evidence-​sensitivity criterion for distinguishing alief from belief, in §3 I  discussed more specific criteria for distinguishing implicit attitudes from beliefs. These focused on the inferential promiscuity and form-​ sensitivity of beliefs. Drawing on Levy (2012, 2014) and Madva (2016b), I argued that implicit attitudes are inferentially impoverished and form-​insensitive. That is, there is a limited range of patterns through which implicit attitudes can give rise to other mental states and to behavior. Paradigmatically, these do not include doing so through inference. Madva’s account of form-​sensitivity provides additional detail for why this may be the case with implicit attitudes; they are insensitive to the logical form of the presentation of information, as it is structured by operators like

92

Mind

negation or the order of words in a proposition. Specifying why implicit attitudes appear to be evidence-​insensitive connects with explaining the role of these states in cases of both the virtues and vices of spontaneity. For it is not that implicit attitudes, once formed, are wholly resistant to evidence that contradicts them. Rather, they are insensitive to the forms of learning characteristic of states like belief. The way in which they respond to evidence is different, in other words. But they nevertheless display characteristic forms of value-​guided learning and improvement over time, which makes them capable of figuring in to skilled and even exemplary behavior. Finally, more has to be said than that the components of our immediate reaction to stimuli co-​activate. Understanding the processes of co-​activation between FTBA relata underscores why implicit attitudes are a unified state. I summarize the following central characteristics. First, while I have emphasized that particular associations are activated in varying contexts, when an FTBA is set off, a “spread” of automatic activation always occurs. When an agent learns or modifies her implicit attitudes, she replaces one token relation for another (e.g., one behavioral response for another). To the extent that a smoker can weaken the co-​activating association between nicotine cravings and smoking-​initiation behaviors, for example, she does so not by eliminating all behavioral responses to nicotine cravings, but by replacing one behavioral response with another. The tennis player who learns to hit a drop volley instead of a stab volley similarly replaces one motor response with another, effectively adding a new spontaneous inclination to her repertoire. This is the sense in which Gendler (2008a, 635, n.  4)  includes behavior as part of the “content” of alief. This point is not intended as a defense of behaviorism. The proposal is that a psychological motor routine is activated, which is functionally connected to the agent’s activated thoughts and feelings. The activation of this motor routine may not issue in a full-​ fledged action—​see Chapters 4 and 5—​although there is always some behavioral expression, such as changes in heart rate, eyeblink response, or muscle tone. This omnipresent spread of activation is not encapsulated within any particular mental system or type of mental state, but is rather cross-​modal. It is not the case that semantic associations only co-​activate other semantic associations. Thoughts of birthdays activate thoughts of cake, as well as feelings of hunger or joy (or sadness, as the case may be) and behavioral impulses to eat or sing or blow out candles. A spontaneous response to a stimulus does not just induce thoughts, or induce feelings, or induce behaviors. It induces all three. Moreover, activation of this sort may include inhibition (e.g., thoughts of safety may inhibit thoughts or feelings of fear; see Smith, 1996). Implicit attitudes are heterogeneous (Holroyd and Sweetman, 2016), but their variety differs in degree, not kind. As I  discussed briefly in Chapter  2, in the literature on implicit social cognition, it is common to distinguish between, on the one hand, “coldly” cognitive implicit beliefs, cognitions, or stereotypes and, on the other hand, “hot” affective implicit attitudes, evaluations, or feelings. Some

Implicit Attit ud e s and the A rchitec t ure o f the   Mind

93

researchers have advanced theoretical models of implicit social cognition based on this very distinction, arguing that there are two fundamental kinds of implicit mental state:  cold implicit stereotypes and hot implicit prejudices (Amodio and Devine, 2006; Amodio and Ratner, 2011). The picture I  offer here of implicit attitudes rejects this “two-​type” view (for discussion see Madva and Brownstein, 2016). Some implicit attitudes are comparatively more affective than others, but all involve some degree of emotional response. Affect continues to exert causal effects even at very low intensities, although low-​intensity effects will typically escape an individual’s focal attention (and may require more fine-​grained measures than, for example, the IAT). The affective intensity of implicit attitudes is a function of several (a) content-​ specific, (b)  person-​specific, and (c)  context-​specific variables. Regarding (a), implicit attitudes with certain contents (e.g., automatic evaluative responses to perceptions of spiders or vomit) will tend to be more affectively intense than others (e.g., perceptions of lamps or doorknobs). Regarding (b), some individuals will have stronger affective dispositions toward certain stimuli than others. For example, people who were obese as children or had beloved, obese mothers exhibit less negative automatic evaluations of obesity (Rudman et al., 2007); individuals with a strong dispositional “need to evaluate” exhibit more intense automatic evaluations in general ( Jarvis and Petty, 1996; Hermans et al., 2001); and low-​prejudice people tend to be less susceptible than high-​prejudice people to negative affective conditioning in general (Livingston and Drwecki, 2007). Regarding (c), certain contexts, such as being in a dark room, amplify the strength of automatic evaluations of threatening stimuli (Schaller et  al., 2003; see Cesario and Jonas [2014], discussed in Chapter 2 and in the Appendix, for a theoretically elaborated model of which contexts will activate which kinds of affective responses). Future research should focus on identifying the mediators, moderators, and downstream effects of such differences in degree. It is also important to differentiate among distinctive types of affective-​ motivational implicit responses. For example, anxiety and anger are both “negative” affective responses, but research suggests that while anxiety often activates an implicit avoidance orientation, anger typically activates an implicit approach orientation (Carver and Harmon-​Jones, 2009). Affective responses can therefore differ along at least two dimensions—​positive versus negative, and approach versus avoid—​although future research should attempt to identify further types of approach motivation. Anger, joy, hunger, and sexual arousal may each activate distinctive sorts of implicit approach orientations. This means that, instead of modeling affect intensity as a bipolar continuum between positive and negative valence, we must differentiate among distinctive types of affective-​motivational responses. These co-​activation relations of FTBA components demonstrate two key features of implicit attitudes. One, as I’ve argued, is that implicit attitudes are sui generis states. Token implicit attitudes can be changed or eliminated when these patterns

Mind

94

of co-​activation are broken, but as I  argued earlier, a distinctive type-​identifying spread of activation between components always occurs. The automaticity of this spread of activation helps to explain why these states do not take part in the inferential processes definitive of states like beliefs. This in turn suggests that implicit attitudes cannot figure in to practical reasoning in a way that any standard account of practical normativity would require. That is, any account of ordinary practical normativity would not admit of actions based on implicit attitudes, given their inferential impoverishment and form-​insensitivity. As I’ve argued, however, implicit attitudes do not merely cause action. In some sense, they recommend it. This is a deep point of contrast between implicit attitudes and aliefs. Aliefs are, on Gendler’s view, neither good nor bad in and of themselves, but only good or bad to the extent that they are in “harmony” with an agent’s considered beliefs and intentions. In contrast, implicit attitudes have a pro tanto guiding function, one that is also seen in the temporal interplay between co-​activating FTBA relata. As an agent moves and attends to perceived ambient features, her low-​ level feelings of tension are or are not alleviated, giving her a sense of lingering tension or not. This affective sense of lingering tension is action-​guiding, signaling to the agent to continue to attend or behave in some particular way. The skywalker’s aversive feelings persist so long as she perceives the chasm below; the museumgoer feels repelled from the painting until she reaches the right distance from it; the implicitly biased agent feels as if the CV with the male name on it is just a little better, and (unfortunately) this tension resolves as she moves on to the next one in the batch.43 These subtle action-​guiding feelings offer the agent a sense of better and worse that is indexed to her actual behaviors. Of course, this guiding sense of better and worse is not tantamount to the guidance provided by her beliefs, values, and evaluative judgments. Those provide what might be called full-​blown moral or rational normativity. I suggest that the pro tanto guidance function of implicit attitudes may be captured in terms of what Ginsborg (2011) calls “primitive normativity.” At a high level of generality, this is a distinguishing feature of implicit attitudes. Primitive normativity offers agents a sense of how to “go on” without requiring the agent to recognize (explicitly or implicitly) any rules for “going on” correctly. Ginsborg identifies three requirements for an agent to “make a claim” to primitive normativity:  (1) having the necessary training and experience; (2)  having

  I have in mind here the situation in which a CV is not quite worthy of one evaluation but a bit too good for another. Cases of ambiguity like this—​when one says something like “Hmmm . . . not this pile . . . but not this other pile . . . hmmm . . . I guess this pile”—​are those in which gut feelings and the like are most evident. These are the situations in which implicit attitudes are most clearly affecting behavior. Ambiguous situations like this are also those in which measures of implicit attitudes like the IAT are most effective for making behavioral predictions. 43

Implicit Attit ud e s and the A rchitec t ure o f the   Mind

95

sufficient motivation; and (3) experiencing some sense of appropriateness when getting things right.44 Imagine a child, Ginsborg suggests, who has not yet mastered color concepts but who, by following the example of an adult, is sorting green objects by placing them into a bin, while leaving objects of other colors aside.45 It is unlikely that this child is following a rule, like “Place all the green objects in the bin,” since the child does not seem to possess the concept green. But the child is not simply being caused to sort the objects as she does. Rather, a normative claim is embedded in her behavior. The adult who showed her what to do has provided the necessary learning experience. She is sufficiently motivated to follow the adult’s lead, in virtue of her innate disposition to learn by imitation. And, arguably, she experiences some sense of appropriateness in the act. The green objects presumably feel to the child as if they “fit” with the other objects in the bin. The child may become upset upon finding a red object in the bin and experience some sense of pleasure in completing the task.46 Museumgoers and skywalkers and people with implicit biases also seem to make claims to primitive normativity. They would not display the behaviors they

44   I  follow Ginsborg’s formulation that agents “make a claim” to primitive normativity. I  take Ginsborg’s idea to be that there is a normative claim implicit in the agent’s behavior. The agent acts as she does because doing so is, for her, in some sense, appropriate. This is not to say that she endorses what she does or consciously takes her behavior to be appropriate. Rather, the idea is that her behavior is in part motivated by a sense of appropriateness, which is akin, I suggest, to the felt sense of rightness or wrongness embedded in the process of alleviation (see Chapter 2, §4). 45   In this example, it is not just that the child lacks verbal mastery of the concept green. Rather, the child (by hypothesis) lacks the concept itself (some evidence for which may be that the child cannot use the word “green” correctly). That is, the child may be able to discriminate between green and not-​green things without having the concept green. Note that this is a controversial claim. See Berger (2012). 46   See the discussion in Chapter 4 of theories of skill learning. Interestingly, this sense of appropriateness may be found in nonhuman animals, or so suggests Kristen Andrews (2015), who makes use of Ginsborg’s concept of primitive normativity in discussing what she calls “naive normativity.” Naive normativity offers agents a specifically social sense of “how we do things around here.” Andrews and Ginsborg seem to differ on whether, or when, nonhuman animals make claims to primitive or naive normativity. Ginsborg discusses the case of a parrot that has been trained to say “green” when shown green things. She argues that the parrot does not make a claim to primitive normativity, because, while it has had the necessary learning experiences and is suitably motivated to go on in the right way, it does not, Ginsborg thinks, experience a sense of appropriateness when saying “green” at the right time. Andrews discusses the case of goslings having imprinted on a human being rather than their biological mother, and she thinks these animals are in fact likely to experience a sense of appropriateness when following their adopted “mother” around (in addition to having the right experiences and motivation). The goslings will appear to feel calm and comforted when the human “mother” is around and upset in the “mother’s” absence. This empirical question about what parrots and goslings do or don’t experience provides an interesting route to considering whether or how claims to primitive normativity are shared by human beings and nonhuman animals.

96

Mind

do without the necessary learning experiences;47 they are sufficiently motivated by innate or learned mechanisms having to do with object perception, bodily safety, and intergroup categorization; and they experience, if my previous arguments are correct, low-​level affective feelings that are indexed to the immediate success or failure of their actions. Moreover, they do all this without, it seems, needing to grasp rules for their behavior, rules like “Stand this many feet from paintings of that size,” “Avoid glass-​bottomed platforms,” and “Value men’s CVs over women’s.” Indeed, as these cases illustrate, sometimes primitive normativity and full-​blown normativity provide contradictory guidance. In developing the concept of primitive normativity, Ginsborg takes herself to be providing a middle ground for interpreting a certain class of presumably pervasive phenomena, that is, behavior that seems intelligently guided but also seems not to be guided by a conceptual grasp of rules. The middle ground is between thinking that the child sorting blocks is, on the one hand, just being caused to behave appropriately by some subpersonal mechanism and, on the other hand, is acting on the basis of rules that she implicitly understands. These two options mirror my earlier discussion about the place of implicit attitudes in cognitive architecture. To think that the child is being caused to behave appropriately by nothing other than some subpersonal mechanism is akin to saying that her behavior is merely reflexive or associative, as reflexes and mere associations provide no normative guiding force to action. And to surmise that the child is acting on the basis of rules she understands, but only implicitly, is analogous to thinking that she is behaving on the basis of nonconscious doxastic states (i.e., putative implicit beliefs, operating on the basis of unconscious inferences, etc.). Ginsborg’s claim for the middle ground derives from considerations about how the child ultimately masters the concept green. If the child is caused to act appropriately only by subpersonal mechanisms to discriminate green things from not-​green things, then it is unclear how her competence at sorting would ever lead to her acquisition of the concept. The ability to sort things by color wouldn’t at any point offer the agent a basic sense of the appropriateness of which things belong with which, which is presumably an important step in acquiring the relevant concept. And if the child sorts on the basis of an implicit rule, then it is equally unclear how her learning to sort would have any bearing on her acquiring the concept, since, on this interpretation, the sorting presupposes the child’s having the concept. Ginsborg’s middle ground is appealing, then, as a model for how certain kinds of complex abilities that involve perceptions of better and worse interact with higher-​order conceptual abilities.48 More specifically for my purposes, 47   Although it is important to note that these learning experiences can be very brief in some cases. See, for instance, research on the “minimal group paradigm” (Otten and Moskowitz, 2000; Ashburn-​ Nardo et al., 2001). 48   Although, of course, much more would have to be said in order to substantiate this claim. My aim is not to defend Ginsborg’s account of skill learning. Rather, my aim is to show why it is plausible

Implicit Attit ud e s and the A rchitec t ure o f the   Mind

97

Ginsborg’s middle ground also provides a model for the sort of normative guidance implicit attitudes offer agents via their spontaneous inclinations and dispositions. As the kinds of cases I’ve discussed show, sometimes our implicit attitudes go awry from the perspective of moral or rational normativity. Implicit bias illustrates this, as do the other kinds of cases I discussed in Chapter 1 of impulses and intuitions leading to irrational and immoral ends. Other times, our implicit attitudes are better, but in mundane ways that we barely notice, such as in the distance-​ standing and museumgoer cases. And other times still, our implicit attitudes get it right in spectacular ways, such that they seem to provide action guidance in ways that our reflective beliefs and values don’t. The cases of spontaneous reactions and decisions in athletic and artistic domains illustrate this. Here it seems as if agents’ claims to primitive normativity are not just defeasibly warranted. Rather, they seem to be illustrative of a kind of action at its best. The world-​class athlete’s spontaneous reactions show the rest of us how to go on in a particular context; the master painter’s reactions reveal features of perception and emotion we wouldn’t otherwise experience.

7. Conclusion I’ve argued in this chapter that states with FTBA components are best understood as implicit attitudes, which are distinct from reflexes, mere associations, beliefs, dispositions, and aliefs. Along the way, and in summary, I’ve described what makes implicit attitudes unique. By no means have I given a complete account of implicit attitudes, but I hope to have shown why they deserve to be considered a unified and distinct kind of mental state. With these points in mind, I now turn to the relationship between these states and agents themselves. In what sense are implicit attitudes features of agents rather than features of the cognitive and affective components out of which agents minds’ are built? Are implicit attitudes, and the spontaneous actions for which they seem to provide guidance, really ours?

and how it could then play a role in illuminating the peculiar nature of implicit attitudes, as states that neither merely cause behavior nor rationalize it in any full-​blooded sense.

PA RT   T W O

SELF

4

Caring, Implicit Attitudes, and the Self

In “The View from in Here,” an episode of the This American Life podcast, reporter Brian Reed (2013) plays recorded conversations between prisoners and prison guards at the Joseph Harp Correctional Center in Lexington, Kentucky. The prisoners and guards had both just watched a documentary film critical of the prison industry in the United States. The conversations were meant to allow prisoners and guards to reflect on the film. At the center of Reed’s story is a conversation between Antoine Wells, an inmate serving a nine-​year sentence, and Cecil Duly, a guard at the prison. Their conversation quickly turned from the film itself to personal problems between Wells and Duly. Wells speaks at length about his perception of being treated disrespectfully by Duly. He resents being ignored when asking for help, being told to do meaningless tasks like picking daisies so that he’ll remember “who’s in charge,” and generally being viewed as if he’s “nothing.” In response, Duly holds his ground, offering a different interpretation of each of the events Wells describes and claiming that he never shows disrespect to Wells. Duly explicitly defends the notion that Wells, as a prisoner, has “no say over anything.” That’s just what being in prison means. The conversation is heart-​wrenching, in part because Wells and Duly speak past one another so profoundly, but also because both Wells and Duly see that Wells’ experiences will do him no good. They both recognize that Wells is likely to leave prison bereft of resources and skills, angry and indignant toward the society that locked him up, and anything but “rehabilitated.”1 The episode takes a surprising turn when Reed returns to the prison several months later to see if anything has changed between Wells and Duly as a result of their conversation. Duly, the guard, states unequivocally that nothing has changed. He stands by his actions; he hasn’t thought about the conversation with Wells much at all; he feels no different; and he continues to claim that he treats all of the prisoners fairly and equally. Wells, however, feels that quite a lot has changed since he expressed his feelings to Duly. And Wells claims that it is Duly who has changed.

  To his credit, Lieutenant Duly also laments that much of the contemporary prison system in the United States is a for-​profit industry, seemingly incentivized to fail to rehabilitate prisoners. 1

101

102

Self

Duly is less dismissive, he says. Duly takes the time to answer questions. He looks at Wells more like a human being. If we accept both of their testimonies at face value, it seems that Duly has begun to treat Wells kindly on the basis of inclinations that run contrary to Duly’s explicit beliefs. These inclinations seem to unfold outside the ambit of Duly’s intentions and self-​awareness.2 In this sense, Duly’s case resembles those discussed by Arpaly (2004), in particular that of Huckleberry Finn. On Arpaly’s reading, Huck’s is a case of “inverse akrasia,” in which an agent does the right thing in spite of his all-​things-​ considered best judgment. Huck’s dilemma is whether to turn in his friend Jim, an escaped slave. On the one hand, Huck believes that an escaped slave amounts to a stolen piece of property and that stealing is wrong. On the other, Huck is loyal to his friend. He concludes from his (less than ideal) deliberation that he ought to turn Jim in. But Huck finds himself unable to do it.3 While Huck is fictional, there is good reason to think that he is not, in the relevant respects, unusual. Consider, for example, one of the most landmark studies in research on intergroup prejudice. Richard LaPiere published “Attitudes vs. Actions” in 1934, a paper about the two years he spent visiting 251 hotels and restaurants with a couple of Chinese ethnicity. LaPiere and the couple would enter establishments asking for accommodations, and were turned down only once. However, when LaPiere followed up the visits with phone calls to the hotels and restaurants, asking, “Will you accept members of the Chinese race in your establishment?” 92% of the 128 responses were “no.” LaPiere’s study is usually discussed in terms of the gap between attitudes and actions, as well as the importance of controlled laboratory studies.4 (For instance, it is not clear whether LaPiere spoke to the same person at each establishment when he visited and when he phoned subsequently.) But what is perhaps most striking about LaPiere’s study is that the hoteliers and restaurateurs seemed to act ethically when LaPiere visited, despite their explicit prejudiced beliefs. That is, their explicit beliefs were prejudiced but their behavior (in one context, atleast) was comparatively egalitarian. It seems that when these people were put on the spot, with the Chinese couple standing in front of them, they reacted in a comparatively more egalitarian way, despite their beliefs to the contrary. 2   As I say, this depends on our accepting Duly’s testimony—​that he denies feeling any differently toward Wells—​at face value. It is possible that Duly is misleading Reed, the interviewer. It is also quite possible that Duly is aware of his changes in feeling and behavior, and has intended these changes in an explicit way, despite his avowals to the contrary. Perhaps Duly is conflicted and just doesn’t know what to say. This interpretation also runs contrary to his testimony, but it doesn’t quite entail his misleading the interviewer in the same way. The story of Wells and Duly is only an anecdote, meant for introducing the topic of this chapter, and it is surely impossible to tell what is really driving the relevant changes. See §4 for further discussion. 3   The case of Huckleberry Finn was discussed in this context earlier, most notably by Jonathan Bennett (1974). See Chapter 6. 4   See, e.g., the discussion in Banaji and Greenwald (2013).

Car ing , Implicit Attit ud e s , and the   S el f

103

These are all cases in which agents’ spontaneous behavior seems to be praiseworthy, relative, at least, to their explicit beliefs. But are agents’ spontaneous reactions really praiseworthy in these cases? Praise typically attaches to agents, and many people associate agents with their reflective beliefs and judgments. Similar questions arise with respect to the many vice cases in which agents’ spontaneous inclinations seem to be blameworthy. In these cases it is equally difficult to assess the person who acts. Does the skywalker’s fear and trembling tell us anything about her? Are judges who are harsher before lunch (Chapter  1) on the line for the effects of their glucose levels on their judgment, particularly assuming that they don’t know or believe that their hunger affects them? These questions are perhaps clearest in the case of implicit bias. Philosophers who think of agential assessment in terms of a person’s control over or consciousness of her attitudes have rightfully wondered whether implicit biases are things that happen to people, rather than features of people (as discussed later). Across both virtue and vice cases, spontaneity has the potential to give rise to actions that seem “unowned.” By this I mean actions that are lacking (some or all of) the usual trappings of agency, such as explicit awareness of what one is doing or one’s reasons for doing it; direct control over what one is doing; responsiveness to reasons as such; or perceived consistency of one’s behavior with one’s principles or values. But these are actions nevertheless, in the sense that they are not mere happenings. While agents may be passive in an important sense when acting spontaneously, they are not thereby necessarily victims of forces acting upon them (from either “outside” or “inside” their own bodies and minds). The central claim of this chapter is that spontaneous actions can be, in central cases, “attributable” to agents, by which I mean that they reflect upon the character of those agents.5 Attributability licenses (in principle) what some theorists call “aretaic” appraisals. These are evaluations of an action in light of an agent’s character or morally significant traits. “Good,” “bad,” “honorable,” and “childish” are all aretaic appraisals. I distinguish attributability—​which licenses aretaic appraisals—​ from “accountability,” which I take to denote the set of ways in which we hold one another responsible for actions.6 Accountability may license punishment or reward, for example. I develop an account of attributability for spontaneous action in this chapter, in virtue of the place of implicit attitudes in our psychological economy.

  Note that I use the terms “character” and “identity” interchangeably. Note also that while some theorists focus on attributability for attitudes as such, my focus is on attributability for actions. However, as will be clear, I think that judgments about attributability for actions are, and should be, driven primarily by considerations of the nature of the relevant agent’s relevant attitudes. This stands in contrast to questions about accountability, or holding responsible, as I discuss here and in more depth in Chapter 5. 6   For related discussion on distinguishing attributability from accountability for implicit bias, see Zheng (2016). 5

Self

104

In the next chapter, I situate this account with respect to broader questions about accountability and holding responsible.

1. Attributability At its core, attributability is the idea that some actions render the person, and not just the action itself, evaluable. Imagine that I inadvertently step on your toes in a crowded subway car. It’s the New York City subway, which means the tracks are old, and the cars shake and bump and turn unpredictably. I’m holding onto the overhead rail, and when the car jostles me, I shift my feet to keep my balance, and in the process step on your toes. Chances are that you will be upset that I’ve stepped on your toes, because something bad has happened. And, perhaps momentarily, you will be upset at me, not just unhappy in general, since I’m the cause of your pain. Had I not been on the train this day, your toes wouldn’t be throbbing. Or perhaps you have negative feelings about people on the subway in general, because you think they’re clumsy or self-​absorbed and now I’ve just confirmed your beliefs. None of these responses, though, is really about me. The first is about me as nothing more than the causal antecedent of your pain; you’d be equally angry if an inanimate object fell on your foot. The second is about me as an anonymous member of a general class you dislike (i.e., subway riders). In neither case would your reaction signal taking the outcome as reflecting well or poorly on my personality or character. It is doubtful, for example, that you would think that I’m a thoughtless or selfish person, if you granted that my stepping on your toes was really an accident. A contrasting case makes this clear too. Imagine that I stomped on your toes because I felt like you weren’t listening to me in a conversation. In this case, you might understandably feel as if you know something about what kind of person I am.7 You might think I’m a violent and childish person. The charge of childishness is telling, since this kind of behavior isn’t unusual in children, and it curries a different kind of moral assessment in their case. A five-​year-​old who stomps on his teacher’s toes because she’s ignoring him is behaving badly,8 of course, but it is far less clear what we should think about what kind of a person the child is compared with the adult who stomps on your toes on purpose. Back to the subway for a second: it is also not hard to imagine cases in which something significant about my character is open for evaluation, even if I’ve done nothing more than inadvertently step on your toes. If I aggressively push my way toward my favorite spot near the window on the subway and crunch your toes on the way, then something about my character—​something about who I  am as an agent in the world—​gets expressed, even if I didn’t mean to step on your toes. In   You might know about what Peter Strawson (1962) called my “quality of will.”   Mrs. Sykes, wherever you are, I’m sorry.

7 8

Car ing , Implicit Attit ud e s , and the   S el f

105

this last case, I am open for evaluation, even if other putatively “exculpating conditions” obtain.9 In addition to lacking an intention to step on your toes, I might also not know that I’ve stepped on your toes, and I might even have tried hard to avoid your toes while I raced to my favorite spot. Regardless, what I do seems to express something important about me. I’m not just klutzy, which is a kind of “shallow” or “grading” evaluation (Smart, 1961). Rather, you would be quite right to think “what a jerk!” as I push by.10 Theorists have developed the notion of attributability to make sense of the intuition that agents themselves are open to evaluation even in cases where responsibility-​exculpating conditions might obtain. Here’s one standard example: Loaded Gun Fifteen year old Luke’s father keeps a shotgun in the house for hunting, and last fall started to teach Luke how to shoot with it. Luke is proud of the gun and takes it out to show his friend. Since the hunting season has been over for months, it doesn’t occur to Luke that the gun might be loaded. In showing the gun to his friend, unfortunately he pulls the trigger while the gun is aimed at his friend’s foot, blowing the friend’s foot off.11 To some people at least, there is a sense in which Luke himself is on the line, despite the fact that he didn’t intend to shoot his friend and didn’t know that the shotgun was loaded. Luke seems—​to me at least—​callow or reckless. This sense is, of course, strongly mitigated by the facts of the case. Luke would seem monstrous if he meant to shoot his friend in the foot, and he would seem less reckless if he were five rather than fifteen. But in Luke’s case, as it stands, the key facts don’t seem to exculpate all the way down. It should have occurred to Luke that the gun might be loaded, and his failure to think this reflects poorly on him. Some kind of aretaic appraisal of Luke seems appropriate. Of course, I’m trading in intuitions here, and others may feel differently about Luke. There is a large body of research in experimental moral psychology testing the   I borrow the term “exculpating conditions” from Natalia Washington and Daniel Kelly (2016).   I say this loosely, though, without distinguishing between the thought “What a jerk!” and “That guy is acting like a jerk!” The latter reaction leaves open the possibility that the way in which this action reflects on my character might not settle the question of who I really am, at the end of the day. As I discuss in Chapter 5, in relation to the idea of the “deep self,” I am skeptical about summative judgments of character like this. But I recognize that some assessments of character are deeper than others. Perhaps I am having an extraordinarily bad day and am indeed acting jerky, but I don’t usually act this way. As I discuss in §3, dispositional patterns of thought, feeling, and behavior are an important element of characterological assessment. 11   This version of Loaded Gun is found in Holly Smith (2011). Smith’s version is an adaptation from George Sher (2009). For related discussions, see Smith (2005, 2008, 2012), Watson (1996), Hieronymi (2008), and Scanlon (1998). 9

10

106

Self

conditions under which people do and don’t have these kinds of intuitions. I discuss some of this research in the next chapter. For now, all I need is that there exists at least one case in which an action seems rightly attributable to an agent even if the action is nonconscious in some sense (e.g., “failure to notice” cases), nonvoluntarily, nontracing (i.e., the appropriateness of thinking evaluatively of the person doesn’t trace back to some previous intentional or voluntary act or omission), or otherwise divergent from an agent’s will. The difficulty for any theory of attributability is determining that on the basis of which actions are attributable to agents. What distinguishes those actions that are attributable to agents from those that aren’t? Influential proposals have focused on those actions that reflect an agent’s reflective endorsements (Frankfurt, 1988); on actions that reflect an agent’s narrative identity or life story (Schechtman, 1996); and on actions that stem from an agent’s rational judgments (Scanlon, 1998; Smith, 2005, 2008, 2012).12 However, a case like Loaded Gun seems to show how an action can render an agent open to evaluative assessment even if that action conflicts with the agent’s reflective endorsements, narrative sense of self, and rational judgments. Similarly, something about the “moral personality” (Hieronymi, 2008) of agents like Duly, Huck, and the skywalker seem to be on the line, even if these agents’ actions don’t have much to do with their reflective endorsements, narrative sense of self, and rational judgments, and as such aren’t “owned” in the full sense. I’ll say more about these other approaches to attributability in Chapter 5, although nowhere will I offer a full critical assessment of them. Rather, in this chapter I’ll lay out my own view, and in the next I will situate it with respect to other prominent theories.

2.  Caring and Feeling In what follows, I adopt a “care”-​based theory of attributability. Care theories argue that actions that reflect upon what we care about are actions that are attributable to us.13 Caring is intuitively tied to the self in the sense that we care about just those things that matter to us. We care about quite a lot of what we encounter in our day-​ to-​day lives, even if we judge the objects of our cares to be trivial. It might matter to 12   Properly speaking these are theories of “identification.” Identification names the process through which some trait, experience, or action is rendered one’s own (Shoemaker, 2012, 117). Naming the conditions of identification has proved difficult to say the least; it has been called a “holy grail” in the philosophy of action (Shoemaker, 2012, 123). I focus on the conditions of attributability rather than identification because of the line I want to draw between attributability and accountability. That is, I am making a case for how certain “minimal” (unintentional, nontracing, etc.) actions reflect on agents’ character; I am not making a case for the conditions of full ownership of action or for what it means to be responsible for an action. 13   Of course, one can provide a theory of caring itself, with no concern for questions about attributability. My claim is more narrowly focused on the relationship between caring and attributability.

Car ing , Implicit Attit ud e s , and the   S el f

107

me that the ice cubes in my drink are square rather than round, even if, reflectively, I think this is a trivial thing to care about. Or I might care about whether I get to the next level on my favorite phone app, all the while wishing that I spent less time staring at a little screen. Both the ice cubes and the phone app might even matter to me if I’m focally unaware of caring about them. All I might notice is that something feels off about my drink or after I’ve put the phone down. It might become clear to me later that it was the ice cubes or the app that were bothering me, or it might not ever become clear to me that I care about these things. Conversely, sometimes we don’t care about things, even when we think we should. Despite believing that I should probably care about the free-​will debate, usually it just makes me feel . . . meh.14 It is crucial to note that I  am referring to what Agnieska Jaworska (2007b) calls ontological, rather than psychological, features of caring. In the psychological sense, what one cares about are the things, people, places, ideas, and so on that one perceives oneself as valuing. More specifically, the objects of one’s cares in the psychological sense are the things that one perceives as one’s own. Cares in the psychological sense track the agent’s own perspective. In the ontological sense, cares are, by definition, just those attitudes (in the broad sense) that belong to an agent, in contrast to the rest of the “sea of happenings” in her psychic life ( Jaworska, 2007b, 531; Sripada, 2015).15 One can be wrong about one’s cares in the ontological sense, and one can discover what one cares about too (sometimes to one’s own surprise). For example, I might discover that I have, for a long time, cared about whether other people think that I dress stylishly. All along I might have thought that I don’t care about such a trivial thing. But on days that people complimented my clothes, or even merely cast approving glances at me, I felt peppier and more confident, without consciously recognizing it. Both the content of my care (looking stylish) and the emotions connected to it (e.g., feeling confident) might have escaped my conscious awareness. (Recall the point I made in Chapter 2, that emotion is often sufficiently low-​level as to escape one’s own focal awareness.) The care-​based view of attributability is concerned with cares in the ontological sense. Of course, it is often the case that what one cares about in the ontological sense often coincides with what one cares about in the psychological sense. But this is not a requirement. (In 14   Might believing that you should care about φ suffice for showing that you care about φ, perhaps just a little? This is entirely possible. As I note later, my view is ecumenical about various routes to attributability. Believing that φ is good might very well be sufficient for demonstrating that I care about φ. Similarly, avowing that φ is good might also be sufficient for demonstrating that I care about φ. Indeed, I suspect that beliefs and avowals about what one ought to care about often do reflect what one cares about. I intend here only to point to the possibility of there being at least one case of a person believing that she ought to care about φ but failing to care about φ. 15   The psychological sense of caring is perhaps more clearly labeled the “subjective” sense, but for the sake of consistency I follow Jaworska’s (2007b) usage. Note also that the psychological–​ontological distinction is not between two kinds of cares, but rather between two senses in which one might refer to cares.

108

Self

the next chapter, I discuss in more detail the relationship between cares in the ontological sense and the agent’s own perspective.) All things considered, a care-​based theory of attributability is unusually inclusive, in the sense that, on its lights, a great many actions will end up reflecting on agents, potentially including very minor actions, like the museumgoer’s shifting around to get the best view of the painting, as well as actions that conflict with an agent’s reflective endorsements, narrative identities, and rational judgments.16 One virtue of this inclusiveness, as some care theorists have put it, is that cares are conceptually well suited to make sense of actions “from the margins,” for example, the actions of small children and Alzheimer’s patients ( Jaworska, 1999, 2007a; Shoemaker, 2015) or agents with severe phobias or overwhelming emotions (Shoemaker, 2011). Small children, for example, may not be able to make rational judgments about the value of their actions, but they may nevertheless care about things. These sorts of actions don’t easily fit into familiar philosophical ways of conceptualizing attributability. The hard question is what it means to care about something. A persuasive answer to this question is that when something matters to you, you feel certain ways about it. According to the affective account of caring (e.g., Shoemaker, 2003, 2011; Jaworska, 1999, 2007a,b; Sripada, 2015), to care about something is to be disposed to feel certain complex emotions in conjunction with the object of one’s cares. When we care about something, we feel “with” it. As David Shoemaker (2003, 94) puts it, in caring about something, we are emotionally “tethered” to it. To care about your firstborn, your dog, the local neighborhood park, or the history of urban beekeeping is to be psychologically open to the fortunes of that person, animal, place, or activity. Caring in this sense—​of being emotionally tethered to something because it matters to you—​is inherently dispositional. For example, I can be angry about the destruction of the Amazon rainforest—​in the sense that its fate matters to me—​without experiencing the physiological correlates of anger at any particular moment. To care about the Amazon involves the disposition to feel certain things

16   To clarify, the care-​based theory of attributability that I endorse is unusually inclusive. Other care theorists’ views tend to be more restrictive. For example, Arpaly and Timothy Schroeder (1999) argue that “well-​integrated” beliefs and desires—​those beliefs and desires that reflect upon what they call the “whole self ”—​must be both “deep” (i.e., deeply held and deeply rooted) and unopposed to other deep beliefs and desires. I address the issue of opposition in Chapter 5; I’ll argue that we can in fact have conflicting cares. The point I am making here can be fleshed out in terms of depth. Actions that are attributable to agents need not stem from “deep” states, on my view. Theorists like Arpaly and Schroeder are focused only on morally relevant actions and attitudes, however, whereas I am focused on actions that reflect character in general. It is also crucial to keep the scope of my claim in mind. Attributability licenses aretaic attitudes—​reactions stemming from an evaluation of a person’s character—​but it does not necessarily license actively blaming or punishing a person (in the case of bad actions). Keeping in mind that attributability licenses aretaic attitudes alone should help to render the inclusiveness of my claim less shocking. My view can be understood as a reflection of the way in which we perceive and evaluate each other’s character constantly in daily life.

Car ing , Implicit Attit ud e s , and the   S el f

109

at certain moments, like anger when you are reminded of the Amazon’s ongoing destruction. (This isn’t to say that the disposition to feel anger alone is sufficient for caring, as I discuss later.) Caring in this sense is also a graded notion. Imagine that you and I both have pet St. Bernards, Cupcake and Dumptruck. If you tell me that Cupcake has injured her foot, I might feel bad for a moment, and perhaps I will give her an extra treat or recommend a good vet. Maybe I care about Cupcake, but not that much. Or perhaps I care about you, and recognize that you care about Cupcake. If Dumptruck hurts his foot in the same way, however, my reaction will be stronger, more substantive, and longer-​lasting. It seems that I care more about Dumptruck than I do about Cupcake. But what, really, are cares, such that feelings can constitute them? I  follow Jaworska’s (2007b) Neo-​Lockean approach, which builds upon work by Michael Bratman (2000). The core of this approach is that a mental state or attitude that belongs to an agent—​those that are “internal” to her—​must support the cohesion of the agent’s identity over time. Bratman famously argues that plans and policies play this role in our psychological economy. But it is possible that more unreflective attitudes play this role too. As Jaworska shows, Bratman’s elaboration of how plans and policies support identity and cohesion over time is applicable to more unreflective states, like certain emotions. Bratman argues that internal states display continuity over time and referential connectedness. Continuity distinguishes, for example, a fleeting desire from a desire that plays a more substantive role in one’s mind. The concept of continuity also helps to distinguish one and the same state occurring at two points in time from two distinct states occurring at two points in time. In order to be identity-​bearing, my desire for ice cream today must be the same desire as my desire for ice cream tomorrow. Referential connectedness is a relatively more demanding condition. Connections are referential links between mental states or between attitudes and actions. A  referential link is a conceptual pointer. The content of my desire for ice cream, for example, points to the action I take, and the action I take is an execution of this particular desire. The content of the state and the action are co-​referring. This clarifies that it is not enough for internality that a state like a desire causes an action; the content of my desire—​that it is a desire for ice cream—​must point, through a conceptual connection, to my decision to go to the store. Jaworska argues that some, but not all, emotions display continuity and connection. Grief, for example, meets these conditions. On her view, grief involves painful thoughts, a tendency to imagine counterfactuals, disturbed sleep, and so on. These patterns display continuity and, by pointing referentially to the person or thing for which one grieves, display connections as well. “In this way,” Jaworska writes, “emotions are constituted by conceptual connections, a kind of conceptual convergence, linking disparate elements of a person’s psychology occurring at different points in the history of her mental life” (2007b, 553). Other emotions, like a sudden pang of fear, do not display continuity and connection, on her view.

Self

110

On this rendering of the affective account of caring, the thing that you grieve for is something you care about, while whatever made you spontaneously shrink in fear is not. In turn this suggests that your grieving is something reflective of your character, while your fearing is not. I think it is right to say that feelings are tied to “mattering” in this way and that affective states must display continuity and connection to count as mattering. But I find the distinction between grief and fear—​and, more important, the distinction between putative kinds of emotions on which it is based—​unconvincing.

3.  Feeling and Judging The affective account of cares is often based on a distinction between so-​called primary and secondary emotions. Only secondary emotions, the argument goes, are appropriate for underwriting cares. For Jaworska (2007b, 555), secondary emotions are those that involve self-​awareness, deliberation, an understanding of one’s situation, and systematic thought about the significance and consequences of one’s feelings. Jaworska offers gratitude, envy, jealousy, and grief as examples of secondary emotions. A paradigmatic example of a primary emotion, on the other hand, is fear, of the sort that precipitates a driver’s slamming on the brake when the car in front of her stops short or precipitates a mouse’s crouching when it detects the shadow of a hawk pass overhead. Other ostensible primary emotions are disgust, rage, and surprise. All of these, on Jaworska’s view, are more or less stimulus-​bound reflex-​like responses that require no understanding of one’s situation. Much in the same vein, Shoemaker writes: Primary emotions are like reflexes, responses triggered with no mediation by the cognitive mechanisms of the prefrontal cortex, and the emotional reactions falling under this rubric are the familiar “automatic” ones of fear, anger, and surprise. Secondary emotions, on the other hand, require the cognitive ability consciously to entertain a variety of mental images and considerations with respect to the myriad relationships between self, others, and events, i.e., to engage in “a cognitive evaluation of the contents of the events of which you are a part” (Antonio Damasio, Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain [New York: Putnam’s, 1994], p. 136). This, I take it, is the capacity that infants (and nonhuman animals) lack. The analytic relation between emotions and cares discussed in the text, therefore, holds only with respect to these secondary, more robust or developed emotions. (2003, 93–​94)17   Shoemaker and Jaworska appear to disagree about whether “marginal” agents, such as young children, can care about things, but I do not pursue this question. For skepticism about whether nonhuman animals lack the capacity to care, see Helm (1994). 17

Car ing , Implicit Attit ud e s , and the   S el f

111

Jaworska and Shoemaker both stress the importance of complex cognitive capacities—​ deliberation, self-​ awareness, conceptual understanding, systematic evaluative thought, and so on—​in anything that counts as a secondary emotion. In addition, Shoemaker adds the condition of a secondary care-​underwriting emotion being “mediated” by the prefrontal cortex. I do not think the affective account of caring can hang on this distinction between primary and secondary emotion. I offer three reasons. First, some of the core features of the apparent distinction rest on unpersuasive assumptions. This is the case when Shoemaker claims that primary emotions are not mediated by the cognitive mechanisms of the prefrontal cortex. Jaworska (2007b, 555) makes a similar claim in arguing that the defining feature of primary emotions is that they are not processed by “higher” cognitive functions. On a neurofunctional level, the evidence for the traditional association of the amygdala with affect and the prefrontal cortex with cognition is mixed (e.g., Salzman and Fusi, 2010). Moreover, research suggests that affect may be involved in all forms of thought. In a review of recent literature showing that affect plays a key role in the processing of conscious experience, language fluency, and memory, Seth Duncan and Barrett (2007) argue that “there is no such thing as a ‘nonaffective thought.’ Affect plays a role in perception and cognition, even when people cannot feel its influence” and conclude that “the affect-​cognition divide is grounded in phenomenology.”18 Second, the affective account of caring is meant as an alternative to both voluntaristic and judgment-​based accounts of attributionism. I discuss judgment-​based accounts of attributionism in more detail in Chapter 5, especially Angela Smith’s “rational-​relations” view. Here the relevant point is that the appeal of affective accounts of caring is their ostensible ability to make sense of actions that appear to reflect upon agents even if those actions conflict with the agent’s deliberation, explicit judgment, and so on.19 The affective account does so by tracing the source of internality to something other than these cognitively complex reflective capacities. Both Jaworska and Shoemaker stress this point. Jaworska (2007b, 540) writes, “Caring cannot be an attitude derived from an evaluative judgment,” and Shoemaker 18   My point is not that Duncan and Barrett’s strong claim is necessarily correct, but rather that the data’s attesting to the pervasiveness of affect in cognition makes it unlikely that there is a clear line between cognitive and noncognitive emotion. 19   I follow these authors in focusing on cognitively complex reflective capacities in a broad sense. Of course, deliberation, self-​understanding, evaluative judgment, and so on can and sometimes do come apart. Certainly some emotions involve self-​understanding but not deliberation, for example. Perhaps a good theory of secondary emotions would focus on some (or one) of these capacities but not others. A care theorist interested in maintaining the distinction between her approach and voluntarist or judgment-​based approaches to attributionism would then need to show how the particular cognitively complex capacity associated with secondary emotions is functionally distinct from what voluntarist and judgment-​based approaches posit as the source of internality.

112

Self

(2003, 2011) goes to great lengths to distinguish his view from those that find the source of internality in an agent’s reflective judgment (such as Gary Watson [1975] and Smith [2005, 2008]). However, if secondary emotions alone can underwrite cares, and secondary emotions are just those emotions that are partly constituted by cognitively complex reflective capacities like evaluative judgment, then it looks as if the affective account of cares collapses into one based on cognitively complex reflective capacities. Third, the precise relationship between feelings and judgments in so-​called secondary emotions is vague. Jaworska says that secondary emotions “involve” self-​ awareness, deliberation, and so on. Shoemaker says that secondary emotions are “mediated” by the prefrontal cortex and require certain cognitive abilities, such that agents can engage in processes of evaluation. It is hard to situate these claims precisely within theories of emotion (see below for more on theories of emotion). Are evaluative judgments, according to Jaworska and Shoemaker, causes of emotions? Or do they simply co-​occur with emotions? Are they, perhaps, components of emotional states? These differences matter. For example, in the case of envy, it is one thing to say that the object of one’s envy matters to a person because envy involves co-​occurring feelings and judgments, such as the belief that the person who is envied is smarter than oneself. It is another thing to say that the object of one’s envy matters to a person because envy is triggered by the judgment that the person who is envied is smarter than oneself, and subsequently one experiences certain feelings. In the latter case, in which the agent’s judgment is taken to be a causal precursor to her feelings, it seems clear that it is the judgment itself that fixes the agent’s cares. The judgment is responsible for showing what matters to the person, in other words. But, alternatively, if feelings and judgments are taken to co-​occur in a state of envy, it is less clear which of these co-​occurring states is responsible for constituting a care. This becomes particularly salient in cases where feelings and judgments seem to diverge. It’s hard to tell whether and how to attribute a care to me if emotions are constituted by co-​occurring feelings and judgments in the case in which I feel envious despite believing that there is no reason for me to feel this way. Instead of distinguishing between primary and secondary emotions, the affective account of cares should take emotions to represent features of the world that an agent values, even if those representations do not constitute judgments about what the agent finds valuable. Here I build upon Jesse Prinz’s (2004) theory of emotion.20 Prinz (2004) aims to reconcile “feeling” (or “somatic”) theories of emotion with “cognitive” theories of emotions. Crudely, feeling theories argue that emotions are 20   See also Bennett Helm (2007, 2009), who develops an affective theory of caring that does not rely on the distinction between primary and secondary emotions. Helm argues that to experience an emotion is to be pleased or pained by the “import” of your situation. Something has import, according to Helm, when you care about it, and to care about something is for it to be worthy of holistic patterns of your attention and action.

Car ing , Implicit Attit ud e s , and the   S el f

113

feelings and that particular emotions are experiences of particular changes in the body ( James, 1884; Lange, 1885; Zajonc, 1984; Damasio, 1994). For example, elation is the feeling of one’s heart racing, adrenaline surging, and so on. As Prinz argues, feeling theories do a good job of explaining the intuitive difference between emotions and reflective thought. Evidence supporting this intuition stems from the fact that particular emotions can be induced by direct physiological means, like taking drugs. Similarly, particular emotions can be elicited by simple behaviors, such as holding a pencil in your mouth, which makes you feel a little happier, by forcing your lips into a smile (Strack et al., 1988).21 It is hard to give an explanation of this result in terms of an agent’s beliefs or evaluative judgments; why should mechanically forcing your lips into a smile make you think about things differently and thus feel happier? Relatedly, feeling theories do a good job of explaining the way in which our feelings and reflective thoughts can come into conflict, as in the case where I  think that I  shouldn’t be jealous, but feel jealous nevertheless. Feeling theories have trouble, however, making sense of the way in which some emotions are sometimes closely tied to our thoughts. Consider the difference between feeling fearful of a snake, for example, and feeling fearful of taking a test (Prinz, 2004). While your bodily changes may be equivalent in both cases—​racing heart, sweating, and the like—​in the case of the test your fear is tied to your belief that the test is important, that you value your results, and so on, while in the snake case your fear can unfold regardless of whether you believe that snakes are dangerous or that fearing snakes is rational or good. There are many cases like this, wherein our emotions seem closely tied to our beliefs, judgments, values, self-​knowledge, and so on. Parents probably wouldn’t feel anxious when their kids get sick if they didn’t wonder whether what seems by all rights like a common cold might actually be a rare deadly virus. Similarly, jealous lovers probably wouldn’t feel envy if they didn’t harbor self-​doubt. And so on. Traditional feeling theories of emotion—​those that define emotions strictly in terms of the experience of particular changes in the body—​have trouble explaining these common phenomena. Cognitive theories of emotion (Solomon, 1976; Nussbaum, 2001) and related “appraisal” theories (Arnold, 1960; Frijda, 1986; Lazarus, 1991)  do better at explaining the link between emotions and reflective thought. Traditional cognitive theories identify emotions as particular kinds of thoughts. To be afraid of something is to believe or imagine that thing to be scary or worthy of fear, for example. These theories founder on precisely what feeling theories explain: the ways in which emotions and thoughts often seem to come apart and the ways in which emotions can form and change independently of our evaluative judgments. Appraisal theories are a more plausible form of cognitive theory. Appraisal theories argue that

  But see Wagenmakers et al. (2016) effort to replicate Strack et al. (1998). See the Appendix for discussion of replication in psychological science. 21

Self

114

emotions are at least in part caused by thoughts, but they do not identify emotions as such with beliefs, judgments, and the like. Rather, appraisal theories hold that particular emotions are caused by evaluative judgments (or appraisals) about what some entity in the environment means for one’s well-​being. These appraisals are of what Richard Lazarus (1991) calls core relational themes. Particular emotions are identified with particular core relational themes. For example, anger is caused by an appraisal that something or someone has demeaned me or someone I care about; happiness is caused by an appraisal that something or someone has promoted my reaching a goal; guilt is caused by the appraisal of my own action as transgressing a moral imperative; and so on. In one sense, appraisal theories are hybrids of feeling theories and cognitive theories of emotions (Prinz, 2004, 17–​19). This is because appraisals themselves are said to cause agents to experience particular feelings. Appraisals are precursors to feelings, in other words, and emotions themselves can then be thought of as comprising both judgments and feelings. This does not represent a happy reconciliation of feeling theories and cognitive theories, however. If appraisals do not constitute emotions, but are instead causal precursors to feelings, then there should be no cases—​or, at least, predictable and relatively exceptional cases—​in which agents experience the feelings component of emotions without appraisals acting as causal precursors. But the very cases that threaten traditional cognitive theories of emotion illustrate this very phenomenon. These are cases of direct physical induction of emotions, for example, by taking drugs or holding a pencil in one’s mouth. These acts cause emotions without appraisals of core relational themes. And these kinds of cases are pervasive.22 Prinz (2004) suggests a new kind of reconciliation. He retains the term “appraisal” but deploys it in an idiosyncratic way. On a view like Lazarus’s, appraisals are judgments (namely, judgments about how something bears on one’s interest or well-​being). On Prinz’s view, appraisals are not judgments. Rather, they are perceptual representations of core relational themes. Prinz draws upon Fred Dretske’s (1981, 1986) sense of mental representations as states that have the function of carrying information for a particular purpose. In the case of emotions, our mental representations are “set up” to be “set off ” by (real or imagined) stimuli that bear upon core relational themes. For example, we have evolved to feel fear when something is represented as dangerous; we have evolved to feel sadness when something is represented as valued and lost. But just as a boiler being kicked on by the thermostat   Appraisal theorists might add additional conditions having to do with the blocking, swamping, or interruption of appraisals. These conditions would be added in order to explain away cases of apparent dissociation between appraisals and emotions. Given the pervasiveness of such cases, however, the onus would be on appraisal theorists to generate these conditions in a non–​ad hoc way. Moreover, it is unclear if such conditions would cover cases in which the putative appraisal is missing rather than in conflict with the resulting emotion. 22

Car ing , Implicit Attit ud e s , and the   S el f

115

need be reliably caused only by a change in the room’s temperature, fear or sadness need be reliably caused only by a representation of the property of being dangerous or being valued and lost, without the agent judging anything to be dangerous or valued and lost. This is the difference between saying that an appraisal is a representation of a core relational theme and saying that an appraisal is a judgment about a core relational theme. The final key piece of Prinz’s view is to show how representations of core relational themes reliably cause the emotions they are set up to set off. They do so, Prinz argues, by tracking (or “registering”) changes in the body.23 Fear represents danger by tracking a speeded heart rate, for example. This is how Prinz reconciles feeling theories of emotion with cognitive theories. Emotions are more than just feelings insofar as they are appraisals (in the sense of representations) of core relational themes. But emotions are connected to core relational themes not via rational judgments about what matters to a person, but instead by being set up to reliably register changes in the body. 24 My aim is not to defend Prinz’s theory as such (nor to explicate it in any reasonable depth), although I take it to provide a plausible picture of how emotions “attune” agents’ thoughts and actions around representations of value.25 What I take from Prinz’s account is that emotions can represent features of the (real or imagined) world that the agent values without the agent thereby forming rational judgments about that thing. This is, of course, a “low-​level” kind of valuing. In this sense, agents can have many overlapping and possibly conflicting kinds of values (see discussion in Chapter 5). Understood this way, emotions are poised to help indicate what matters to us, in a broader way than other theorists of affective cares have suggested. (That is, some emotions that theorists like Jaworska and Shoemaker think do not tell us   For a related account of emotion that similarly straddles feelings theories and cognitive theories, see Rebekka Hufendiek (2015). Hufendiek argues, however, that the intentional objects of emotions are affordances, not changes in the body. 24   The idea that the emotional component of implicit attitudes are “set up to be set off ” by representations of particular stimuli may seem to sit uncomfortably with my claim that the objects of these representations matter to agents, in the attributability sense. That is, some are inclined to see a conflict between saying that a response is both “programmed” by evolution and attributable to the agent. I do not share this intuition, both because it follows from voluntaristic premises about attributability that I do not endorse and because I do not know how to draw a distinction between responses that are and are not “programmed” by evolution. This is, of course, a question about free will and compatibilism, which I leave to philosophers more skilled than myself in those dark arts. 25   According to Randolph Nesse and Phoebe Ellsworth, “Emotions are modes of functioning, shaped by natural selection, that coordinate physiological, cognitive, motivational, behavioral, and subjective responses in patterns that increase the ability to meet the adaptive challenges of situations that have recurred over evolutionary time” (2009, p. 129; emphasis in original). See also Cosmides and Tooby (2000) and Tooby and Cosmides (1990) for related claims. I take it as counting in favor of Prinz’s theory that treating emotions as perceptual representations of core relational themes helps to show how emotions are adaptive in this sense. 23

Self

116

anything about what an agent cares about will, on my view, indicate what an agent cares about.) But my claim is not that all emotions indicate cares. The relevant states must be continuous across time and referentially connected. I’ll now argue that when emotional reactions are components of implicit attitudes, they can meet these conditions.

4.  Caring and Implicit Attitudes Cross-​temporal continuity is a form of persistence through time, such that states A1 and A2 count as tokens of the same attitude (i.e., A at T1 and A at T2). Connections are referential links between mental states or between attitudes and actions that refer to each other. On the Neo-​Lockean view, states induce organization and coordination within the agent by way of continuities and connections. This is why these are proposed as conditions of agency. On Neo-​Lockean views like Bratman’s (2000), reflective states like plans and policies paradigmatically induce organization and coordination by way of being cross-​temporally continuous and referentially connected. Affective care theorists like Jaworska show that certain emotions also do this. My claim is also that certain emotions do this, not because they are caused by or co-​occur with evaluative judgments, but rather because they are part of integrated FTBA response patterns. As I argued in Chapter 2, implicit attitudes change over time, both quickly and slowly. The intentional object of the implicit attitude remains the same through this process, tokening the state. While stray emotions can fail to display continuity over time, emotional reactions that are part of an implicit attitude are shaped by the agent’s learning history as well as by the feedback she receives on her behavior. Implicit attitudes are also anticipatory states; the museumgoer, for example, seeks alleviation by looking for the right spot to view the painting. Emotions—​understood in the way I  have proposed—​also display conceptual connections when they are components of implicit attitudes. They do so in two ways. First, the FTBA relata of implicit attitudes converge upon the same intentional object. The museumgoer notices the big painting, feels tension about the big painting, steps back from the big painting, and registers the success of this reaction in feed-​forward learning mechanisms stored in memory for future encounters with big paintings.26 Second, implicit attitudes internally co-​refer. Recall my argument in Chapter 3, building upon Gendler (2012), that implicit attitudes are unlike ordinary beliefs and desires in the sense that beliefs and desires are “combinatoric.” That is, any belief can, in principle, be paired with any desire. In contrast, implicit   As I have noted, cares are graded. You might care about the big painting only a little bit. It might also be right to say that what you care about are paintings like this one. The object of your care in this case is the type, not the token. 26

Car ing , Implicit Attit ud e s , and the   S el f

117

attitudes are individuated at the cluster level. Their relata co-​activate rather than merely frequently co-​occur. This is why implicit attitudes are singular entities rather than a collection of frequently co-​occurring but fundamentally separate representations, feelings, actions, and changes over time. Given this, it seems right to say that the FTBA relata of implicit attitudes are co-​referring in the sense that they are conceptually connected. It is this bonding between the relata that connects these states to an agent’s cares. More precisely, it is the tight connection between particular combinations of dispositions to notice, feel, behave, and adjust future automatic reactions to similar stimuli that displays referential connections of the sort that indicate a genuine connection to what the agent cares about.27 These conditions are not met in contrast cases of isolated perceptual, affective, or behavioral reactions. On its own, an agent’s tendency to notice particular features of the ambient environment, for example, bears little or no relation to the agent’s cares. The odd shape of a window might catch your eye while you walk to work, or a momentary feeling of disgust might surface when you think about having been sick last week. So what? Whatever fleeting mental states underlie these changes in attention fail to display both continuity and connection. The states do not persist through time, nor do they refer to any of the agent’s other mental states. But when you notice that the window causes a coordinated response with FTBA components, and you see and act and learn from your actions, perhaps stepping back to see it aright, something about what you care about is now on display. Or when you recoil from the feces-​shaped fudge, not just feeling disgust but also reacting behaviorally in such a way as to stop the fudge from causing you to feel gross, something about what you care about is now on display. Consider two cases in more detail. First, ex hypothesi, Cecil Duly displays belief-​discordant attitudes toward Antoine Wells. While Duly denies that he thinks or feels differently about Wells after their conversation, he begins to treat Wells 27   Developing a point from John Fischer and Mark Ravizza (1998), Levy (2016) identifies three criteria for demonstrating a “patterned” sensitivity to reasons. Meeting these criteria, he argues, is sufficient for showing that an agent is directly morally responsible for an action, even if the agent lacks person-​level control over that action. Levy’s three criteria are that the agent’s apparent sensitivity to reasons be continuously sensitive to alterations in the parameters of a particular reason; that the agent be sensitive to a broad range of kinds of reasons; and that the agent demonstrate systematic sensitivity across contexts. Levy then goes on to argue that the mechanisms that have implicit attitudes as their components fail to be patterned in this way; they fail to meet these three criteria. While I think these criteria represent a promising way to think about the relationship between implicit attitudes and the self, I would frame and analyze them differently. Being patterned in this way strikes me as a promising avenue for understanding actions that are attributable to agents. In any case, I would contest—​as much of the discussion in this and the preceding chapter suggests—​Levy’s claim that implicit attitudes paradigmatically fail to be patterned in this way. Elsewhere, Levy (2016) writes that implicit attitudes are not “entirely alien to the self ” and that “that suffices for some degree of attributability.” One could interpret the argument of this chapter to be my way of analyzing the degree of attributability that implicit attitudes paradigmatically deserve.

Self

118

more kindly and humanely nevertheless. It’s plausible to think that Duly’s action-​ guiding attitudes are implicit. In interacting with Wells, Duly might now see, without explicitly noticing, a particular pained look on Wells’s face (F:  “human suffering!”), feel disquieted by it (T: “bad to cause pain!”), move to comfort Wells in some subtle way, perhaps by saying “please” and “thank you” (B:  “offer reassurance to people in pain!”), and absorb the feedback for future instances when this behavior alleviates his felt tension (A: “suffering reduced!”). Focusing on the emotional component of Duly’s reaction in particular, in Prinz’s terms, Duly seems to have formed an emotion-​eliciting appraisal of Wells. The core relational theme Duly represents is perhaps guilt; Wells’s perceived suffering conveys to Duly that he has transgressed a moral value. This appraisal will be reliably caused by particular somatic changes in Duly’s autonomic nervous system associated with representations of others as suffering or as in pain (De Coster et  al., 2013). These processes are value-​signaling, even if Duly forms no evaluative judgments about Wells or even if Duly’s evaluative judgments of Wells run in the opposite direction of his implicit attitudes. Of course, other interpretations of this anecdote are possible. Perhaps, despite his testimony, Duly simply thought to himself that Wells deserves better treatment and changed his behavior as a result. Nothing in the story rules this interpretation out. But it seems unlikely. Duly’s testimony should be taken as prima facie evidence for what he believes.28 People do not always report their beliefs truthfully or accurately, but Duly’s explicit denial of feeling or acting differently toward Wells is not irrelevant to determining what has changed in him. Moreover, while Duly was forced to listen to Wells during the discussion of the film, and thus might have simply been persuaded by Wells’s reasoning, in a way indicative of a belief-​based interpretation of Duly’s changed attitudes, it is not as if Wells’s arguments are new to Duly. Duly has heard Wells complaining for a long time, he says. It is plausible to think that something other than the force of Wells’s arguments had an impression on Duly.29 Perhaps there was something in the look on Wells’s face that affected Duly in this particular context. Or perhaps the presence of a third party—​Reed—​ acted as an “occasion setter” for a change in Duly’s implicit attitudes toward Wells.30 For example, Duly probably had never before been forced to interact with Wells in   See Chapter 3.   An experiment to test these questions might change the strength of Wells’s arguments and look for effects on Duly (or, more precisely, would do so on subjects performing tasks operationalized to represent Wells’s and Duly’s positions). Or it might change crucial words in Wells’s testimony and compare implicit and explicit changes in Duly’s attitudes. See Chapter 3 for a discussion of analogous experiments. See also the discussion in Chapter 6 of research on changing unwanted phobic reactions (e.g., to spiders) without changing explicit attitudes. 30   Occasion setting is the modulation of a response to a given stimulus by the presence of an additional stimulus, usually presented as part of the context (Gawronski and Cesario, 2013). See the discussion in Chapter 7 of renewal effects on implicit learning in the animal cognition literature. 28 29

Car ing , Implicit Attit ud e s , and the   S el f

119

anything like an equal status position, and perhaps by virtue of being in this position, Duly’s associations about Wells shifted.31 If this is right, then the question is whether the object of Duly’s implicit attitude constitutes something that Duly cares about. It does to the extent that Duly’s attitude appears to display both cross-​temporal continuities and the right kind of referential connections. Duly’s interactions with Wells are sustained over time. Wells himself experiences Duly’s actions as manifestations of one and the same attitude. Indeed, it would be hard to understand Duly’s actions if they were interpreted as manifesting distinct attitudes rather than as various tokens of one and the same attitude. This makes sense, also, given that Duly’s relevant attitudes all point toward the same intentional object (i.e., Wells). Not only does Duly’s attitude point toward Wells, but the various components of this attitude also all seem to refer to Wells. Duly perhaps noticed a look on Wells’s face, feels disquieted by the look on Wells’s face, acts in such a way as seems appropriate in virtue of his perception of and feelings about Wells, and incorporates feedback from this sequence into his attitude toward Wells in future interactions. All of this suggests that Duly cares about Wells, if only in a subtle and conflicted way. Indeed, Duly’s caring attitude is conflicted. He explicitly states the opposite of what I’ve suggested his implicit attitudes represent. But this can be the case, given that cares, in the sense I’ve discussed, are ontological, not psychological. Second, consider an implicit bias case. Here it seems perhaps more difficult to show that the objects of an agent’s implicit attitudes are things she cares about. In “shooter bias” studies (see Chapter 1), for instance, participants try hard to shoot accurately, in the sense of “shooting” all and only those people shown holding guns. Participants in these experiments clearly care about shooting accurately, in other words. But this fact does not foreclose the possibility that other cares are influencing participants’ judgments and behavior. Indeed, it seems as if participants’ shooting decisions reflect a care about black men as threatening (to the agent). Again, this is a care that the agent need not recognize as her own.32 The emotional component here is fear, which it is argued signals to the agent how she is faring with respect to personal safety. This value-​laden representation speaks to what matters to her. To see this, it is important to note that the shooter bias test does not elicit generic or undifferentiated fear, but rather fear that is specifically linked to the perception of black faces. This linkage to fear is made clear in consideration of the interventions that do and do not affect shooter bias. For example, participants who adopt the conditional plan “Whenever I see a black face on the screen, I will think ‘accurate!’ ” do no better than controls. However, participants who adopt the plan “Whenever I see 31   Changes in social status have been shown to predict changes in implicit attitudes (e.g., Guinote et al., 2010). See Chapter 7. 32   In Chapter 5, I discuss the way in which inconsistent caring is not problematic in the way that inconsistent believing is.

Self

120

a black face on the screen, I will think ‘safe!’ ” demonstrate significantly less shooting bias (Stewart and Payne, 2008). Fear is one of Lazarus’s core relational themes; it is thought to signal a concrete danger. And in Prinz’s terms, it is reliably indicated by specific changes in the body (e.g., a faster heart rate). Evidence for the cross-​temporal continuity of participants’ implicit attitudes in this case comes from the moderate test-​retest reliability of measures of implicit associations (Nosek et al., 2007).33 Moreover, Correll and colleagues (2007) find little variation within subjects in multiple rounds of shooter bias tests. It is also fairly intuitive, I think, that agents’ decisions across multiple points in time are manifestations of the same token attitude toward black men and weapons rather than manifestations of wholly separate attitudes. The case for conceptual convergence is strong here too. The agent’s various spontaneous reactions to white/​black and armed/​unarmed trials point referentially to what matters to her, namely, the putative threat black men pose. The finding of Correll and colleagues (2015) that participants in a first-​person shooter task require greater visual clarity before responding to counterstereotypic targets compared with stereotypic targets (see Chapter  2) is conceptually connected to pronounced fear and threat detection in these subjects (Stewart and Payne, 2008; Ito and Urland, 2005) and to slower shooting decisions. Note that this conceptual convergence helps to distinguish the cares of agents who do and do not demonstrate shooter bias. Those who do not will not, I suggest, display the co-​activating perceptual, affective, and behavioral reactions indicative of caring about black men as threatening. Of course, other cases in which agents act on the basis of spontaneous inclinations might yield different results. I have focused on particular cases in order to show that implicit attitudes can count as cares. The upshot of this is that actions caused by implicit attitudes can reflect on character. They can license aretaic appraisals. This leaves open the possibility that, in other cases, what an agent cares about is fixed by other things, such as her beliefs.

5. Conclusion One virtue of understanding implicit attitudes as having the potential to count as cares, in the way that I’ve suggested, is that doing so helps to demystify what it means to say that a care is ontological rather than psychological. It’s hard to see how one can discover what one cares about, or be wrong about what one cares about, on the basis of an affective account of caring too closely tied to an agent’s self-​understanding, beliefs, and other reflective judgments. To the extent that these accounts tie care-​ grounding feelings to self-​awareness of those feelings or to evaluative judgments   See the discussion of test-​retest reliability in Chapter 3 and the Appendix.

33

Car ing , Implicit Attit ud e s , and the   S el f

121

about the object of one’s feelings, cares in the ontological and psychological senses seem to converge. But implicit attitudes are paradigmatic instances of cares that I can discover I have, fail to report that I have, or even deny that I have. This is most relevant to the vices of spontaneity, where, because of potential conflict with our explicit beliefs, we are liable to think (or wish) that we don’t care about the objects of our implicit attitudes. But, of course, cases like those of Huck and Duly show that this is relevant to the opposite kind of case too, in which our spontaneous reactions are comparatively virtuous. This in turn gives rise to at least one avenue for future research. In what ways do changes in implicit attitudes cause or constitute changes in personality or character? Two kinds of cases might be compared: one in which a person’s implicit attitudes are held fixed and her explicit attitudes (toward the same attitude object) change and another in which a person’s implicit attitudes change and her explicit attitudes (toward the same attitude object) are held fixed. How would observers judge changes in personality or character in these cases? Depending, of course, on how changes in attitudes were measured (e.g., what kinds of behavioral tasks were taken as proxies for changes in attitudes), my intuition is that the former case would be associated with larger changes in perceived personality than would the latter case, but that in both cases observers would report that the person had changed.34 Relatedly, the arguments in this chapter represent, inter alia, an answer—​or alternative to—​the question of whether implicit attitudes are personal or subpersonal states. Ron Mallon, for example, argues that personal mental states occur “when a situation activates propositional attitudes (e.g. beliefs) about one’s category and situation,” while subpersonal mental states occur “when a situation activates mere representations about one’s category and situation” (2016, p.  135, emphasis in original). On these definitions, implicit attitudes are not personal mental states, because they are not propositional attitudes (like beliefs; see Chapter  3).35 Nor are they subpersonal mental states, because they are not mere representations of categories and situations (Chapter 2).36 Neither are implicit attitudes what Mallon 34   Loosely related research shows that measures of explicit moral identity tend to make better predictions of moral behavior than do measures of implicit moral identity (Hertz and Krettenauer, 2016). 35   Levy (2017) offers an even more demanding definition of the related concept of “person-​level control.” On his view, adapted from Joshua Shepherd, “[p]‌erson-​level control is deliberate and deliberative control; it is control exercised in the service of an explicit intention (to make it the case that such and such)” (2014, pp.  8–​9, emphasis in original). On the basis of this definition, Levy argues that we generally lack person-​level control over actions caused by implicit attitudes. I discuss Levy’s argument—​in particular the role of intentions to act in such and such a way in assessing questions about attributability and responsibility—​in Chapter 5. 36   Implicit attitudes are not mere representations of categories and situations, because they include motor-​affective and feedback-​learning components (i.e., the T-​B-​A relata). Perhaps, however, Mallon could posit action-​oriented or coupled representations as subpersonal states (see Chapter 2). Even so, Mallon suggests that however subpersonal states are defined, they are connected with one another in merely causal ways. Implicit attitudes, by contrast, are sensitive to an agent’s goals and cares.

122

Self

calls personal mental processes—​“rational processes of thought and action”—​nor subpersonal mental processes—​merely “automatic, causal processes.” Implicit attitudes seem to share features of both personal and subpersonal states and processes. They are about us, as persons, but not necessarily about our beliefs or our rational processes of thought and action. More broadly, the upshot of what I’ve said here is that implicit attitudes can constitute cares, even though these states may involve nothing more than tendencies to notice salient features in the environment, low-​level feelings, “mere” motor behavior, and subpersonal dynamic feedback systems. The relation to one’s identity is not in these mental state relata themselves, but in their mutual integration. Most important, then, the kind of mental state that I have identified with our spontaneous inclinations and dispositions—​implicit attitudes—​is a source of identity over time. These inclinations are therefore attributable to us and license aretaic appraisals of us. When we act on the basis of these attitudes, our actions are not just instrumentally valuable or regrettable, or good and bad as such. Evaluations of these actions need not be shallow or merely “grading.” In virtue of them, we are admirable or loathsome, compassionate or cruel, worthy of respect or disrespect. Admittedly, this entails a very broad account of the self. On my view, a great many more actions and attitudes will reflect on who we are as agents, compared with what other attributionist views suggest. This raises questions about the precise relationship between cares and actions, about responsibility for this broad array of actions that are attributable to us, and about the fundamentality of the “deep self.” I address these and other questions in the next chapter.

5

Reflection, Responsibility, and Fractured Selves

The preceding chapter established that paradigmatic spontaneous actions can be “ours” in the sense that they can reflect upon us as agents. They may be attributable to us in the sense that others’ reactions to these actions are sometimes justifiably aretaic. I have defended this claim about spontaneous actions being ours on the basis of a care-​based theory of attributability. In short, caring attitudes are attributable to agents, and implicit attitudes can count as cares. But a number of questions remain. First, what exactly is the relationship between cares and action, such that actions can “reflect upon” cares (§1)? Second, when an action reflects upon what one cares about, is one thereby responsible for that action? In other words, are we responsible for the spontaneous actions in which our implicit attitudes are implicated (§2)? Third, how “deep” is my conception of the self? Do our implicit attitudes reflect who we are, really truly deep down (§3)? Finally, my account of attributable states is not focused on agents’ intentions to act or on their awareness of their actions or their reasons for action. Nor does my account focus on agents’ rational judgments. What role do these elements play (§4)?

1. Reflection While I hope to have clarified that implicit attitudes can count as cares, I have not yet clarified what it takes for an action to reflect upon one’s cares. As Levy (2011a) puts it in a challenge to attributionist theories of moral responsibility, the difficulty is in spelling out the conditions under which a care causes an action, and “in the right sort of way.”1 The right sort of causality should be “direct and nonaccidental” 1   Most researchers writing on attributionism accept that a causal connection between an agent’s identity-​grounding states and her attitudes/​actions is a necessary condition for reflection (e.g., Levy, 2011a; Scanlon, 1998; Sripada, 2015). Note also two points of clarification regarding Levy’s (2011a) terminology. First, he identifies a set of propositional attitudes that play the same role in his discussion

123

Self

124

and must also be a form of mental causality, as others have stressed (Scanlon, 1998; Smith, 2005, 2008; Sripada, 2015). These conditions are to rule out deviant causal chains, but also to distinguish actions that reflect upon agents from actions as such. For an action to say something about me requires more than its simply being an action that I perform (Shoemaker, 2003; Levy, 2011a). Answering my ringing cell phone is an action, for example, but it doesn’t ipso facto express anything about me. In the terms I have suggested, this is because answering the phone is not something I particularly care about. My cares are not the effective cause of my action, in this case. (I will return to this example later.) Causal connection between cares and actions is a necessary condition for the latter to reflect the former, but it doesn’t appear to be sufficient. To illustrate this, Chandra Sripada describes Jack, who volunteers at a soup kitchen every weekend. Jack cares about helping people in need, but Jack also cares about Jill, who also works at the soup kitchen and whom Jack wants to impress. Sripada stipulates that the reason Jack volunteers is to impress Jill. The problem, then, is that “given his means-​ends beliefs, two of Jack’s cares—​his Jill-​directed cares and his charity-​ directed cares—​causally promote his working at the soup kitchen. But working at the soup kitchen, given the actual purposes for which he does so, expresses only his Jill-​directed cares” (Sripada, pers. com.). The problem, in other words, is that agents have cares that are causally connected to their actions yet aren’t reflected in those actions.2 We can overcome this problem by considering Jack’s actions in a broader context.3 Does he go to the soup kitchen on days when Jill isn’t going to be there? Does he do other things Jill does? Has he expressed charity-​directed cares in other venues, and before he met Jill? These kinds of questions not only illuminate which of an agent’s cares are likely to be effective (as in the Jack and Jill case), but also whether an

as what I have been calling cares. That is, he refers to an agent’s identity-​grounding states as “attitudes.” Second, Levy distinguishes between an action “expressing,” “reflecting,” and “matching” an attitude (or, as I would put it, an action or attitude expressing, reflecting, and matching an agent’s cares). For my purposes, the crucial one of these relations is expression. It is analogous to what I call “reflection.”   How can two cares “causally promote” the same action? Shouldn’t we focus on which singular mental state actually causes the action, in a proximal sense? This kind of “event causal” conception of cares—​that is, the view that the event that is one’s action must be caused by a singular state—​runs into the problem of long causal chains (Lewis, 1973; Sripada, 2015). Cares are not proximal causes of action. For example, Jack’s cares about Jill don’t directly cause him to volunteer at the soup kitchen. Rather, these cares cause him to feel a particular way when he learns about the soup kitchen, then to check his schedule, then call the volunteer coordinator, then walk out the door, and so on. “Because the connections between one’s cares and one’s actions are so indirect and heavily mediated,” Sripada writes, “there will inevitably be many cares that figure into the causal etiology of an action, where the action does not express most of these cares” (pers. com.). Thanks to Jeremy Pober for pushing me to clarify this point. 3   Sripada (2015) proposes a different solution, which he calls the Motivational Support Account. 2

R ef l ec tion , R e spons ib ilit y, and Frac t ured   S elve s

125

agent’s cares are effective in any particular case. Consider again the case of answering the cell phone. Imagine a couple in the midst of a fight. Frank says to work-​ obsessed Larry, “I feel like you don’t pay attention to me when I’m talking.” Larry starts to reply but is interrupted by his ringing phone, which he starts to answer while saying, “Hang on, I might need to take this.” “See!” says Frank, exasperated. In this case, answering the phone does seem to reflect upon Larry’s cares. His cares are causally effective in this case, in a way in which they aren’t in the normal answering-​ the-​phone case. We infer this causal effectiveness from the pattern toward which Frank’s exasperation points. The fact that this is an inference bears emphasizing. Because we don’t have direct empirical access to mental-​causal relations, we must infer them. Observations of patterns of behavior help to justify these inferences. Patterns of actions that are most relevant to making inferences about an agent’s cares are multitrack. Jack’s and Larry’s actions appear to reflect their cares because we infer counterfactually that their Jill-​directed cares (for Jack) and work-​directed cares (for Larry) would manifest in past and future thought and action across a variety of situations. Jack might also go to see horror movies if Jill did; Larry might desire to work on the weekends; and so on. Patterns in this sense make future actions predictable and past actions intelligible. They do so because their manifestations are diverse yet semantically related. That is, similar cares show up in one’s beliefs, imaginations, hopes, patterns of perception and attention, and so on. Another way to put all of this, of course, is that multitrack patterns indicate dispositions, and inferences to dispositions help to justify attributions of actions to what a person cares about. Levy articulates the basis for this point in arguing that people are responsible for patterns of omissions: Patterns of lapses are good evidence about agents’ attitudes for reasons to do with the nature of probability. From the fact that there is, say, a 50% chance per hour of my recalling that it is my friend’s birthday if it is true that I care for him or her and if internal and external conditions are suitable for my recalling the information (if I am not tired, stressed, or distracted; my environment is such that I am likely to encounter cues that prompt me to think of my friend and of his or her birthday, and so on), and the fact that I failed to recall her birthday over, say, a 6-​hour stretch, we can conclude that one of the following is the case: either I failed during that stretch to care for him or her or my environment was not conductive to my thinking of him or her or I was tired, stressed, distracted, or what have you, or I was unlucky. But when the stretch of time is much longer, the probability that I failed to encounter relevant cues is much lower; if it is reasonable to think that during that stretch there were extended periods of time in which I was in a fit state to recall the information, then I would have had to have been much unluckier to have failed to recall the information if I genuinely cared for my friend (Levy 2011[b]‌). The longer the period of time, and the more

Self

126

conducive the internal and external environment, the lower the probability that my failure to recall is a product of my bad luck rather than of my failure to care sufficiently. This is part of the reason why ordinary people care whether an action is out of character for an agent: character, as manifested in patterns of response over time, is good evidence of the agent’s evaluative commitments in a way that a single lapse cannot be. (2011a, 252–​253) In practice, this notion of reflection as inferred on the basis of dispositional patterns of behavior works as follows. Consider again the case of shooter bias (Chapters 1 and 4). The fact that behavioral responses on a shooter bias test are predicted by measures of black–​violence implicit associations (e.g., an IAT; Glaser and Knowles, 2008) suggests that the agent’s behavior is indeed caused by her attitudes (i.e., those attitudes that reflect upon what she cares about). These behavioral predictions are buttressed by studies in which manipulations of black–​violence implicit associations lead to changes in shooting behavior (Correll et al., 2007). Moreover, the multitrack patterns of behavior that tests of black–​danger associations appear to predict rule out the possibility that participants’ behavior is caused by their cares but that their behavior doesn’t reflect their cares (as in the Jack and Jill case). Test-​ retest reliability (Nosek et al., 2007), particularly within specific and shared contexts, demonstrates that the relevant associations are relatively durable.4 Also, caring about the purported violent tendencies of black men doesn’t manifest in shooting behavior alone, but gives rise to a pattern of related results, such as ambiguous word and face detection (Eberhardt et  al., 2004), social exclusion (Rudman and Ashmore, 2007), and the allocation of attention (Donders et al., 2008).5 These patterns may be hard to notice in daily life, since social norms put pressure on people to behave in unprejudiced ways, and most people are fairly good at regulating their

  See the Appendix for discussion of test-​retest reliability and boosting it using relevant context cues.   See Chapter  2, footnote 9, for discussion of Eberhardt et  al.’s (2004) finding of how black–​ criminal associations create attentional biases and shape word and face detection. Laurie Rudman and Richard Ashmore (2007) used an IAT measuring associations between white and black faces and negative terms specifically (although not exclusively) related to violence. The terms were violent, threaten, dangerous, hostile, unemployed, shiftless, and lazy. (Compare these with the terms used on a standard attitude IAT:  poison, hell, cancer, slime, devil, death, and filth.) Rudman and Ashmore found that black–​violent associations on this IAT predicted reports of engaging in socially excluding behavior (specifically, how often participants reported having made ethnically offensive comments and jokes, avoided or excluded others from social gatherings because of their ethnicity, and displayed nonverbal hostility, such as giving someone “the finger,” because of their ethnicity). The black–​violent IAT outpredicted the attitude IAT specifically with respect to discriminatory behavior. Finally, Nicole Donders and colleagues (2008) show that black–​violent associations—​but neither danger-​irrelevant stereotypes nor generic prejudice—​predict the extent to which black faces, versus white faces, capture the attention of white subjects. 4 5

R ef l ec tion , R e spons ib ilit y, and Frac t ured   S elve s

127

implicit attitudes.6 This is precisely the reason controlled experiments are important. They have the ability to create and control the conditions under which multitrack patterns of behavior emerge. These points seem to be building to the claim that people should be held responsible for their implicit attitudes. And, more broadly, that people are responsible for any spontaneous action that fits the characterization I’ve given. But responsibility is not a monolithic concept.

2.  Caring and Responsibility Theories of attributability are generally meant as theories of responsibility. The usual idea is that actions that are attributable to agents are actions for which agents are responsible. If attributability is sufficient for responsibility, and if my arguments in the preceding chapter were correct, then it would follow that having an implicit attitude toward φ, which causes one to act toward φ in some way that meets the conditions described in that chapter, would be sufficient for holding an agent responsible for those actions. This would be a problematic upshot, for at least two related reasons. First, it seems strange to say that agents are responsible for minor acts like stepping back from large paintings and smiling at friends who look like they need reassuring. These actions just seem too minor and inconsequential to raise questions about responsibility (let alone questions about moral responsibility). Second, this result would seem to entail an incredibly expansive conception of responsibility, one that would mean holding people responsible for seemingly unfree behaviors, like phobic reactions (e.g., to spiders), actions resulting from brainwashing, addictions, and so on. One might worry that my account of attributability is far too inclusive, such that on its lights we end up caring about—​and seemingly responsible for—​just about everything we do (and maybe even everything that is done to us). I suspect this worry is driven by conflating the concept of being responsible with the concept of holding responsible. More specifically, I  think it is the reasonable

  Although the truth of each of these three claims—​that patterns of biased behavior are hard to notice in daily life; that social norms put pressure on people to behave in unprejudiced ways; and that people are fairly good at regulating their implicit attitudes—​are highly dependent on many contextual factors. People in different epistemic positions, due to education and social privilege, will likely be variably susceptible to the “blind spot bias” (i.e., the tendency to recognize biases more easily in others than in oneself). Social norms favoring egalitarianism are highly geographically variable. And people’s untutored skill in regulating their implicit attitudes is content-​dependent. This can be seen in average correlations between implicit and explicit attitudes. Generally implicit and explicit attitudes converge for attitude-​objects like brand preferences, for which there are not strong social incentives to regulate one’s implicit attitudes, and diverge for attitude-​objects like racial preferences, for which there are strong incentives to regulate one’s implicit attitudes (although more so in some places than others). Thanks to Lacey Davidson for pushing me to clarify this. 6

Self

128

thought that it would be strange to hold a person responsible for some minor spontaneous action—​in the sense of holding the person to some obligation that she ought to discharge—​that drives the worry about my account of attributability being too inclusive. First I’ll explain the important difference between being and holding responsible, as I understand it, and what this difference means for the relationship between the self and spontaneity (§2.1). My basic claim will be that agents are often responsible for their spontaneous actions in the attributability sense but that this does not license judgments about how we ought to hold one another responsible.7 I’ll then use this distinction to contextualize my claims with recent research in empirical moral psychology (§2.2). To be clear, through all of this, my claims have to do with responsibility for actions. But in many cases (though not all, as I argue later), whether and how one is responsible for a given action—​or even for a mere inclination—​has to do with the psychological nature of the attitudes implicated in it.

2.1  Being Responsible and Holding Responsible As I argued in Chapter 4, attributability opens agents in principle to aretaic appraisals. This is, roughly, what I take being responsible for some action to mean. I say “roughly” because it is often the case that “being responsible” is used as a catch-​ all for a collection of related concepts. One might say, “Lynne is responsible,” and mean by it that Lynne (and not Donna) stole the money or that Lynne is a responsible person or that Lynne should be punished. On my view, no one of these meanings of the concept of responsibility is basic or fundamental.8 Attributability captures just one of these meanings, namely, that some action expresses something about the agent herself who acted. It captures the sense in which, for example, we might say that Lynne is responsible for this; she’s really greedy sometimes. In this attributability sense, we don’t say that “Lynne is responsible” simpliciter. Rather, we use the concept of responsibility as a way of opening space for characterological or aretaic assessment. In contrast, holding responsible is essentially actional, in the sense that it levies a behavioral demand upon oneself or another. To hold oneself or another responsible is to demand that one do something. I think there are basically two ways to hold an agent responsible: borrowing terms from Shoemaker (2011), I call these “answerability” and “accountability.”9 I describe each in turn. My overall point is to show   Because my primary interest in this and the preceding chapter is the relationship between the self and spontaneity (which I take the concept of attributability to address), I will leave aside the question of when, or under what conditions, we ought to hold one another responsible for actions driven by implicit attitudes. 8   See John Doris (2015) for a sustained argument that there is no one monotonic way of setting the conditions of responsible agency. 9   Shoemaker does not understand answerability and accountability as two forms of holding responsible. For Shoemaker, there are three kinds of moral responsibility, each equiprimordial, so to 7

R ef l ec tion , R e spons ib ilit y, and Frac t ured   S elve s

129

that it is plausible that agents are responsible for paradigmatic spontaneous actions in the attributability sense, because being responsible in this sense does not necessarily mean that one is obliged to answer for one’s actions or be held to account for them in some other way. Answerability describes the condition of being reasonably expected to defend one’s actions with justifying (and not just explanatory) reasons. These must be the reasons that the agent understood to justify her action (Shoemaker, 2011, 610–​ 611). Holding Lynne responsible in the answerability sense means conceptualizing the question “Why did you φ?” as appropriate in this context. When we demand an answer to this kind of question, we intrinsically tie the action to the agent’s judgment; we tie what Lynne did to the presumed considerations that she judged to justify what she did. Demanding an answer to this question is also a way of exacting a demand on Lynne. Being answerable in principle means being open to the demand that one offer up one’s reasons for action. In this sense, being answerable is a way of being held responsible, in the sense of being held to particular interpersonal obligations.10 Being “accountable” is another way of being held responsible for some action. It is different from answerability in the sense that being accountable does not depend solely or even primarily on psychological facts about agents. Whether it is appropriate to demand that Lynne answer for her actions depends, most centrally, on whether her action stemmed from her evaluative judgments or was connected to them in the right way (see §4 for further discussion). In contrast, there are times when it seems appropriate to hold someone responsible notwithstanding the status of that person’s evaluative judgments or reasons for action. These are cases in which we incur obligations in virtue of social and institutional relationships. Watson (1996, 235), for example, defines accountability in terms of a three-​part relationship of one person or group holding another person or group to certain expectations, demands, or requirements. For example, the ways in which I might hold my daughter accountable have to do with the parenting norms I accept, just as what I expect of a baseball player has to do with the social and institutional norms governing baseball. In a similar vein, Shoemaker (2011) defines accountability in terms of actions that involve relationship-​defining bonds. Understood this way, practices of holding accountable can be assessed in particular ways, for example, whether they are justified in light of the promises we have made within our relationships. speak: attributability, answerability, and accountability. My view is much indebted to Shoemaker’s, and the ways I define these terms are similar to his. But I take answerability and accountability to be two species of the same kind, namely, as two ways of holding responsible, and my usage of these terms departs from his accordingly.   In §4.3, I  will discuss Smith’s influential “rational-​relations” view, according to which moral responsibility is just answerability. On Smith’s view, in other words, attributability and answerability range over precisely the same actions. 10

Self

130

I am, of course, running somewhat roughshod over important disagreements between other theorists’ conceptions of answerability and accountability. My aim is only to make the case that these forms of holding responsible are separate from responsibility as attributability. Consider the difference between being responsible in the attributability sense and holding responsible in the answerability sense. Both Shoemaker (2011) and Jaworska (1999, 2007a) have offered extensive discussion of cases that are meant to make this distinction clear. Shoemaker discusses agents who suffer from phobias, such as an irrational fear of spiders, which cause them to feel and behave in spider-​averse ways that they reflectively disavow. He also discusses agents with strong emotional commitments that persist in spite of what they think they ought to do, such as a parent who continues to love a child despite judging that the child is a bad person for having done something unforgivable. Shoemaker argues that evaluations of agents like these are more than “shallow.” They are, rather, deep in the sense that we treat phobias and strong emotions as reflective of agents’ enduring traits and identity. Feelings and actions like these “reflect on me,” Shoemaker writes, “and in particular on who I am as an agent in the world, but they are not grounded in any evaluative reasons” (2011, 611–​612). Shoemaker defends his argument in three ways: via an appeal to intuition; an appeal to folk practices; and an appeal to his own account of cares as identity-​grounding attitudes. Jaworska’s examples are young children and Alzheimer’s patients. Both, she argues, have deep, identity-​grounding attitudes that nevertheless do not reflect rational judgments. This is because rational judgments require commitments to correctness, and young children and Alzheimer’s patients are often incapable of being so committed. Before a certain age, for example, young children appear not to grasp the notion of a belief being correct or incorrect.11 If true, then they cannot form ration­al judgments. Yet they are moral agents, for whom actions can be, in at least an attenuated way, expressive of who they are. Whether or not the agents in these cases should be held responsible in the accountability sense depends on further facts about each case. The spider-​phobe can’t reasonably be held accountable for her phobic reactions just as such, but if she takes a job at the zoo, she might incur institutional obligations that require her to work in the proximity of spiders. In this case, notwithstanding her psychology, she might be justifiably asked to undergo treatment for her phobia, if she wants to   Jaworska’s claim here is ambiguous between young children being unable to distinguish between true and false beliefs and young children failing to possess the concept of a false belief as such. Very young children—​as young as two or three —​demonstrate in their own behavior the ability to recognize a belief as mistaken. It is trickier to determine when children come to possess the concept of a false belief as such. One proxy may be a child’s ability to fluently distinguish between appearance and reality. John Flavell and colleagues (1985) report that a fragile understanding of the appearance–​reality distinction emerges somewhere around ages four to six. Thanks to Susanna Siegel for pushing me to clarify this point. 11

R ef l ec tion , R e spons ib ilit y, and Frac t ured   S elve s

131

keep her job.12 In a more intimately interpersonal context, you might hold a friend accountable for returning your phone calls in virtue of the obligations of friendship.

2.2  Responsibility in Practice I have been arguing for particular conceptions of action, the self, and responsibility more or less from the armchair. The growing literature in empirical moral psychology is relevant to these concepts, however. Many moral psychology studies suggest that people do not always (or often) conceptualize action, the self, and responsibility in the ways philosophers have suggested.13 More specifically, some studies suggest that the proposals I’ve made are at odds with dominant folk judgments. A telling example is the investigation by Cameron and colleagues (2010) into the conditions under which people are more or less likely to hold others responsible for implicit racial biases. Cameron and colleagues compared participants’ reactions across three conditions. In each condition, participants read about “John,” a white manager of a company who has to decide whom to promote among various candidates on the basis of merit. (Two other analogous scenarios were used as well: one describing “Jane,” who has to decide to whom to rent an apartment; and one describing “Jim,” who has to assign grades to students’ work.) In the “consciousness” condition, participants are told that John consciously believes that people should be treated equally, regardless of race, but subconsciously dislikes black people. John doesn’t consciously know that he doesn’t like black people, and his subconscious dislike ends up influencing his hiring decisions, such that he sometimes unfairly denies black employees promotions. In the “automaticity” condition, John is aware of his negative “gut feelings” toward black people; he tries, but fails to control this feeling and ends up unfairly denying black employees promotions. Finally, in the third condition, participants are given no details about John’s biases. They are simply told that he believes that people should be treated equally, regardless of race, but sometimes he unfairly denies black employees promotions. Cameron and colleagues’ question was whether and how participants would assign moral responsibility differently across these conditions. Their finding was that participants cut John significantly more slack in the first condition than in the second and third conditions. That is, when participants understood John to be unaware of his biases, they considered him to be less morally responsible for his actions. This is an interesting finding in its own right, given that lack of awareness diminished moral responsibility judgments significantly more than lack of control. On the face of it, this study could also be understood to contradict my claim that   But the facts about her psychology might make her answerable for her decision to take the job at the zoo in the first place. 13   For an overview, see Doris (2015). 12

132

Self

agents are responsible, in the attributability sense, for paradigmatic spontaneous actions, including actions influenced by implicit biases, even when agents are unaware of the reasons why they act as they do. But a closer look at how judgments about moral responsibility were assessed in Cameron and colleagues’ study is telling. After reading the vignette about John, participants were asked to agree or disagree (on a 5-​point Likert scale) with four statements, which together constituted the study’s “Moral Responsibility Scale.” The statements were: (1) “John [or Jane or Jim, depending upon the assigned content domain of the scenario] is morally responsible for his treating African Americans unfairly”; (2) “John should be punished for treating African Americans unfairly”; (3)  “John should not be blamed for treating African Americans unfairly” (reverse-​coded); and (4), “John should not be held accountable for treating African Americans unfairly” (reverse-​ coded) (Cameron et al., 2010, 277). While intuitive, these items lump together moral responsibility as such, punishment, blame, and accountability. Participants’ overall responses to this scale don’t tell us whether they distinguished between John being responsible, in the attributability sense, and holding John responsible, in the sense of demanding that John explain himself or demanding that John be punished or actively blamed. It’s possible that participants’ judgments were driven entirely by their assessments of whether John ought to be held responsible for his actions, particularly since none of the four items on the Moral Responsibility Scale single out aretaic appraisals.14 More recent research by Liz Redford and Kate Ratliff (2016) appears to support this possibility. Using Cameron and colleagues’ Moral Responsibility Scale, Redford and Ratliff also found that participants were more willing to ascribe responsibility to a person described in a vignette as being aware, rather than unaware, of his implicit biases. But Redford and Ratliff also found that participants’ judgments about the target’s obligation to foresee the behavioral consequences of his own implicit biases mediated their moral responsibility judgments.15 The more a participant thought that the person in the vignette had an obligation to foresee his discriminatory behavior, the more the participant held the person in the vignette responsible for that behavior. It is important to note that participants’ perceptions of 14   Cameron and colleagues (2010) report that the four items on the Moral Responsibility Scale had an “acceptable” internal consistency (Cronbach’s α = .65). This means that participants’ answers to the four items on the scale were somewhat, but not strongly, correlated with each other. While this suggests that participants’ conceptions of moral responsibility as such, punishment, blame, and accountability are clearly related to one another, it also suggests that these may be distinct concepts. Another possibility is that participants’ answers are internally consistent, to the degree that they are, because participants treat the four questions as basically equivalent, when taking the survey. When enacting related judgments in the wild, these same participants might make more discrepant judgments. It would be interesting to see the results of a similar study in which the questions were presented separately between subjects. 15   See also Washington and Kelly (2016).

R ef l ec tion , R e spons ib ilit y, and Frac t ured   S elve s

133

targets’ actual foresight of their own behavior, rather than participants’ perceptions about what the targets ought to foresee, did not mediate their moral responsibility judgments. This suggests that participants’ views about holding responsible—​the obligations they ascribe to others—​explain their answers on the moral responsibility scale. This suggests in turn that we do not know how participants in these studies would make specifically aretaic judgments about actions affected by implicit attitudes. A study on folk attitudes toward responsibility for implicit bias could carefully distinguish between participants’ willingness to evaluate others’ character, to demand others’ reasons for action, and to hold others accountable in various ways. These same outcome measures could be applied to other cases of spontaneous and nondeliberative actions as well, such as subtle expressions of interpersonal fluency and even athletic improvisation.

3.  The Deep Self It is easy to think that talk about actions that reflect on one’s “self” implies that each of us is defined by one core unified thing, our fundamental or “deep” self. I want to resist this implication, as it surfaces in both the attributionist literature (§3.1) and the empirical moral psychology literature (§3.2).

3.1  Attributionism and Fundamentality In most of the attributionism literature, the fundamentality of the self has to do with the essence of one’s evaluative attitudes.16 Conceptualizing the self in this sense offers an answer to the question “But what do you truly think or feel about φ, at the end of the day?” Here I use “think” loosely, not to describe a cognitive state per se, but an agent’s overall evaluative sense of things or, put another way, an agent’s summary judgment, including her thoughts and feelings. Perhaps another way to put this would be that the self for attributionism represents how you regard things, deep down, both cognitively and affectively. For example, Holly Smith writes: It appears that to blame someone is to negatively appraise something like that person’s whole evaluative structure insofar as it bears on his act . . . [and i]ntroducing the term “moral personality,” we can say that a person’s full moral personality with respect to an act is the entirety of the person’s evaluative attitudes (including both attitudes with explicitly moral content as well as ones without explicit moral content) toward the features the person supposes the act to have. Blameworthiness, then, seems to turn on the

  See, e.g., Levy (2011).

16

134

Self

extent to which a person’s full moral personality is involved in choosing to perform the act. (2015, 190)17 Levy also articulates the view that attributionism is concerned with the fundamental self in this sense. In writing about responsibility for implicit bias, he argues that attributionists are “committed to excusing agents’ responsibility for actions caused by a single morally significant attitude, or cluster of such attitudes insufficient by themselves to constitute the agent’s evaluative stance, when the relevant attitudes are unrepresentative of the agent. This is clearest in cases where the attitude is inconsistent with the evaluative stance” (2011, 256). In other words, attributionists must excuse agents’ responsibility for actions caused by implicit biases because these attitudes, while morally significant, don’t constitute the agent’s fundamental stance. He then goes on to describe implicit biases in these terms, stressing their arationality (or “judgment-​insensitivity”), concluding that attributionists “ought to excuse [agents] of responsibility for actions caused by these attitudes.” Levy takes this as a problem for attributionism. But for my purposes, the important point is that Levy assumes a fundamentally unified conception of an agent’s evaluative stance. This is what I take him to mean when he says that an attitude or cluster of attitudes “constitutes” the agent’s “global” evaluative stance.18 One challenge for this conception of the self is that conflicts occurring within one’s self are difficult to understand, on its lights. There is no problem for this view with the idea of conflict between an agent’s superficial attitudes, of course. But the notion that agents have a fundamental evaluative stance—​a unified deep self—​ means that one of their attitudes (or set of attitudes) must represent them, at the end of the day. Conflicts within the self—​for example, both favorable and unfavorable deep evaluations of φ—​would make answering the question “But what do you truly think or feel about φ, at the end of the day?” seemingly impossible. If this understanding of the self is correct, then it will be hard to see how spontaneous action will ever reflect on the agent. If there can be no conflicts within one’s fundamental self, then in cases of conflict between spontaneous inclination (of the 17   Emphasis added. Smith credits the term “moral personality” to Pamela Hieronymi (2008), but uses it in a different way. 18   In concluding their presentation of what they call the “Whole Self ” view of moral responsibility, Arpaly and Schroeder write, “We agents are not our judgments, we are not our ideals for ourselves, we are not our values, we are not our univocal wishes; we are complex, divided, imperfectly ration­al creatures, and when we act, it is as complex, divided, imperfectly rational creatures that we do so. We are fragmented, perhaps, but we are not some one fragment. We are whole” (1999, pp.  184–​185). I agree with this eloquent description of what it is to be an agent. The question I am here considering is whether the fact that we are whole agents means that attributability judgments necessarily target each other’s “whole” self.

R ef l ec tion , R e spons ib ilit y, and Frac t ured   S elve s

135

kind I’ve described, and not just mere reflexes or mere associations) and reflective judgment, it is hard to see how attributability would ever “go with” one’s spontaneous inclinations. But must we think of the self (in the attributability sense) as fundamental and unified? Why assume that there is some singular way that one regards φ at the end of the day? It strikes me as coherent to think of the self as tolerating internal heterogeneity and conflict. Sripada (2015), for example, writes of a “mosaic” conception of the deep self. The mosaic conception accepts conflicts internal to the deep self. Recall that Sripada’s conception of the self is, like mine, constituted by one’s cares. Unlike a set of beliefs, Sripada argues, it is not irrational to hold a set of inconsist­ ent cares. “To believe X, believe that Y is incompatible with X, and believe Y is irrational,” he writes, but “to care for X, believe that Y is incompatible with X, and care for Y is not irrational.” In other words, cares need not be internally harmonious, in contrast with (an ideally rational set of) beliefs or reflective judgments, which reflect what the agent takes to be true. Thus while a belief-​based conception of the deep self would not be able to tolerate internal conflict between evaluative attitudes, a care-​based conception can, because it is not irrational to have an inconsistent set of cares. On my view, a theory of attributability need not try to pinpoint a person’s bottom-​line evaluative regard for φ, at the end of the day, so to speak. Instead, it can aim to clarify the conditions under which an action reflects upon a person’s substantive evaluative regard for φ, even if that regard conflicts with other deep attitudes of the agent. Everything hangs on what “substantive” means. I endorse a capacious conception of “substantive.” Character is reflected in a great many more actions than most theories suggest. In spirit my claim is close to Shoemaker’s when he offers aretaic praise for his demented grandfather: Suppose that when I visit my demented grandfather, he reaches for a chocolate in the candy jar and brings it over to me, despite the great physical effort it requires. After accomplishing this, he is on to the next things: moving a bowl on his kitchen counter an inch to the left, gazing out the window at a preening cardinal, turning to ask me who I am. My expressing real gratitude to him at that point has no communicative point (it may well be highly confusing). He cannot remember what he just did, he will not remember how I respond to what he just did, he cannot identify with that moments-​ago agent, and he cannot deliberate about the future (and so identify with some expected future self). He lacks the sense of his agential identity required to be accountable. Nevertheless, what he did was kind—​ perhaps he took the fact that it would give me pleasure to be a reason to bring me a chocolate—​and if he does this generally, it reflects on a kindness that is a trait of his character. He is kind. (2015, 98)

Self

136

In Chapter 4, I offered an account of cares meant to capture this intuition. Here my claim is that these cares may be disunified and that no one set need be considered fundamental. Note that this allows that some of an agent’s evaluative attitudes are more substantive than others. Thus the kinds of aretaic appraisals directed toward an action reflecting implicit bias, for example, are likely to be considerably weaker than the kinds of aretaic appraisals directed toward an action reflecting explicitly endorsed bias. As before (§2), I think the intuition that there must be some fundamental attitude, or set of attitudes, that “takes the rap” at the end of the day makes perfect sense when one is considering the question of how to hold agents responsible for their actions. But it plays no necessary role in thinking about the nature of the self to which those actions are attributable.19

3.2  The Deep Self in Practice As in the case of Cameron and colleagues’ study of folk attributions of responsibility for implicit bias (§2.2), empirical research on this question is illuminating, while also leaving some questions open. This is particularly true in the moral psychology literature focused on the theory of the “good true self ” (Newman et al., 2014, 2015). According to this theory, people commonly believe that everyone has a “true self,” who they really are “deep down,” and, moreover, that the true self is fundamentally good (according to one’s own subjective perception of “good”). Evidence for this view is found in studies in which observers are more likely to say that another person’s true self is reflected in behavior that the observer thinks is morally good rather than morally bad (Newman et al., 2014). For example, liberals’ versus conservatives’ values toward homosexuality predict different judgments about whether a person’s actions stem from her true self. Liberals, who are more inclined to find homosexuality morally acceptable, are more likely to attribute same-​sex attraction to a person’s true self, compared with conservatives, who are more inclined to find homosexuality morally unacceptable (Inbar et  al., 2012). Moreover, and what is important for my purposes, George Newman and colleagues (2014) find that these results are independent of whether people are described as acting on the basis of their “feelings” or their “beliefs.” This is meant to dispel the idea that the folk more commonly associate who one “really is” with one’s unmediated, automatic, affective states (one’s “feelings”) or with one’s reflective, considered avowals (one’s “beliefs”). Instead, Newman and colleagues find that people associate others’ true selves with whatever behavior they (the observers) think is morally good. The findings of this research seem to be bad news for my view, in the sense that they might warrant, in this context, displacing discussion of the differences between   For research suggesting that the folk hold a related pluralist conception of the self, see Tierney et al. (2014). 19

R ef l ec tion , R e spons ib ilit y, and Frac t ured   S elve s

137

spontaneous and reflective action with discussion of moral judgments as such. In other words, I have spilled a lot of ink arguing about the conditions under which spontaneous action reflects upon who one is. But research on the good true self seems to suggest—​so far as questions about the relationship between action and the self are concerned—​that whether an action is spontaneous or impulsive matters less than whether the action is perceived as good. This sort of displacement of the central topics of traditional discussion in the literature is argued for by revisionists about moral responsibility (Vargas, 2005; Faucher, 2016; Glasgow, 2016). But as in Cameron and colleagues’ study, here too we have to look closely at the measures. Participants in Newman and colleagues’ (2014) study 3, the one comparing the roles of feelings and beliefs, were directly asked to what extent the person described in the vignette would “still be true to the deepest, most essential aspects of his being.” Participants were directly asked about their attitudes toward the person’s “deepest” self, in other words. Whatever the answers people give to this question, those answers won’t tell us whether people think that particular kinds of action reflect upon the agent herself, independent of questions about the agent’s deepest self. In other words, what research on the “good true self ” shows is that when people are asked about others’ deepest selves, they primarily use their own moral values for guidance. But assume that I’m correct that the “deep” self can be fractured and mosaic, that both my positive and negative attitudes toward φ can be part of my deep self (or, as I would put it, can count among my cares). The good true self literature doesn’t illuminate how the folk would make judgments about others’ selves in this sense. This is not a knock against the theory of the good true self. It would be interesting to investigate the role of participants’ moral values in judgments about others’ fractured selves, that is, judgments about others’ selves in the attributability sense I developed in Chapter 4. For example, in testing intuitions about a Huck Finn–​like character, participants might be asked whether deep down in Huck’s soul he truly cares about Jim, truly believes in slavery, or is truly divided. It would be unsurprising to find that moral values play a key role in judgments like these, given the large body of moral psychology research demonstrating the pervasiveness of moral values in judgments of all sorts, such as judgments about intentional action (Knobe, 2003), moral luck (Faraci and Shoemaker, 2014), and the continuity of personal identity (Strohminger and Nichols, 2014). I  suspect that this research can be integrated with, rather than represent a challenge to, the kind of attributionist theory for which I have been arguing.

4.  Intention, Awareness, and Rational Relations Thus far, I’ve argued that actions that reflect upon our cares are attributable to us and that the conditions under which an action is attributable to an agent are not the

Self

138

same as the conditions under which an agent ought to be held responsible for an action. Moreover, I’ve argued that our cares can be in conflict with one another. This leads to a pluralistic or mosaic conception of the self. But surely, a critic might suggest, there must be something to the idea that an agent’s intentions to act, and her awareness of those intentions or of other relevant features of her action, play a core role in the economy of the self. When we consider one another in an aretaic sense, we very often focus on each other’s presumed intentions and conscious states at the time of action. Intentions and self-​awareness seem central, that is, not just to the ways in which we hold one another responsible (e.g., in juridical practices), but also to the ways in which we assess whether an action tells us anything about who one is. What role do these considerations play in my account? I consider them in turn: intentions first, then self-​awareness. Then, I consider an influential alternative: if neither intentions to act nor awareness of one’s reasons for action are necessary features of attributable actions, what about the relatively weaker notion that for an action to be attributable to an agent, the agent’s relevant attitudes must at least be in principle susceptible to being influenced by the agent’s rational judgment? Mustn’t attributable actions stem from at least in principle judgment-​sensitive states?

4.1 Intentions Judging whether or not someone acted on the basis of an intention is indeed very often central to the kind of aretaic appraisals we offer that person.20 The subway rider who steps on your toes on purpose is mean-​spirited and cruel, whereas the one who accidently crunches your foot while rushing onto the train is more like moderately selfish. As it pertains to my account of spontaneous action, the question is not whether an agent’s intention to φ often matters, but rather whether it must matter, in the sense of playing a necessary role in the way attributability judgments ought to be made. But what about long-​term intentions? Consider again Obama’s grin. One might concede that this micro-​action was not reflective of an occurrent intention to reassure the chief justice, but insist instead that Obama’s automatic dispositions to smile and nod were reflective of a long-​term, standing intention, perhaps to be a social person. In this case, one might say that Obama’s spontaneous act of interpersonal fluency was attributable to him, but on the basis of its reflecting upon his long-​term intentions. But emphasizing long-​term intentions in this kind of context is problematic, for at least three reasons. First, it is not obvious how to pick out the relevant intention with which one’s gestures are to be consistent without making it either impracticably specific or

  Here I mean “intentional” in the ordinary sense, of doing A in order to bring about B (e.g., smiling intentionally in order to put someone at ease). 20

R ef l ec tion , R e spons ib ilit y, and Frac t ured   S elve s

139

vacuously general. Of which long-​term intentions are Obama’s reactions supposed to be reflective? “To be sociable” is too general to tell an agent much about how to handle a flubbed Oath of Office; and “Reassure chief justices with a smile when they flub Oaths of Office” is uselessly specific. Second, the over-​or underspecificity of such intentions suggests their causal inefficacy. In order for the objection I’m considering to get a grip, some appropriate causal relationship must hold between a long-​term intention and one’s spontaneous action. One’s intentions must be in charge. Perhaps a long-​term intention could make itself felt “in the moment” if an agent had cultivated habits concordant with it in advance. With enough practice, a good Aristotelian can make it the case that the right response springs forth in the face of some salient contextual cue. But making it the case that the intention to be sociable guided one in the moment would radically underdetermine the range of possible ways an agent might respond during a flubbed Oath of Office. The intention is simply too general to help an agent respond appropriately to the contextual particulars. And an agent could not feasibly avoid this problem by identifying and practicing for every possible contingency. Of course, both Obama and Roberts did practice beforehand, and presumably they did consider ways things might go wrong during the inauguration. Indeed, to the extent that Obama holds a relevant long-​term intention to be sociable, doesn’t just about everyone who aspires to public office, including Roberts? (Doesn’t almost everyone?) And yet many people, similarly situated, would have handled the situation much less gracefully. A similarly situated agent who did not respond as Obama did would not thereby have failed to accomplish the intention to be sociable. Nor should we attribute Obama’s success to an ability to harmonize such an intention with his spontaneous reactions. What makes this implausible is the difficulty of imagining how such intentions could be discernibly operative in the moment. Third, to the extent that you find something admirable in how Obama handled the situation, consider what the actual source of that admiration is. Is Obama praiseworthy because he is really good at harmonizing his winks and nods with his long-​ term intentions? Is this the source of our admiration in such cases? Even if some relevant causal connection does obtain between Obama’s long-​term intentions and his spontaneous reactions, we would be forced to think that, in this case, the fact of that connection is the reason we find the spontaneous reaction admirable. It is more likely that we notice Obama’s social adeptness because we sense that, if placed in a similar situation, we would be far less skillful.

4.2 Awareness Aretaic appraisals of spontaneous action don’t necessarily trace back to an agent’s apparent long-​term intentions to act in some way. But what about an agent’s self-​ awareness? In some sense it may seem strange to say that character judgments of others are appropriate in cases where the other person is unaware of what

Self

140

she is doing. But my account of attributability does not include conscious self-​ awareness among the necessary conditions of an action’s reflection on an agent. Should it? It is important to separate different senses in which one might be self-​aware in the context of acting. One possibility is that one is aware, specifically, of what one is doing (e.g., that I’m staring angrily at you right now). Another possibility is that one is aware of the reasons (qua causes) for which one is doing what one is doing (e.g., that I’m staring angrily at you because you insulted me yesterday). A third possibility is that one is aware of the effects of one’s actions (e.g., that my staring will cause you to feel uncomfortable).21 Each of these senses of self-​awareness bears upon attributability. When one is self-​aware in all three senses, the relevant action surely reflects upon who one is in the attributability sense. But is awareness in any of these senses necessary? In advancing what he calls the “Consciousness Thesis,” Levy (2012, 2014) argues that a necessary condition for moral responsibility for actions is that agents be aware of the features of those actions that make them good or bad. They must, in other words, have a conscious belief that what they are doing is right or wrong. For example, in order for Luke to be responsible for accidentally shooting his friend in Loaded Gun (Chapter 4), it must be the case that Luke was aware, at the time of the shooting, that showing the gun to his friend was a bad thing to do, given the possibility of its being loaded. If Luke was completely unaware of the facts that would make playing with the gun a stupid idea, then Luke shouldn’t be held morally responsible for his action. Levy’s argument for this derives from his view of research on the modularity of the mind. In short, the argument is that minds like ours are modular, that is, they are made up of independently operating systems that do not share information (Fodor, 1983). Modularity presents an explanatory problem: How is it that behavior so often seems to integrate information from these ostensibly dissociated systems? For example, if our emotions are the products of one mental module, and our beliefs are the products of another, then why doesn’t all or most of our behavior look like an incomprehensible jumble of belief-​driven and emotion-​driven outputs that are at odds with one another? Everyone recognizes that this is sometimes the case (i.e., sometimes our beliefs and our feelings conflict). But the question is how the outputs of mental modules ever integrate. Levy’s answer is that consciousness performs the crucial work of integrating streams of information from different mental modules. Consciousness creates a “workspace,” in other words, into which different kinds of information are put. Some of this information has to do with action guidance, some with perception, some with evaluative judgment, and so on. This workspace of consciousness is what allows a person to put together information about an action that she is performing with information about that action being   I adapt these three possibilities from Gawronski and colleagues’ (2006) discussion of the different senses in which one might be aware of one’s implicit biases. 21

R ef l ec tion , R e spons ib ilit y, and Frac t ured   S elve s

141

right or wrong. In Luke’s case, then, what it means to say that he is aware of the features of his action that makes the action good or bad is that his mind has integrated information about what he’s doing—​playing with a gun—​with information about that being a bad or stupid thing to do—​because it might be loaded. One of Levy’s sources of evidence for this view are experiments showing that self-​ awareness tends to integrate otherwise disparate behaviors. For example, in cognitive dissonance experiments (e.g., Festinger, 1956), agents become convinced of particular reasons for which they φed, which happen to be false. But after attributing these reasons to themselves, agents go on to act in accord with those self-​attributed reasons. Levy (2012) interprets this to show that becoming aware of reasons for which one is acting (even if those reasons have been confabulated) has an integrating effect on one’s behavior. Levy ties this integrating effect of self-​awareness to the conditions of responsible agency. Put simply, his view is that we can be thought of as acting for reasons only when consciousness is playing this integrating role in our minds. And we are morally responsible for what we do only when we are acting for reasons. Levy doesn’t distinguish between being responsible and holding responsible in the same way as I do, so it is not quite right to say that Levy’s claim is one about the necessary conditions of attributability (as I’ve defined it). But the Consciousness Thesis is meant as a claim about the minimal conditions of agency. Since all attributable actions are actions as such, any necessary condition of agency as such should apply mutatis mutandis to the minimal conditions of attributability. So could some version of the Consciousness Thesis work to show that actions are attributable to agents just in case they consciously believe that they are doing a good or bad thing? One worry about the Consciousness Thesis is that it relies upon Levy’s global workspace theory of consciousness, and it’s not clear that this theory is correct. Some have argued that no such global workspace exists, at least in the terms required by Levy’s account (e.g., Carruthers, 2009; King and Carruthers, 2012). Even if the global workspace theory is true, however, I think there are reasons to resist the claim that consciousness in Levy’s sense is a basic condition of attributability (or of responsible agency in the attributability sense). Consider star athletes.22 In an important sense, they don’t seem to be aware of the reasons their actions are unique and awe-​inspiring. As I noted in Chapter 1, Hall of Fame NFL running back Walter Payton said, “People ask me about this move or that move, but I don’t know why I did something. I just did it.”23 Kimberly Kim, the youngest person ever to win the US Women’s Amateur Golf Tournament, said, “I

22   See Brownstein (2014) and Brownstein and Michaelson (2016) for more in-​depth discussion of these examples. See also Montero (2010) for critical discussion of cases that do not fit the description of athletic expertise that I give. 23   Quoted in Beilock (2010, 224).

Self

142

don’t know how I did it. I just hit the ball and it went good.”24 Larry Bird, the great Boston Celtic, purportedly said, “[A lot of the] things I  do on the court are just reactions to situations . . . A lot of times, I’ve passed the basketball and not realized I’ve passed it until a moment or so later.”25 Perhaps the best illustration arises in an interview with NFL quarterback Phillip Rivers, who fails pretty miserably to explain his decisions for where to throw: Rivers wiggles the ball in his right hand, fingers across the laces as if ready to throw. He purses his lips, because this isn’t easy to articulate. “You always want to pick a target,” he says. “Like the chin [of the receiver]. But on some routes I’m throwing at the back of the helmet. A lot of it is just a natural feel.” Rivers strides forward with his left leg, brings the ball up to his right ear and then pauses in midthrow. “There are times,” he says, “when I’m seeing how I’m going to throw it as I’m moving my arm. There’s a lot happening at the time. Exactly where you’re going to put it is still being determined.” Even as it’s leaving the fingertips? More head-​shaking and silence. Finally: “I don’t know,” says Rivers. “Like I said, there’s a lot going on.” (Layden, 2010) What’s perplexing is that these are examples of highly skilled action. A form of action at its best, you might even say.26 This suggests that skilled action lies within the domain of attributability. Certainly we praise athletes for their skill and treat their abilities as reflecting on them. And yet these athletes report having very little awareness, during performance, of why or how they act. They disavow being aware of the reasons that make their moves jaw-​dropping. Thus there seems to be tension between these athletes’ reports and the claim of the Consciousness Thesis (i.e., that they must be aware of their reasons for action, and in particular their right-​making reasons for action, if they are to deserve the praise we heap on them). Star athletes present a prima facie counterexample to the Consciousness Thesis. One way to dissolve this tension would be to say that star athletes’ articulacy is irrelevant. What matters is the content of their awareness during performance, regardless whether these agents can accurately report it. I agree that the content of awareness is what matters for evaluating the proposal that attributability requires consciousness of the right-​making reasons for one’s action. But articulacy is not

  Quoted in Beilock (2010, 231), who follows the quote by saying, “[Athletes like Kim] can’t tell you what they did because they don’t know themselves and end up thanking God or their mothers instead. Because these athletes operate at their best when they are not thinking about every step of performance, they find it difficult to get back inside their own heads to reflect on what they just did.” 25   Quoted in Levine (1988). 26   See Dreyfus (2002b, 2005, 2007a,b) for discussion of the idea that unreflective skilled action is action “at its best.” 24

R ef l ec tion , R e spons ib ilit y, and Frac t ured   S elve s

143

irrelevant to this question. What agents report offers a defeasible indication of their experience. Coaches’ invocations to “clear your mind” help to corroborate these reports. For example, cricketer Ken Barrington said, “When you’re playing well you don’t think about anything and run-​making comes naturally. When you’re out of form you’re conscious of needing to do things right, so you have to think first and act second. To make runs under those conditions is mighty difficult.”27 Barrington’s is not an unusual thought when it comes to giving instructions for peak performance in sports. Branch Rickey—​the Major League Baseball manager who helped break the color barrier by signing Jackie Robinson—​purportedly said that “an empty head means a full bat.”28 Sports psychologists have suggested as much too, attributing failures to perform well to overthinking, or “paralysis by analysis.” Surely some of these statements are metaphorical. Barrington’s mind is certainly active while he bats. He is presumably having experiences and focusing on something. But research on skill also appears to corroborate what star athletes report and coaches teach. One stream of research focuses on the role of attention in skilled action. Do experts attend—​or could they attend—​to what they are doing during performance? According to “explicit monitoring theory” (Beilock et al., 2002), the answer is no, because expert performance is harmed by attentional monitoring of the step-​by-​step components of one’s action (e.g., in golf, by attending to one’s backswing). Experts can’t do what they do, in other words, if they focus on what exactly they’re doing. Dual-​task experiments similarly suggest that, as one becomes more skilled in a domain, one’s tasks become less demanding of attention (Poldrack et al., 2005).29 Critics of explicit monitoring theory have pointed out that expert performance might not suffer from other forms of self-​directed attention, however. For example, David Papineau (2015) argues that experts avoid choking by focusing on their “basic actions” (i.e., what they can decide to do without having to decide to do anything else) rather than on the components of their actions. But focusing on one’s basic actions—​for example, that one is trying to score a touchdown—​isn’t the same as focusing on the right-​making features of one’s action. “Scoring a touchdown” isn’t what makes Rivers’s actions good or praiseworthy; any hack playing quarterback is also trying to score a touchdown (just as many people aim to be sociable but few display interpersonal fluency like President Obama). Awareness of these course-​ grained reasons isn’t tantamount to awareness of the right-​making features of one’s

  Quoted in Sutton (2007, 767).   Reported in “Manuel’s Lineups Varied and Successful,” http://​www.philly.com/​philly/​sports/​ phillies/​20110929_​Manuels_​lineups_​varied_​and_​successful.html. 29   Dual-​task experiments involve performing two tasks at once, one of which requires skill. People who are skilled in that domain perform better at both tasks because, the theory suggests, the skill-​ demanding task requires less attention for them. Russell Poldrack and colleagues (2005) support this interpretation with neural imaging data. 27 28

Self

144

action. Nor is it tantamount to awareness of the reasons that explain how these agents perform in such exceptionally skilled ways, which is what would be required to reconcile skilled agency with the consciousness requirement. Research on improvisational action in other domains of expertise is suggestive too. In a review of Levy (2014), Arpaly (2015) points out that improvisational jazz musicians simply don’t have enough time to attend to and deliberate about the goodness or badness of their decisions.30 Brain research seems to tell a related story. Neuroimaging studies of improvisational jazz musicians show substantial downregulation of the areas of the brain associated with judgment and evaluation when the musicians are improvising (and not when they are performing scored music; Limb and Braun, 2008). One might assume that awareness of the right-​and wrong-​making features of one’s actions is tied to evaluation and judgment. Another way to dissolve the tension between these exemplars of skill and the Consciousness Thesis might be to focus on what athletes do when they practice. Surely in practice they focus on their relevant reasons for action. Kim might adjust her grip and focus explicitly on this new technique. Indeed, she’ll have to do so until the new mechanics become automatic. So perhaps the role of right-​making reasons is indexed to past practice. Perhaps star athletes’ reasons for action have been integrated in Levy’s sense in the past, when they consciously practiced what to do. But this won’t work either. As Arpaly puts it, if it were the case that past practice entirely explains performance, then all one would need to do to become an expert performer is “work till they drop and then somehow shake their minds like a kaleidoscope” (2015, 2). But clearly this isn’t the case, as those who have practiced till they drop and still failed to perform can attest. So we are still lacking an understanding of what makes star performance distinct. It’s not the integration of reasons for action of which one was aware when practicing. (Relatedly, sometimes people exhibit expertise without ever having consciously or intentionally practiced at all. Arpaly discusses social fluency—​like Obama’s grin—​in similar terms.) Levy’s Consciousness Thesis is rich and intriguing, and represents, to my mind, the most persuasive claim on the market for a consciousness requirement for moral responsibility (and, inter alia, attributability).31 Nevertheless, barring a more persuasive alternative, I proceed in thinking that actions can reflect on agents even if those agents aren’t focally conscious of what they’re doing.   I also discuss musical improvisation in Brownstein (2014).   Levy (2016) discusses cases of skilled action like these and argues that in them agents display a kind of subpersonal control sufficient for holding them responsible. This is because, he argues, the agent displays a “patterned” sensitivity to reasons. See Chapter 4, footnote 27, for an elaboration on this claim. Levy applies this argument about patterned sensitivity to reasons to implicit attitudes, pursuing the possibility that even if agents lack conscious awareness of the moral quality of their action of the kind that renders them morally responsible for that action, perhaps they can still be held responsible because their attitudes display the right kind of patterned subpersonal control. Levy ultimately rejects both possibilities. 30 31

R ef l ec tion , R e spons ib ilit y, and Frac t ured   S elve s

145

4.3  Rational Relations Some might think that intentions and awareness are important for attributing actions to the self because intentions and awareness are reliable representatives of rational cognitive processes. Others have argued more directly that only those actions that reflect upon rational cognitive processes are attributable to agents. One prominent version of this kind of theory is Smith’s “Rational Relations View” (2005, 2008, 2012). Her view is a version of what some have called “Scanlonian” responsibility, in reference to Thomas Scanlon’s (1998) influential work. I focus on Smith’s work rather than Scanlon’s because Smith speaks directly to the challenge, for any view that understands responsible agency in terms of an agent’s rational judgments, of explaining actions that conflict with agents’ apparent judgments and beliefs. After describing Smith’s view, I’ll argue that it does not adequately explain these kinds of actions.32 The upshot is that my account of cares in Chapter 4—​as including implicit attitudes that may be functionally isolated from agents’ rational judgments—​remains unthreatened. The broader upshot is that actions that stem from states that are isolated from agents’ rational faculties can nevertheless reflect upon who those agents are. Smith understands responsibility in terms of answerability. To be clear, she does not endorse the distinction I drew earlier (§2.1) between three kinds of responsibility (attributability, answerability, and accountability). For Smith, responsibility just is answerability. The terminology can be confusing, however, because Smith takes her view to be an attributionist theory of moral responsibility. As I  understand her view, it is that actions for which we are answerable are just those actions that reflect on us as moral agents. Attributability is answerability is responsibility, in other words. Smith argues that answerability—​the ability, in principle, to answer for one’s attitudes with justifying reasons—​acts as a litmus test for determining whether that attitude stems from the agent’s evaluative—​or what she calls rational—​judgments. Your attitudes stem from rational judgments, in other words, when you can in principle be asked to defend that attitude with reasons, according to Smith. Notice that I said “attitudes” here. Smith focuses on responsibility for attitudes, not actions. On her view, then, those attitudes that stem from rational judgments can be thought of as making up a person’s responsibility-​bearing self. They do so because evaluative or rational judgments represent an agent’s reasons for holding a particular attitude. She writes, “To say that an agent is morally responsible for some thing . . . is to say that that thing reflects her rational judgment in a way that makes it appropriate, in principle, to ask her to defend or justify it” (2008, 369). As I understand the “Rational Relations View” (RRV) of responsibility as answerability, then:   Smith develops her view in terms of responsibility for attitudes, not actions per se, as discussed later. 32

Self

146

(1)  R  RV: An agent A is morally responsible for some attitude B iff B reflects A’s rational judgments about reasons for holding B. Despite the fact that Smith is focused on attitudes, RRV can be unproblematically extended to cover responsibility for actions too: (2) RRV(Action): An agent A is morally responsible for some action B iff B reflects A’s rational judgments about reasons for performing B. Moreover, RRV is also connected to a claim about what it means for an attitude to reflect upon an agent. It is incumbent upon Smith to clarify this, as one might wonder what distinguishes the focus on rational judgments in RRV from the voluntarist’s way of tying moral responsibility to an agent’s deliberative or conscious choices.33 This is important because RRV is meant as an alternative to voluntarism about moral responsibility. Smith’s tactic is to offer an expansive definition of those states that reflect our rational assessments of what we have reason to do, a definition sufficiently expansive to include deliberative and conscious choices but also desires, emotions, and mere patterns of awareness. For example, Smith writes, “Our patterns of awareness—​e.g., what we notice and neglect, and what occurs to us—​can also be said to reflect our judgments about what things are important or significant, so these responses, too, will count as things for which we are responsible on the rational relations view” (2008, 370). Sripada (pers. com.) labels Smith’s expansive definition of states that reflect an agent’s rational judgments “in principle sensitivity” (IPS). The claim of IPS is that mere patterns of awareness and the like reflect agents’ rational judgments because the psychological processes implicated in those patterns of awareness are, in principle, open to revision in light of the agent’s reason-​guided faculties. According to Smith: In order for a creature to be responsible for an attitude . . . it must be the kind of state that is open, in principle, to revision or modification through that creature’s own processes of rational reflection. States that are not even in principle answerable to a person’s judgment, therefore, would not be attributable to a person in the relevant sense. (2005, 256) As I formulate it: (1) IPS:  Some attitude B reflects agent A’s rational judgments iff B is in principle causally susceptible to revision by A’s processes of rational reflection.   I am indebted to Holly Smith’s (2011, 118, n 9) articulation of this worry.

33

R ef l ec tion , R e spons ib ilit y, and Frac t ured   S elve s

147

And for actions: (2) IPS(Action): Some action B reflects agent A’s rational judgments iff B is in principle causally susceptible to revision by A’s processes of rational reflection. IPS clarifies how one might think that agents who act spontaneously might still fall within the purview of RRV. On Smith’s view, it does not undermine attributability to show that some attitude is occurrently unresponsive to the agent’s reasoned judgments. Rather, attributability is undermined only if an attitude is in principle causally isolated from the agent’s rational reflections. What is crucial to see is how IPS saves RRV (and their correlative postulates for action) in cases of spontaneous action. It isn’t enough for Kim to say, “I don’t know how I did it,” on this view; Kim might still be answerable for her putting nonetheless. Analogously, an avowed egalitarian who behaves in some discriminatory way cannot be exculpated from responsibility simply by saying that her discriminatory behavior conflicts with what she judges she ought to do. In other words, the implicitly biased avowed egalitarian might be tempted to say, “My evaluative judgment is that discrimination is wrong; therefore, it is wrong in principle to ask me to defend what I have done, because what I have done does not reflect my evaluative judgments.” IPS(Action) cuts off this line of defense. There is something deeply intuitive about this approach. There does indeed seem to be a connection between those actions that I can rightly be asked to defend, explain, or answer for in some way and those being the actions that reflect on me. But if something like this is right—​that attributability is answerability—​then something must be wrong with the care-​based account of attributability I offered in Chapter 4. In the case of virtuous spontaneity, it makes no sense to ask President-​Elect Obama to answer for his reassuring grin or Kimberly Kim to answer for the perfection of her putts. Precisely what agents like these say is that they have no answer to the question “Why did you do that?”34 So, too, in cases of the vices of spontaneity. As Levy puts it, in the case of implicit bias “it makes no sense at all to ask me to justify my belief that p when in fact I believe that not-​p; similarly, it makes no sense to ask me to justify my implicit racism when I have spent my life attempting to eradicate it” (2011, 256). Despite its intuitive appeal, I do not think attributability should be understood as answerability in Smith’s sense. My first reason for saying this stems from cases in which it seems right to attribute an attitude or action to an agent even if that attitude or action fails to reflect her rational judgment. These are the same cases I discussed earlier (§2.1), proposed by Shoemaker (2011) and Jaworska (1999, 2007b), having

  See Brownstein (2014).

34

148

Self

to do with spider-​phobes, parents who continue to love their terrible children, Alzheimer’s patients, and young children. In reply to this kind of critique, Smith discusses the case of implicit racial bias. She shares my view that these implicit attitudes are attributable to the agent, even if they conflict with the agent’s reflective egalitarian judgment. But Smith thinks this is the case because our nonconscious “takings” and “seemings” are often, in fact, judgment-​sensitive: I think it is often the case . . . that we simply take or see certain things as counting in favor of certain attitudes without being fully aware of these reasons or the role they play in justifying our attitudes. And I think these normative “takings” or “seemings” can sometimes operate alongside more consciously formulated judgments to the effect that such considerations do not serve to justify our attitudes. So, for example, a person may hold consciously egalitarian views and yet still find herself taking the fact of a person’s race as a reason not to trust her or not to hire her. In these cases, I think an answerability demand directed toward her racist reactions still makes perfect sense—​a person’s explicitly avowed beliefs do not settle the question of what she regards as a justifying consideration. (2012, 581, n 10) I think Smith’s conclusion is right but her justification is wrong. Implicit biases like these do reflect on agents (as I  argued in the preceding chapter). But this is not necessarily because these biases are judgment-​sensitive. Why think that Smith’s vignette describes someone who takes a person’s race as a reason not to trust or hire her? Part of the problem, I think, is that Smith’s claim that attitudes that are attributable to agents must be in principle causally susceptible to revision by an agent’s processes of rational reflection (i.e., IPS) is both too vague and too strong. It is vague because it is in principle hard to tell what counts as a process of rational revision. Indeed, it is hard to see how anything at all can be ruled out as being in principle susceptible to rational revision. Suppose at some point in the future psychologists develop techniques that allow agents to overcome the gag reflex, or even to stop the beating of their own heart, using nothing but certain “mindfulness” exercises. Would this indicate that these processes, too, are in principle susceptible to rational revision? IPS is too strong because it is sometimes the case that agents can change their attitudes and behavior in such a way that seems to reflect upon them as agents, without those changes counting as responsiveness to rational pressure per se. Sometimes we do this by binding ourselves by force, like Ulysses’ tactic for resisting the Sirens. But this action is attributable to Ulysses simply because the change it wrought in his behavior traces back to his “pre-​commitment” (Elster, 2000). That is, Ulysses made

R ef l ec tion , R e spons ib ilit y, and Frac t ured   S elve s

149

a deliberative choice to instruct his crew to bind him to the mast when they were to pass the island of the Sirens. This case wouldn’t speak against Smith’s view. But there are many cases that do. I’ll call these cases of self-​regulation by indirect means.35 I discuss these in more depth in Chapter 7. Briefly though, for example, there are a slew of “evaluative conditioning” techniques that enable agents to shift the valence of their stored mental associations through repeated practice. A  person who has learned to associate “Bob” with “selfishness” and “anger” can, through training, learn to associate Bob with “charity” and “placidness,” for example. People can also shift their “statistical map” of social stereotypes by repeated exposure to counterstereotypes. One striking field study found, for example, that women undergraduates’ implicit associations between leadership and gender were significantly altered in proportion to the number of women science professors they had (i.e., women in counterstereotypic leadership roles in the sciences; Dasgupta and Asgari, 2004). At the start of the year, the students implicitly associated women with concepts related to nurturance more than with concepts related to leadership. (This is a common finding.) After one year, the women undergraduates who took more classes with women scientists more strongly associated women with leadership concepts on measures of their implicit attitudes. In these examples, there is little reason to think that agents’ implicit attitudes shift in response to rational pressure. That is, there is little reason to think that these successful cases of implicit attitude change are successful because the relevant attitudes are judgment-​sensitive, in Smith’s sense.36 Indeed, in the case of Dasgupta and Shaki Asgari’s study, while women undergraduates’ implicit attitudes changed when they took more classes from women scientists, their explicit attitudes didn’t change. Some of the women undergraduates continued to explicitly endorse the view that women possess more nurturance than leadership qualities, even after they ceased to display this association on indirect measures.

5. Conclusion In this chapter, I’ve situated my account of the relationship between implicit attitudes and the self with respect to familiar ways of thinking about attributability and responsibility. I’ve described how I  understand what it means for an action to “reflect on” the self; I’ve distinguished between being responsible and various forms of holding oneself or others responsible for actions; I’ve offered a picture of the deep self as fractured rather than necessarily unified; and I’ve explained why I think spontaneous actions can reflect on agents even when agents have no relevant   I borrow the term “indirect self-​regulation” from Jules Holroyd (2012). See also Washington and Kelly (2016) on “ecological control,” a term they borrow from Clark (2007). 36   See the discussion in Chapter 3 on implicit attitudes and rational processing, such as inference. 35

150

Self

intentions to act as they do, when they are unaware of what they are doing and why, and even when their attitudes are isolated from their rational judgments. I’ve tried to make sense of these claims in terms of both freestanding philosophical theories and research on relevant folk attitudes. Of course, arguably the most salient concerns about spontaneous and unplanned actions that arise in folk conversation are ethical concerns. How can we improve our implicit attitudes? Under what conditions can they become more morally credible? These are the questions I address in the next two chapters.

PA RT   T H R E E

ETHICS

6

Deliberation and Spontaneity

D’Cruz (2013, 37–​38) imagines the following conversation: Alfred: What shall we have for supper tonight, dear? Belinda: I have an idea: let’s forget about cooking supper and just eat ice-​cream! Alfred: But we have plenty of groceries in the fridge that we should use before they spoil. Belinda: They won’t spoil in one day. We can cook with them tomorrow. Alfred: I guess you’re right. But surely eating ice-​cream for supper isn’t good for our cholesterol levels? Belinda: But Alfred, we so rarely do such a thing. Skipping supper just once isn’t going to kill us. Alfred: I guess you’re right. But what if the kids come home and there’s no ice-​ cream left? They might be cross. Belinda: Alfred, they’ll understand when we tell them that their parents have decided to go on a little binge. They’ll probably find it quite funny. Alfred: I guess you’re right again, Belinda, all things considered. Our diet won’t be seriously compromised, the groceries won’t be wasted, and the children won’t be cross. Yes, you’re quite right. Ice-​cream for dinner it is! Belinda: Oh, Alfred, forget about it. We’ll just put in a roast and boil up some cabbage. As D’Cruz puts it, Belinda has better “instincts” for when to act on a whim, while Alfred seems overly cautious and even stultified. He acts like “a Prufrock.” By thinking so carefully about what to do, Alfred undermines Belinda’s suggestion, which at its core was to do something without thinking too carefully about it. D’Cruz’s vignette must be understood against the backdrop of a familiar and appealing idea. The idea is that deliberation is necessary and central to ethical action. By ethical action, I mean action that promotes goodness in the agent’s life,

153

154

Ethics

considered in the broadest possible terms.1 By deliberation, I  mean “bringing to mind ideas or images meant to have some rational relation to the topic being considered, in the service of reaching a conclusion about what to think or do” (Arpaly and Schroeder, 2012, 212). The appeal of the idea that deliberation is necessary and central to ethical action is reflected in Alfred’s dilemma. How can he know whether it is really a good idea to eat ice cream for dinner without thinking carefully about it? His careful consideration of the reasons for and against taking Belinda’s suggestion seems, to many people, like an obvious thing to do. He must “step back” from his immediate inclinations in order to consider them in the light of his broader goals and values. But the contrast between Alfred and Belinda appears to challenge this idea. Belinda doesn’t deliberate and seems better off for it. This suggests that, in some contexts at least, deliberation may have a limited role to play in making our spontaneous reactions more virtuous. More specifically, deliberation may be neither necessary nor always recommended for acting well.2 The aim of this chapter is to argue that this is so. I begin by arguing that deliberation cannot be foundational for action (§1). Here I  synthesize arguments made previously by Railton and by Arpaly and Timothy Schroeder. Next, I elaborate on cases in which agents appear to act ethically in spite of their deliberative reasoning (§2). People like Cecil Duly, Lapiere’s hoteliers and restaurateurs, and, most notably, Huckleberry Finn, present prima facie counterexamples to the idea that deliberation is necessary for ethical action. However, the prima facie suggestion these cases present is limited, because these agents plausibly would be better off, ethically speaking, if they were better deliberators. Cases like Huck’s show that deliberation can go awry, in other words, but not that practical deliberation, when done properly, is problematic. But I  introduce another set of cases that show that deliberation itself—​even perfect deliberation—​can undermine ethical action (§3). The considerations I introduce in my discussion of these cases apply as well to the question of how to combat the vices of spontaneity, like implicit bias. Here, too, the relationship between spontaneity and deliberation is fraught (§4). This suggests the need for a different perspective on implicit attitude 1   I will not delve into theories of what constitutes goodness in an agent’s life. All I mean by “goodness” is what appears to me to be good. For example, it appears to me that implicit attitudes that promote egalitarian social practices are good, while implicit attitudes that promote discriminatory social practices are bad. Bennett takes a similar approach in his discussion of the relationship between “sympathy” and “bad morality” (in cases like those of Huckleberry Finn). Bennett writes, “All that I can mean by a ‘bad morality’ is a morality whose principles I deeply disapprove of. When I call a morality bad, I cannot prove that mine is better; but when I here call any morality bad, I think you will agree with me that it is bad; and that is all I need” (1974, 123–​124). 2   Thus the spirit in which my argument is made is similar to that of Doris (2015), who writes, “ I insist that reflection is not necessary for, and may at times impede, the exercise of agency, while self-​ ignorance need not impede, and may at times facilitate, the exercise of agency.”

Deliberation and Spontane i t y

155

change, one not centered on deliberation. I develop this alternative framework in Chapter 7. Before moving on, however, I want to emphasize the scope of my claim. I will not argue that deliberation is useless or unimportant. For one, a lot of deliberation went into the writing of this book—​although you will have to judge to what end. And surely stepping back to evaluate one’s reasons for action, as Alfred does, is sometimes the right thing to do. More broadly, practical deliberation is ineliminably central to human experience. One may be persuaded that human beings have a great deal more in common with nonhuman animals than was previously thought (cf. de Waal, 2016), yet recognize the distinctiveness in human experience of stepping back from a situation, contemplating a suite of reasons for and against doing something, forecasting the outcomes of different decisions, discussing those hypothetical outcomes in language with others, making sophisticated inferences about combinations of likelihoods, weighting competing norms, and so on. The importance of these sorts of conceptual capacities for our identity as a species, and for ethical decision-​making, has been long emphasized, and rightly so. But this is not to say that deliberating in these ways is always the right thing to do. Deliberation can be faulty, and even when it isn’t, it can have costs. Moreover, as I argue later, even when deliberation appears to be playing a central role in guiding our decisions and behavior, things may in fact be otherwise. It is important to emphasize the background that frames this discussion. In the Western tradition at least, practical deliberation has mostly been understood as necessary for ethical action and, not infrequently, as representing the paradigmatic route to doing what we ought. There are important historical exceptions, of course. Aristotelian phronesis might be one, depending on how you interpret it. Moral sentimentalism is another. But the overwhelming emphasis otherwise has been on the importance of thinking carefully in order to act rightly. My aim is to push back against this in order to highlight the sometimes positive relationship between being spontaneous and ethical. As Arpaly put it, “A moral psychology that feeds on an unbalanced diet of examples in which people form beliefs by reflection and practical judgments by practical deliberation risks missing out on important parts of moral life” (2004, 25).

1. Nondeliberative Action My claim that deliberation is neither necessary nor always recommended for ethical action would be a nonstarter if deliberation were foundational for action. If we had to deliberate in order to act for reasons, in other words, then we would have to deliberate in order to act for ethical reasons. This idea—​that practical deliberation is necessary for action (properly so called)—​is familiar in the philosophy of action. For example, David Chan writes, “To make a reason for doing something the agent’s reason for doing it, the reason must enter into a process of practical reasoning”

156

Ethics

(1995, 140). Similarly, Peter Hacker writes, “Only a language-​using creature can reason and deliberate, weigh the conflicting claims of the facts it knows in the light of its desires, goals and values, and come to a decision to make a choice in the light of reasons” (2007, 239). But I  think deliberation is not foundational for action in this sense. Railton (2009, 2014, 2015) and Arpaly and Schroeder (2012) have convincingly argued for this view. They begin with the observation that agents often do things they have reasons to do without having to recognize or consider those reasons in deliberation. Railton argues that driving a car skillfully, producing just the right witty reply in conversation, adjusting one’s posture to suit the mood of a group, shoplifting competently, playing improvisational music, and shooting a basketball in the flow of a game are all nondeliberative reason-​responsive actions. Arpaly and Schroeder discuss examples like seeing at a glance that a reaching device can be used to grasp a banana, multiplying numbers in one’s head, passing the salt when someone says, “Pass the salt,” and knowing how and when to deliberate itself. These examples are similar to those discussed throughout this book. Railton and Arpaly and Schroeder discuss them in order to address a regress problem common to many theories of action. For Railton, the problem is with theories that attempt to identify a special act—​like choosing or endorsing one’s reasons for action—​that distinguishes either action done for reasons or autonomous action from mere behavior. For Arpaly and Schroeder, the problem is with theories that rationalize action exclusively in terms of deliberation.3 The problem for both Railton and Arpaly and Schroeder is that an action cannot be rationalized or shown to be done for reasons by another secondary act of choosing or endorsing or deliberating unless that secondary choosing, endorsing, or deliberating itself is autonomous or done for reasons. For if the secondary choosing, endorsing, or deliberating is not itself autonomous or done for reasons, it will not be capable of showing the resulting action to be autonomous or done for reasons. But whatever makes the secondary choosing, endorsing, or deliberating autonomous or done for reasons itself must be autonomous or done for reasons . . . and so on. This means that no act of past, present, or future deliberation can rationalize deliberation itself. Arpaly and Schroeder (2012, 218–​219) elaborate on this, arguing against what they call Previous Deliberation, Present Deliberation, and Possible Deliberation. Previous Deliberation holds that deliberation is responsive to reasons if it stands in an appropriate relation to a previous act of deliberation, such as antecedently resolving to act in accord with a certain principle. The trouble with this way of rationalizing deliberative action is that it succumbs to the regress problem. Each 3   Arpaly and Schroeder are more explicit than Railton about whose theories they have in mind. They identify Barry (2007), Chan (1995), Hacker (2007), Korsgaard (1997, 2009), and Tiberius (2002) as holders of the putatively mistaken view that deliberation is required for responding to reasons. They identify David Velleman’s (2000) model of practical reason as one that may avoid this problem.

Deliberation and Spontane i t y

157

previous act of deliberation, so long as it is an act, must itself be rationalized in some way. Present Deliberation holds that deliberation is responsive to reasons if, when we reach a deliberative conclusion, we also simultaneously embrace the process by which we reached that conclusion, perhaps via an act of endorsement or accept­ ance (2012, 220). This avoids a temporal regress, but succumbs to another kind of vicious regress. To deliberate at all, on this view, requires infinite acts of simultaneous deliberation. Finally, Possible Deliberation holds that deliberation is responsive to reasons if it stands in an appropriate relation to a merely possible act of deliberation, such as reasoning about what conclusion one would have reached, had one deliberated (2012, 221). Here, too, the regress problem persists, this time in the form of infinite counterfactuals that an agent would possibly have to deliberatively consider in order to act for reasons. The agent’s counterfactual reasoning about each of her deliberative acts would itself have to be counterfactually supported by other possible acts of deliberation. Railton argues that, to stop the regress, there must be “ways in which individuals could come to embrace one reason over others autonomously, but not via a further ‘full fledged’ act” (2009, 103). When one drives a car carefully, out of concern for the safety of others, it must be the case that one acts for reasons (i.e., others’ safety) without necessarily choosing or endorsing those reasons. Likewise, as a driver’s skill increases, nondeliberative habituation permits her to drive more flexibly (i.e., to respond to a broader array of reasons in diverse situations) and more self-​expressively (i.e., in a way that represents some aspect of who she is). Driving in this way is a kind of nondeliberative competence, according to Railton, comprising well-​honed affective, automatic, and nonconscious processes. It represents the exercise of what he calls “fluent agency,” which is an expression of regress-​stopping nondeliberative processes that enable individuals to respond to reasons without that responsiveness depending upon rationalization by further actions. Akin to an acquired habitus, fluent agency promotes autonomy, but not necessarily rationality.4 In some cases, on Railton’s account, fluent agency is a competence that operates independently of our rational faculties, for instance when we drive a car without having to think about what we’re doing. (Fluency permits the driver to be a better responder to driving-​related reasons, Railton argues, but not to be any more or less rational.) In other cases, fluent agency is a competence that allows us to deploy our rational faculties. When a person matches her means to her ends by picking up a letter she wishes to read and think about, she is exercising a nondeliberative competence—​matching means to ends—​which is necessary for the deployment of her rational competence—​as a reader of letters (Railton, 2009, 115). Arpaly and Schroeder similarly argue that the regress can be stopped if (in their terms) there are fundamental processes by means of which agents can think and

  See Chapter 3 for brief discussion of Bourdieu’s concept of “habitus.”

4

158

Ethics

act for reasons that are not themselves full-​fledged acts of thinking and acting for reasons. They are especially concerned to show that deliberation itself (a “mental action”) is reason-​responsive on the basis of fundamental reason-​responsive nondeliberative processes. However, they extend these arguments to cases beyond mental action, arguing that, for example, passing the salt when someone says, “Pass the salt,” is a nondeliberative reason-​responsive action that need not stand in a rationalizing relationship to other previous, present, or possible acts of deliberation. The central idea is that the act of passing the salt is rationalized, not by any deliberative act, but by a nondeliberative process that is nevertheless responsive to reasons. Such nondeliberative reason-​responsive processes are regress-​stoppers. The upshot of these arguments is that deliberation is not foundational for action. As Arpaly and Schroeder put it, “Deliberation is not the foundation of our ability to think and act for reasons but a tactic we have for enhancing our preexisting, and foundational, abilities to think and act for reasons: our ND [nondeliberative] reason-​responding” (2012, 234). If this is correct, then there should be cases in which agents’ spontaneous nondeliberative reactions get things right—​that is, seize upon the agent’s best reasons for action—​in the absence of, or even in spite of, the conclusions of their deliberative practical reasoning.

2.  Huck and Friends The examples I discussed at the beginning of Chapter 4 fit this description. Cecil Duly seems clear that, in his view, Antoine Wells deserves no better treatment than Duly had given him all along. Yet after he interacts with Wells in a new context, Duly’s unreflective treatment of Wells changes, and for the better. One can easily imagine asking Duly how he ought to treat Wells in the future and finding similar discord between his practical reasoning and his behavior. He seems likely to conclude that he ought to continue to give Wells “tough love,” but continue to treat him empathetically nevertheless. Similarly, when asked how they ought to treat Chinese customers, LaPiere’s hoteliers/​restaurateurs give the wrong answer. Yet their unreflective behavior, it seems, was more humane and unprejudiced than the results of their practical deliberation. The story of Huckleberry Finn provides the most famous illustration of this pattern. As I  said in Chapter  4, Huck fails to do what he understands to be his duty, turning in his friend Jim, the escaped slave. Huck takes seriously the idea of “property rights” and believes that Jim is Miss Watson’s property. But at the crucial moment something in Huck prevents him from turning Jim in. One way to interpret this scene is that, when Huck is faced with the moment of action, his spontaneous reaction is comparatively more egalitarian than are the explicit attitudes that figure into his deliberation. Indeed, Arpaly suggests that Huck is the inverse of an implicitly biased agent. “There are people,” she writes, “who sport liberal views but cross

Deliberation and Spontane i t y

159

the road when a person of a different race appears or feel profound disbelief when that person says something intelligible. Huckleberry, from the beginning, appears to be the mirror image of this sort of person: he is a deliberative racist and viscerally more of an egalitarian” (2004, 76). To interpret Huck this way requires two things. First, Huck’s explicit attitudes conflict with his behavior. Indeed, what seems to elude Huck, as Arpaly argues, is the belief that letting Jim go is the right thing to do. Much to the contrary, Huck explicitly believes that, because he fails to turn Jim in, he’s a wicked boy and is going to hell.5 Second, to interpret Huck this way requires that his action be a response to some kind of character-​sustaining motivation. Huck’s action-​guiding attitude must be his in such a way that it reflects well upon him. While of course Huck is fictional and many interpretations of Twain’s text are possible, there is reason to think that Huck’s motivation is praiseworthy in this sense. Contrast this with Jonathan Bennett’s (1974) interpretation. He uses the Huck Finn case to consider the relationship between what he calls “sympathy” and morality. By sympathy, Bennett seems to mean what most people today would call empathy, an emotional concern for others in virtue of their feelings and experiences. Huck’s sympathy for Jim, on Bennett’s reading, is “just a feeling,” a “natural” reaction to one’s friend, which Bennett says is irrational, given that all of Huck’s reasons suggest that he ought to turn Jim in (1974, 126, 126–​127). Bennett contrasts actions based on sympathy to actions based on reasons (whether good or bad). While I agree with Bennett’s broad view that Huck’s conscience gets it right despite his deliberation, I think Arpaly (2004) is right in pointing out that Bennett’s understanding of Huck’s conscience is too crude. For Bennett, Huck acts on the basis of some “purely atavistic mechanism,” perhaps akin, Arpaly suggests, to what Kant calls “mere inclination” (76). But Twain’s description of Huck suggests that he undergoes something more like a “perceptual shift” in his view of Jim. Arpaly writes: [The] discrepancy between Huckleberry’s conscious views and his unconscious, unconsidered views and actions widens during the time he spends with Jim. Talking to Jim about his hopes and fears and interacting with him extensively, Huckleberry constantly perceived data (never deliberated upon) that amount to the message that Jim is a person, just like him. Twain makes it very easy for Huckleberry to perceive the similarity between himself and Jim:  the two are equally ignorant, share the same language and superstitions, and all in all it does not take the genius of John Stuart Mill 5   Arpaly writes that Huck acts for good moral reasons “even though he does not know or believe that these are the right reasons. The belief that what he does is moral need not even appear in Huckleberry’s unconscious. (Contra Hursthouse 1999, my point is not simply that Huckleberry Finn does not have the belief that his action is moral on his mind while he acts, but that he does not have the belief that what he does is right anywhere in his head—​this moral insight is exactly what eludes him.)” (2004, 77).

160

Ethics

to see that there is no particular reason to think of one of them as the inferior to the other. While Huckleberry never reflects on these facts, they do prompt him to act toward Jim, more and more, in the same way he would have acted toward any other friend. That Huckleberry begins to perceive Jim as a fellow human being becomes clear when Huckleberry finds himself, to his surprise, apologizing to Jim—​an action unthinkable in a society that treats black men as something less than human. (2004, 76–​77) If this is right, then it is appropriate to say that Huck acted ethically, in a nonaccidental way, despite what he believed he ought to do. Huck’s feelings for Jim are not brute instincts, as Bennett suggests, but are instead attitudes that reflect upon Huck’s experience and perception, his behavior, and how he incorporates feedback from this behavior over time. In short, it isn’t a stretch to credit Huck’s egalitarian act to his implicit attitudes toward Jim. Huck comes to care about Jim’s personhood, it seems, and this is ethically praiseworthy, in the sense I argued in Chapters 4 and 5. His implicit attitudes don’t reflect upon how rational he is or upon how consist­ ently his conscience might be deployed in other contexts. They don’t necessarily reflect on who Huck is in a deep sense, overall. But they do reflect upon him. This suggests that in a case like Huck’s, deliberation is not necessary for genuinely ethical action (i.e., action that isn’t just accidentally good or is good in some way that doesn’t reflect on the person). However, it remains open that this may be tantamount to scant praise. It seems clear that one’s esteem for Huck would rise had he both acted rightly and recognized the rightness of his action in deliberation. In other words, we can praise Huck despite his being conflicted, while also recognizing that it would have been better had he not been conflicted. Huck isn’t good at deliberating. He fails to take into consideration a number of crucial premises, for example, that Jim is a person and that people are not property. Had Huck been a better deliberator, we might imagine him going forward in life more likely to act ethically, without having to overcome deep rending personal conflict. Similarly, in the Duly and LaPiere cases, there is no reason to think that the agents couldn’t have acted deliberatively, or wouldn’t have acted better had their deliberative judgments and nondeliberative inclinations aligned. While one might think that Duly’s increasingly kinder treatment of Wells reflects well upon him—​despite what Duly appears to believe—​one might still hold that Duly would be better off both treating Wells kindly and explicitly judging that Wells ought to be treated kindly. Similarly, LaPiere’s hoteliers/​restaurateurs would have been better off, ethically speaking, both behaving in a nondiscriminatory way and avowing to act in a nondiscriminatory way. Cases like these leave it open that deliberation, while nonfoundational for action, and perhaps not necessary in all cases for ethical action, is still always recommended. Deliberating (well) is always the best option, in other words. But other cases challenge this idea too.

Deliberation and Spontane i t y

161

3.  Costly Deliberation D’Cruz’s vignette of Alfred and Belinda is meant to illustrate a tension between deliberation and spontaneity in practical ethics. The tension is this: if there is value in acting spontaneously, it is a value that is always at risk of being undermined when one deliberates about whether or not to act spontaneously. Belinda’s rejection of Alfred’s decision represents the realization of this risk. Once Alfred has forced Belinda to deliberate about whether to eat ice cream for dinner on a lark, the idea of eating ice cream for dinner on a lark is no longer appealing. The appeal of eating ice cream for dinner was precisely its spontaneity. D’Cruz labels this the “deliberation-​volatility” of the particular class of reasons for action having to do with acting spontaneously. Agents may have “deliberation-​volatile reasons” (DVRs) to act spontaneously from time to time, but these degrade as reasons for action once the agent deliberates upon them. These reasons are volatile upon deliberation.6 If cases like Huck’s represent an existence proof of agents who can act ethically in spite of their practical deliberation, cases involving DVRs represent an existence proof of agents who ought to act nondeliberatively. DVRs, D’Cruz argues, lurk in any situation in which agents have reasons to act spontaneously. He focuses on “whim” cases. In addition to Alfred and Belinda, D’Cruz imagines Moritz, who is riding the train from Berlin to Dresden, but decides at the last second to skip his stop and ride to Zittau, despite thinking that he probably should get off in order to stick to his plans in Dresden. “As the train starts, [Moritz] feels an overwhelming euphoria come over him,” D’Cruz writes, “a powerful sensation of freedom that, in retrospect, easily outweighs his other reasons for going to Dresden” (2013, 33). Moritz has good reasons for skipping his stop, assuming that feeling free and euphoric contribute to Moritz’s desire to lead a good and happy life. But, D’Cruz asks, consider the outcome had Moritz deliberated about this choice. He might have thought, “If I continue to Zittau, I will feel an overwhelming sense of euphoria and freedom.” Had Moritz contemplated this conditional, he would have rendered it false.7 This 6   See also Slingerland (2014) for extended discussion of what he calls the “paradox of wu wei”—​ which is effectively the paradox of trying to be spontaneous—​in classical Chinese ethics. 7   Borderline cases are possible. Moritz might deliberate about continuing to Zittau, decide to do it, and still feel some degree of euphoria and freedom. Rather than rendering the conditional “If I continue to Zittau, I will feel an overwhelming sense of euphoria and freedom” categorically false, perhaps deliberating upon it only renders it much more likely to be false. Or perhaps deliberating upon the conditional will diminish the strength of Moritz’s feelings of euphoria and freedom. Speculatively, it seems to me that what matters is whether one makes a decision before one’s process of deliberation has concluded, from one’s own perspective. If Moritz briefly considers the conditional, but then just decides to head to Zittau before considering its implications or its weight in light of other considerations—​a “what the hell” moment, in other words—​it seems likely that he will experience the euphoria and freedom associated with acting spontaneously. If, however, he considers the conditional sufficiently to feel confident or settled in making a deliberative decision, then I suspect he will not experience the euphoria and freedom associated with acting spontaneously.

Ethics

162

is because, presumably, Moritz’s euphoria was tied to the spontaneity of his decision. The more that Moritz engages in deliberative practical reasoning about what to do, the less he has reason to continue to Zittau. Of course, Moritz doesn’t have reasons to create a policy of skipping his stop regularly, just as Alfred and Belinda don’t have reasons to eat ice cream for dinner every night. Indeed, doing so would be another way of undermining the spontaneity of these decisions. But in these particular cases, agents have positive reasons to act nondeliberatively. There is no reason Huck, Duly, or LaPiere’s hoteliers/​restaurateurs wouldn’t have been better off, ethically, had they been better deliberators and acted on the basis of their practical deliberation. But this isn’t the case with Alfred and Belinda, or in any case involving DVRs. Alfred’s problem is not that he should be a better deliberator.8 His problem—​the thing preventing him from acting spontaneously in a way that he himself would value—​is his very need to deliberate. In other words, just in virtue of deliberatively considering whether to make a spontaneous choice to eat ice cream for dinner, Alfred no longer has reasons to spontaneously choose to eat ice cream for dinner. DVR cases show that deliberation can have costs. And sometimes these costs tip the scales in favor of not deliberating. The fact that deliberation can have costs in this sense suggests that, in some contexts at least, deliberation can undermine ethical action. Moreover, the contexts in which deliberation can undermine ethical action are not rare. The relevant context is not limited to cases of acting on a whim, as Belinda and Moritz do. In some cases, it simply isn’t feasible to deliberate, and thus one’s goals are instrumentally supported by acting nondeliberatively.9 One reason for this is that real time interaction does not offer agents the time required to deliberate about what to say or do, and trying to deliberate in such circumstances is counterproductive. This is evident when you think of a witty comeback to an insult, but only once it’s too late. Unfortunately, most of us don’t have Oscar Wilde’s spontaneous wit. (Fortunately, most of us also don’t have the same doggedness that motivated George Costanza to fly to Ohio to deliver a good comeback.) To be witty requires rapid and fluent assessments of the right thing to say in the moment. In addition to time pressure, social action inevitably relies upon nondeliberative reactions because explicit thinking exhausts us. We are simply not efficient enough users of cognitive resources to reflectively check our spontaneous actions and reactions all the time. Beyond the feasibility problem of acting deliberatively in cases like these, there are many cases in which agents’ nondeliberative reactions and dispositions are particularly well suited to the situation. The research on expertise in athletics discussed in Chapter 5 provides one set of examples. On the tennis court, it is not just difficult   See D’Cruz (2013, 35).   For this “feasibility argument,” I  am indebted to Gendler “Moral Psychology for People with Brains.” 8 9

Deliberation and Spontane i t y

163

to think deliberatively about which shots to play while playing. The best players are those who seem to have the best spontaneous inclinations; the flexibility and situation-​specific responsiveness of their impulses is a positive phenomenon.10 That is, like Belinda, their spontaneous reactions are getting it right, and there is no reason to think that they, like Huck, would be better off were these reactions supported by deliberative reasoning. Athletes who reflect on the reasons for their actions while playing sometimes end up like Alfred, destroying those very reasons. (Of course, in a wider slice of time, athletes do analyze their play, when they practice. I’ll argue later that this doesn’t undermine the claim that deliberation is costly in sports, nor does it undermine the broader claim that examples like these show that deliberation can undermine ethical action.) The same can be said of particular elements of social skill. The minor social actions and reactions explained by our implicit attitudes often promote positive and prosocial outcomes when they are spontaneously and fluently executed. Hagop Sarkissian describes some of the ways in which these seemingly minor gestures can have major ethical payoffs: For example, verbal tone can sometimes outstrip verbal content in affecting how others interpret verbal expressions (Argyle et al. 1971); a slightly negative tone of voice can significantly shift how others judge the friendliness of one’s statements, even when the content of those statements are judged as polite (Laplante & Ambady 2003). In game-​theoretic situations with real financial stakes, smiling can positively affect levels of trust among strangers, leading to increased cooperation (Scharlemann et  al. 2001). Other subtle cues, such as winks and handshakes, can enable individuals to trust one another and coordinate their efforts to maximize payoffs while pursuing riskier strategies (Manzini et al. 2009). (2010b, 10)11 Here, too, nondeliberative action is a positive phenomenon. It is not just that since deliberation is not feasible in real-​time action, we must make do with the second-​best alternative of relying upon our nondeliberative faculties. Rather, in cases of social fluency, like athletic expertise, agents’ nondeliberative inclinations generate praiseworthy outcomes, outcomes that could be undermined by deliberation. A smile that reads as calculated or intentional—​a so-​called Pan Am smile—​is less likely than a genuine—​or Duchenne smile—​to positively affect levels of trust among strangers. Here it seems that it is the very spontaneity of the Duchenne smile—​precisely that it is not a product of explicit thinking—​that we value. Supporting this, research suggests that people value ethically positive actions more highly when those actions   But see Montero (2010) for discussion of particular sports and arts in which this is not the case.   W hile I endorse giving others kind smiles and meaningful handshakes, I think one should probably avoid winking at strangers. 10 11

164

Ethics

are performed spontaneously rather than deliberatively (Critcher et  al., 2013). (However, perhaps as in the case of athletic expertise, the role of deliberation in social fluency is indexed to past practice, as discussed later.) Well-​known thought experiments in philosophy can illustrate this idea too. Bernard Williams’s suggestion that it is better to save one’s drowning spouse unhesitatingly than to do so accompanied by the deliberative consideration that in situations like this saving one’s spouse is morally required illustrates the same point. Williams’s point isn’t that deliberating interferes with right action by distracting or delaying you. Rather, it’s that the deliberative consideration adds “one thought too many” (1981, 18).12 Your spouse desires that you rescue him or her without your needing to consult your moral values.13 Spontaneity has distinctive value in all of these cases, from conversational wit to athletic expertise to social fluency to ethical actions that are necessarily nondeliberative. Deliberating in real time, when one is in the flow of decision-​making, threatens to undermine one’s practical success in all of these cases. Conversational wit is undermined by deliberation in the moment, as is athletic improvisation, social fluency, and so on. To the extent that people have reasons to be witty, or to excel in high-​speed sports, or to promote trust and cooperation through verbal tone and smiling, they will undermine these very reasons by deliberating upon them. Of course, in many cases, we contemplate and consider what to do in situations like these ahead of time. Arguably the sharpest wits—​stand-​up comics—​spend a lifetime contemplating those nuances of social life that ultimately make up their professional material. Likewise, expert athletes train for thousands of hours, and much of their training involves listening to and considering the advice of their coaches. So it is not as if deliberation plays no role in these cases. Rather, it seems to play a crucial role in the agents’ past, in shaping and honing their implicit attitudes. This seems to suggest that deliberation is indeed recommended in promoting and improving virtuous implicit attitudes. It is just that the role it plays is indexed to the agent’s past. It is important to note that this is not inconsistent with Railton’s and Arpaly and Schroeder’s critique of Previous Deliberation (§1). Their point is that past instances of deliberation cannot solve the regress problem of rationalizing 12   Bernard Williams makes this point in arguing against consequentialist forms of ethics, but the idea can be broadened. 13   Or consider the key scene in the film Force Majeure. What appears to be an avalanche is rushing toward a family. The father keeps his cool . . . until he panics and flees the oncoming rush, grabbing his cell phone on the way but abandoning his family. The avalanche turns out to be a mirage, but this takes nothing away from what was his quite reasonable terror. Of course, what was not reasonable was his abandonment of his wife and small children. Surely his problem wasn’t a failure to deliberate clearly about what to do, but rather that he acted like a coward in a situation demanding spontaneity. The rest of the film grapples with his inability to admit what he did, but also with what his cowardly spontaneous reaction says about him as a person. All of this makes sense, I think, only within the framework of thinking that his nondeliberative reaction itself should have been better.

Deliberation and Spontane i t y

165

action. To reiterate, this is because one cannot claim that a present nondeliberative action is an action as such just because the agent contemplated her reasons for it at some point in the past, because that act of past deliberation itself stands in need of rationalizing. The point of this argument is to show that agents can—​indeed, must—​act for reasons nondeliberatively. But this claim about the nature of action does not provide normative guidance about what agents ought to do, that is, when they should or shouldn’t deliberate. As such, it is consistent with the argument against Previous Deliberation that agents ought to cultivate their implicit attitudes by reflecting on them in various ways ahead of time, in the ostensible manner of comics and athletes and so on. We should hesitate to accept the idea that deliberation is always normative even if it is indexed to the past, however. One reason for this is that there are some cases in which agents act excellently and nondeliberatively without having had any sort of training or preparation. Heroes, for example, often “just react” to the situation, and do so without having deliberated about what to do at any time in the present or the past. Wesley Autrey (Chapter 1)—​the “Subway Hero” who saved the life of an epileptic man who had fallen onto some subway tracks, by holding him down while a train passed just inches overhead—​didn’t credit his decision to any deliberative act or explicit forethought, but rather to his experience working construction in confined spaces (such that he could snap-​judge that he would have enough room for the train to pass overhead).14 Cases of social fluency often have this form too. As I argued about Obama’s grin (Chapters 2 and 5), it is unlikely that any intentional efforts in the past to practice reassuring gestures like this explain the fluency of his act. Such efforts are usually woefully underspecific. They fail to distinguish those with and without the relevant fluency (just as I said, in Chapter 4, that expert athletes’ thousands of hours of intentional practice don’t distinguish them from inexpert athletes who have practiced for thousands of hours too). There is also reason to question the role past deliberation plays in shaping one’s implicit attitudes even in those cases in which agents do train for and practice what they do. Expert athletes learn from their coaches and plausibly deliberate about what their coaches teach them, but it’s not clear that what they learn is a product of what they deliberate about or conceptualize. For example, in many ball sports, like baseball, tennis, and cricket, athletes are taught to play by “watching the ball” or “keeping their eye on the ball.” This instruction serves several purposes. Focusing on the ball can help players to pick up nuances in the angle and spin of the incoming serve or pitch; it can help players keep their head still, which is particularly important in sports like tennis, where one has to meet the ball with one’s racquet at a precise angle while one’s body is in full motion; and it can help players avoid distractions. One thing that attempting to “watch the ball” does not do, however, is

  See http://​en.wikipedia.org/​wiki/​Wesley_​Autrey.

14

166

Ethics

cause players to actually visually track the ball from the point of release (in baseball or cricket), or opponent contact (in tennis), to the point of contact with one’s own bat or racquet. In fact, it is well established that ball players at any level of skill make anticipatory saccades to shift their gaze ahead of the ball one or more times during the course of its flight toward them (Bahill and LaRitz, 1984; McLeod, 1987; Land and McLeod, 2000). These saccades—​the shifting of the eye gaze in front of the ball—​occur despite the fact that most players (at least explicitly) believe that they are visually tracking the ball the whole time.15 Moreover, it seems clear that a batter who does have an accurate understanding of what she does when she watches the ball, and attempts to put this understanding into action as a result of practical deliberation, won’t necessarily be any better off than the ordinary batter who falsely understands what she does when she intends to watch the ball. The batter with the accurate belief might even be worse off. The point isn’t that batters can’t articulate their understanding of what they do while playing. The point is that the best available interpretation of batters’ skill posits well-​honed implicit attitudes to explain their ability, not true beliefs about what to do (as I argued in Chapter 3). These implicit attitudes generate dispositions to respond to myriad circumstances in spontaneous and skillful ways. Good coaches are ingenious in identifying ways to inculcate these attitudes. Of course, this tutelage involves explicit instruction. But as in the case of watching the ball, explicit instruction may achieve its goal not via the force of the meaning of the instruction itself. In tennis, the coach might say, “Think about placing your serve in the outermost square foot of the service box,” but effectively what this might do is cause the player to unconsciously rotate her shoulders outwardly while serving. While these are very specific examples, broader theories of skill learning tend to emphasize observation rather than instruction. Consider research on how children learn to manipulate objects given their goals. Showing them various toys, Daphna Buchsbaum and colleagues (2010) told four-​year-​olds, “This is my new toy. I know

15   In fact, David Mann et al. (2007) show that skilled cricketers suffer little to no loss in their batting abilities even when they are wearing misprescribed contact lenses that render the batters’ eyesight on the border of legal blindness (although one must note the small sample size used in this study). Research suggests that visual information in these contexts is processed in the largely unconscious dorsal visual stream (see Chapter 2, footnote 13). For an extensive analysis of the watching-​the-​ball example, see Brownstein and Michaelson (2016) and Papineau (2015). Recall (from Chapter 4) that Papineau argues that athletes in these contexts must hold in mind an intention to perform what he calls a “basic action.” Basic actions are, on his view, actions that you know how to do and can decide to do without deciding anything else. For example, a batter might hold the intention in mind to “hit defensively.” The batter need not—​and ought not—​focus on how to hit defensively. Focusing in this way on the components of a basic action can cause what Papineau calls the “yips.” But failing to keep the right intention in mind causes what Papineau calls “choking.” Distinguishing between choking and the yips in this way is useful, but the concern I just discussed remains so long as there is the possibility of the agent’s intentions to perform basic actions being confabulated.

Deliberation and Spontane i t y

167

it plays music, but I haven’t played with it yet, so I don’t know how to make it go. I thought we could try some things to see if we can figure out what makes it play music.” The experimenters then showed the children various sequences of actions, like shaking the toy, knocking it, and rolling it. Following a pattern, sometimes the toy played music and sometimes it didn’t. Sometimes this pattern included all the actions the experimenter performed, but sometimes it didn’t. When given their turn to make the toy play music, the children didn’t simply imitate what the experimenter did. Rather, they made decisions about which parts of the sequence to imitate. These decisions reflected statistical encoding of the effective patterns for making the toy work. However, in a second experiment, the experimenter told another group of children, “See this toy? This is my toy, and it plays music. I’m going to show you how it works. I’ll show you some things that make it play music and some things that don’t make it play music, so you can see how it works.” In this pedagogical (vs. comparatively nonpedagogical) context, the children “overimitated” the experimenter. They did just what the experimenter did, including needless actions, thus ignoring statistical information. As a result, they were less effective learners. As Alison Gopnik (2016), one of the coauthors of the study put it, summarizing this and other research, “It’s not just that young children don’t need to be taught in order to learn. In fact, studies show that explicit instruction . . . can be limiting.” As with my argument about deliberation writ large, my point here is not that explicit instruction is always counterproductive to skill learning. Rather, my argument is that it is harder than it seems to explain away cases of nondeliberative skill by indexing those skills to past acts of deliberative learning.

4.  Deliberation, Bias, and Self-​Improvement The case for the necessity and warrant for deliberating in order to act both spontaneously and ethically is perhaps strongest when one turns to consider the vices of implicit attitudes. For example, surely one must reflect on the wrongs of racism and inequality in order to overcome one’s implicit biases. Deliberation can help us to calibrate the goals that activate particular implicit attitudes in particular situations to our long-​term reflective goals (Moskowitz and Li, 2011; see also Chapter  2). Deliberation also seems crucial for recognizing when the statistical regularities in the environment that reinforce our implicit attitudes are themselves reflective of inequalities and unjust social arrangements (Railton, 2014; Huebner, 2016). And discussing the wrongs of discrimination does seem to help promote implicit attitude change (Devine et al., 2012). Thinking carefully about our spontaneous inclinations seems crucial for making them more virtuous in other contexts too. Understanding and contemplating the problems that stem from confirmation bias and attribution errors and so on—​these and all the other problems associated with spontaneous and impulsive

168

Ethics

thinking—​seem essential for avoiding them. Indeed, arguably the most widely practiced and seemingly effective techniques for habit change and overcoming unwanted impulses focus on critical self-​reflection. I have in mind versions of cognitive-​behavioral therapy (CBT), which are standardly understood in terms of encouraging agents to consciously and explicitly revise the ways in which they make sense of their own habitual thoughts, feelings, and actions. CBT strategies teach agents how to replace their unwanted or maladaptive cognitive, affective, and behavioral patterns with patterns that match their reflectively endorsed goals. This process of recognition and replacement is thoroughly deliberative, or so it is argued. Indeed, it has been compared by its practitioners to an inwardly focused process of Socratic questioning (Neenan and Dryden, 2005; Beck, 2011). Nevertheless, I now want to point out important ways in which deliberation can distract from and even undermine the fight against unwanted implicit attitudes. One way in which deliberation can be distracting in combating unwanted implicit attitudes is by simply wasting time. For example, cognitive therapies are very common for treating phobias and anxiety disorders, in particular in conjunction with various exposure therapies. But reviews of the literature show that they provide little, if any, added benefit to exposure therapies alone (Wolitzky-​Taylor et al., 2008; Hood and Antony, 2012). Moreover, consider one of the most striking demonstrations of effective treatment for spider phobia (Soeter and Kindt, 2015). First, spider-​fearful participants were instructed to approach an open-​caged tarantula. They were led to believe that they were going to have to touch the tarantula and, just before touching it, were asked to rate their level of fear. The point of this was to reactivate the participants’ fearful memories of spiders. After reporting their feelings, the cage was closed (i.e., they didn’t have to touch the spider). A  treatment group was then given 40 mg of the beta blocker propranolol. (One control group was given a placebo; another was given the propranolol but did not have the encounter with the tarantula.) Beta blockers are known to disrupt the reconsolidation of fear memories while leaving expectancy learning unaffected. After taking the beta blocker, the participants’ approach behavior toward spiders was measured four times, from four days post-​treatment to one year post-​treatment. Treatment “transformed avoidance behavior into approach behavior in a virtual binary fashion,” the authors write, and the effect lasted the full year after treatment (Soeter and Kindt, 2015, 880). All participants in the treatment group touched a tarantula four days after treatment, while participants in the control groups were barely willing to touch the tarantula’s cage. Moreover, and most relevant to the effectiveness of deliberatively considering one’s unwanted thoughts and feelings, participants in the treatment condition reported an unchanged degree of fear of spiders after treatment, despite these dramatic changes in their behavior. Eventually, three months later, their self-​reported fear “caught up” with the changes in their behavior. The authors conclude, “Our findings are in sharp contrast with the current pharmacological and cognitive behavioral treatments for anxiety and related disorders. The β-​adrenergic

Deliberation and Spontane i t y

169

blocker was only effective when the drug was administered upon memory reactivation, and a modification in cognitive representations was not necessary to observe a change in fear behavior” (2015, 880).16 In a more general context, it is hard to tell when deliberative self-​criticism and reflection are doing the work of changing one’s attitudes and behavior and when it just seems so. This is often the case with cognitive therapies. Despite its practitioners’ understanding of CBT’s mechanisms for bringing about attitude and behavioral change, there are reasons to think that CBT is effective for quite different reasons. One point of concern about theorists’ understanding of how CBT works has to do with the accuracy of introspection. The theory of CBT assumes that people can accurately introspect the maladaptive thoughts that drive their behavior. This identification is putatively accomplished through a process of introspective Socratic questioning (i.e., Socratic questioning of oneself, guided by the CBT practitioner). But, of course, people are not always (or often) good at identifying through introspection the thoughts that explain and cause their behavior. This is because most of our thoughts are not encoded in long-​term, episodic memory. Instead, as Garson Leder (2016) points out in a critique of the dominant interpretation of how CBT works, usually people rely upon theory-​guided reconstructions when trying to understand their own past experiences and thoughts (e.g., Nisbett and Wilson, 1977). Dominant theories of CBT require that people identify the actual past thoughts that explain their current feelings and behavior, not just past thoughts that could coherently make sense of their current feelings and behavior.17 But the reality of how memory works—​as is in evidence in the large confabulation literature, for example (as discussed later)—​suggests that this is simply not feasible most of the time. Alternatively, it is possible that CBT works through associative processes. Patients might simply be counterconditioning their associations between particular thoughts and particular feelings and behavior by rehearsing desirable thoughts in conjunction with desirable outcomes. A similar pattern may be at work in some cases of interventions for implicit bias. Some research suggests that persuasive arguments effectively shift implicit attitudes.18 If this is so, then it seems to follow that deliberating about the contents of 16   Another reason this experiment is striking is that propranolol has also been used effectively to diminish anti-​black bias on the black–​white race IAT (Terbeck et al., 2012). This is suggestive of possibilities for future research on interventions to combat implicit bias, whether involving beta blockers or other fear-​reconditioning approaches. Such interventions may represent a “physical stance” of the kind I describe in Chapter 7. They may also supplement the role of rote practice in implicit attitude change, also described in Chapter 7. 17   Alternatively, patients are encouraged to “catch” and record snippets of their inner monologue in particular and problematic situations. It is similarly unclear if doing this—​accurately recording parts of one’s inner monologue—​is actually what’s responsible for the salutary effects of CBT. 18   See Richeson and Nussbaum (2004), Gregg et  al. (2006), and Briñol et  al. (2009). See also Chapter 3.

Ethics

170

one’s implicit attitudes is likely to be an effective way of changing them. The connection here is that deliberation is the usual means by which we evaluate and appreciate the strength of an argument. In deliberation, we try to infer sound conclusions from premises and so on. So evidence showing that persuasive arguments change implicit biases would seem to be good evidence in turn that deliberation is effective in combating unwanted implicit biases. Pablo Briñol and colleagues (2009) compared the effects on an IAT of reading strong versus weak arguments for the hiring of black professors at universities. One group of research participants learned that hiring more black professors has been shown to increase the quality of teaching on campus—​a strong argument—​ while the other group was told that hiring more black professors was trendy—​a weak argument. Only participants in the strong argument condition had more positive implicit attitudes toward blacks after intervention. Mandelbaum (2015b) cites this study as evidence supporting his propositional account of implicit attitudes (Chapter 3). The reason he does so is that, on his interpretation, the implicit attitudes of the participants in the strong-​argument condition processed information in an inferentially sound way. If this is right, it suggests that people ought to deliberate about reasons to be unbiased, with the expectation that doing so will ameliorate their implicit biases. But as in the case of CBT, it is unclear exactly why argument strength affects implicit attitudes. As Levy (2014) points out, to show that implicit attitudes are sensitive to inferential processing, it is not enough to measure implicit attitudes toward φ, demonstrate that agents make a relevant set of inferences about φ, and then again measure agents’ implicit attitudes toward φ. It could be, for instance, that the persuasive arguments make the discrepancy between agents’ implicit and explicit attitudes salient, that agents find this discrepancy aversive, and that their implicit attitudes shift in response to these negative feelings (Levy, 2014, 12).19 In this case, implicit attitudes wouldn’t be changing on the basis of the logical force of good arguments. Rather, they would be changing because the agent feels bad. In fact, Briñol and colleagues have explored the mechanisms underlying the effects of persuasive arguments on implicit attitude change. They suggest that what drives the effect is simply the net valence of positive versus negative thoughts that the study participants have. It’s not the logical force of argument, in other words, but rather that positive arguments have positive associations. They write, “The strong message led to many favorable thoughts . . . the generation of each positive (negative) thought provides people with the opportunity to rehearse a favorable (unfavorable) evaluation of blacks, and it is the rehearsal of the evaluation allowed by the thoughts

  Although there may be reasons to doubt this interpretation. As Madva points out (pers. com.), the common finding in the literature is that making people conscious of their implicit biases—​or making those attitudes salient—​tends to amplify rather than diminish bias on indirect measures. 19

Deliberation and Spontane i t y

171

(not the thoughts directly) that are responsible for the effects on the implicit measure” (2009, 295, emphasis added). This is consistent with what I suggested about the possible mechanisms driving the effects of CBT, namely, that agents are counterconditioning their associations between particular thoughts and particular feelings and behavior. If this is what’s happening in Briñol and colleagues’ study, then the right conclusion might not be that agents ought to deliberate about persuasive reasons to be unbiased. It might be more effective to simply make people feel bad about being biased.20 (I’m not arguing that we should make people feel bad about their implicit biases. In the next chapter I canvass various nondeliberative tactics for improving the virtuousness of implicit attitudes.) Recent developments in multinomial modeling of performance on indirect measures of attitudes can help to uncover the particular processes underlying implicit attitude change. The Quadruple Process Model (Quad Model; Conrey et al., 2005), for instance, is a statistical technique for distinguishing the uncontrollable activation of implicit associations from effortful control over activated associations. If persuasive arguments really do effectuate changes within implicit attitudes themselves, rather than by amplifying aversive feelings (or by some other means), the Quad Model would (in principle) demonstrate this by showing changes in the activation of associations themselves rather than heightened effortful control. Unfortunately, this particular analysis has not been done.21 The Quad Model has been used, however, to analyze the processes underlying other implicit attitude change interventions. Thus far, it appears that interventions that change the activation of implicit associations themselves—​in the context of implicit racial biases—​include retraining approach and avoid tendencies toward members of stigmatized racial groups (Kawakami et  al., 2007b, 2008), reconditioning the valence of race-​related stimuli (Olson and Fazio, 2006), and increasing individuals’ exposure to images, film clips, or even mental imagery depicting members of stigmatized groups acting in stereotype-​discordant ways (Blair et  al., 2001; Dasgupta and Greenwald, 2001; Weisbuch et al., 2009). What’s notable about this list of interventions—​all of which I discuss in more depth in the next chapter—​is its striking dissimilarity to reasoned persuasion. These techniques seem to operate via retraining and counterconditioning, not deliberation. In other cases, conscious and seemingly deliberative efforts to be unbiased can actually make implicit biases worse. The problem here—​as previously discussed—​ is that deliberation requires effortful attention, and self-​directed effortful attention is cognitively depleting. The effect of cognitive depletion is then sometimes more biased behavior (in addition to other unwanted behaviors, such as outbursts of   For detailed discussion of Briñol and colleagues’ research and its bearing on questions about the nature of implicit attitudes, see Madva (2016b). 21   So far as I know; see Madva (2017). 20

172

Ethics

anger).22 Evan Apfelbaum and colleagues (2008) show that agents’ tendencies to avoid talking about race in interracial interactions predict negative nonverbal behaviors. People who are “strategically color-​blind,” in other words, tend to demonstrate more negative race-​based micro-​behaviors. Moreover, Apfelbaum and colleagues find that this relationship is mediated by a decreased capacity to exert self-​control. This finding is consistent with a cognitive depletion explanation of this phenomenon. One’s resources for controlling one’s biases through effortful and conscious control become temporarily spent, thus leading to more biased behavior.23 When we move beyond a narrow focus on implicit bias, we see not only that deliberation sometimes has problematic consequences, but also that deliberation itself can be subject to biases and shortcomings. The order in which we contemplate questions or premises, the vivacity with which a moral dilemma is posed, the framing of a policy as an act or an omission—​all of these dramatically affect the judgments we make when deliberating. Perhaps nowhere are the vulnerabilities of deliberation clearest, though, than in the confabulation literature. Nisbett and Wilson’s (1977) classic paper, “Telling More than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes,” instantiated a surge of studies demonstrating the frequent gulf between the contents of our mental deliberations and the actual reasons for our actions. Nisbett and Wilson’s findings pertained to the “position effect” on the evaluation of consumer goods. When asked to rate the quality of four nightgowns or four pairs of pantyhose, which were laid out in a line, participants routinely preferred the rightmost item. This was a dramatic effect; in the case of pantyhose, participants preferred the pair on the right to the other pairs by a factor of 4 to 1. The trick was that all the nightgowns and pantyhose were identical. Moreover, none of the participants reported that they preferred the items on the right because they were on the right. Instead, they confabulated reasons for their choices. Even more dramatic effects have since been found. The research of Petter Johansson and colleagues (2005) on choice blindness demonstrated that people offer introspectively derived reasons for choices that they didn’t even make. This was shown using a double-​card ploy, in which participants are asked to state which of two faces shown in photographs is more attractive and then to give reasons for their preference. The ploy is that, unbeknownst to participants, the cards are switched after they state their preference but before they explain their choice. Johansson and colleagues 22   For cognitive depletion and anger, see Stucke and Baumeister (2006) and Gal and Liu (2011). For cognitive depletion and implicit bias, see Richeson and Shelton (2003) and Govorun and Payne (2006), in addition to Apfelbaum et al. (2008), discussed here. A recent meta-​analysis of the ego depletion literature (Hagger et al., 2016) may complicate these claims, but I am unaware of any failures to replicate these specific studies. For detailed discussion of this meta-​analysis and of effect sizes and replication efforts in the ego depletion literature, see http://​soccco.uni-​koeln.de/​cscm-​2016-​debate. html. See also my brief discussion in the Appendix. 23   Although other factors are surely in play when agents attempt to “not see” race. A difficulty taking the perspective of others is a likely factor, for example. Thanks to Lacey Davidson for this suggestion.

Deliberation and Spontane i t y

173

found that participants failed to detect the fact that they were giving reasons for preferring the face that they did not in fact prefer 74% of the time. This includes trials in which participants were given as much time as they wanted to deliberate about their choice as well as trials in which the face pairs were highly dissimilar.24 Studies like these make it hard to argue straightforwardly that thinking more carefully and self-​critically about our unwanted implicit attitudes is always the optimal solution for improving them. If there is often a gulf between the reasons for which we act and the reasons upon which we deliberate, as studies like these suggest, then deliberation upon our reasons for action is likely to change our behavior or attitudes in only a limited way. Further evidence still for this is found in studies that examine the judgments and behavior of putative exemplars of deliberation. Consider, for example, research on what Dan Kahan and colleagues (2017) call “motivated numeracy.” Numeracy is a scale used to measure a person’s tendency to engage in quantitative reasoning and to do so reflectively and systematically in order to make valid inferences. Kahan and colleagues told one set of participants about a study examining the effects of a new cream developed for treating skin rashes. The participants were given basic data from four conditions of the fictitious study (in a 2 × 2 contingency table): how many patients were given the cream and improved; how many were given the cream and got worse; how many were not given the cream and improved; and how many were not given the cream and got worse. The participants were then asked whether the study supported the conclusion that people who used the cream were more likely to get better or to get worse than those who didn’t use the cream. This isn’t an easy question, as it involves comparing the ratios of those who experienced different outcomes. Unsurprisingly, 59% of participants (across conditions) gave the wrong answer. Also unsurprisingly, and confirming extensive previous research, was that the participants’ numeracy scores predicted their success: 75% of those in the 90th percentile and above gave the right answer. In a second condition, Kahan and colleagues presented the participants with the same data, except that instead of presenting them as the results of a medical study on skin cream, they presented the data as the results of a study on the effects of gun-​control laws  on  crime  rates. The same 2 × 2 table was presented, this time showing how many cities had enacted gun-​control measures and crime increased; how many cities had enacted gun-​control measures and crime decreased; how many cities had not enacted gun-​control measures and crime increased; and how many cities had not enacted gun-​control measures and crime decreased. And 24   I note the general gendered creepiness of the research prompts used in these studies. One wonders why Nisbett and Wilson chose nightgowns and pantyhose, rather than, say, belts and aftershave. Was it a presumption that women are more likely to confabulate than men? One also wonders why Johansson and colleagues had participants rate the attractiveness of photographs of women only. Are men not fitting subjects for evaluation as objects of attraction?

Ethics

174

the participants were then asked to indicate whether “cities that enacted a ban on carrying concealed handguns were more likely to have a decrease in crime . . . or an increase in crime than cities without bans” (Kahan et al., 2007, 63). Here, too, Kahan and colleagues confirmed mountains of previous research, except that in this condition the unsurprising finding had to do with motivated reasoning. Participants’ political attitudes affected their evaluations of the implications of the data. In the gun-​control condition, but not in the skin-​cream condition, liberals increasingly identified the right answer when the right answer (given the fictitious data) was that gun-​control measures decrease crime, and conservatives increasingly identified the right answer when the right answer was that gun-​control measures increase crime.25 What’s striking about this study is a third finding, which builds upon these two unsurprising effects (i.e., that higher numeracy predicts participants’ quantitative reasoning and that people engage in motivated reasoning when they are evaluating something that holds political, social, or moral meaning for them). The third finding was that higher numeracy predicted participants’ performance only in the gun-​control condition when the correct response was congenial to their political outlooks. Higher numeracy didn’t protect participants from motivated reasoning, in other words. In fact—​and this is what’s really striking—​motivated reasoning increased dramatically in more numerate participants. Kahan and colleagues report: On average, the high-numeracy partisans whose political outlooks were affirmed by the data, when  properly interpreted, was 45% more likely (±14%, LC = 0.95) to identify the conclusion actually supported by the gun ban experiment than were the high numeracy partisans whose political outlooks were affirmed by selecting the incorrect response. The average difference in the case of low numeracy partisans was 25%  points (±10%)—​a difference of 20% (±16%) (2017, 72). This suggests that people who are better at quantitative reasoning are more likely to engage in motivated reasoning than people who are worse at quantitative reasoning. Kahan and colleagues suggest that this is because more numerate individuals have a cognitive ability that they use opportunistically to sustain identity-​protective beliefs. They are better at reasoning toward false conclusions, in other words, in order to confirm their antecedent beliefs.26

  Within each condition, half of the participants were given data that supported the inference that the skin cream/​gun-​measure improves/​increases the rash/​crime, and the other half were given data that supported the inference that the skin cream/​gun-​measure worsens/​decreases the rash/​crime. 26   But it is notable that Kahan and colleagues do not take this finding to suggest that these participants are acting irrationally. They write, “We submit that a form of information processing cannot reliably be identified as ‘irrational’, ‘subrational’, ‘boundedly rational’, or the like independent of what an individuals’ aims are in making use of information (Baron, 2008, p. 61). It is perfectly rational, from an 25

Deliberation and Spontane i t y

175

Kahan and colleagues’ findings don’t appear to be specific to quantitative reasoning. Kahan (2013) finds similar patterns using the Cognitive Reflection Test (Toplak et al. 2011), a measure of dispositions to process information in deliberative, System 2ish ways. Likewise, Schwitzgebel and Cushman (2012) find that professional philosophers are no less susceptible to order effects and other reasoning biases than are non-​philosophers, even when making judgments about classic philosophical problems, such as the doctrine of double effect and the principle of moral luck. All of this is consistent with research showing that cognitive sophistication does not attenuate the “blind spot bias” (West et al., 2012), which is the tendency to recognize biases in others more easily than in oneself.27 Research on ethical action, and on consistency between one’s values and one’s behavior, yields similar results. Schwitzgebel and Joshua Rust (2014) compared the ethical behavior of ethics professors with the behavior of other philosophy professors as well as professors outside of philosophy. They examined both how likely participants were to engage in seemingly ethical behavior—​like voting, replying to students’ emails, and filling out questionnaires honestly—​and how consistent participants’ behavior was with their stated values. What they found was that ethics professors’ stated values were more stringent on some issues, like vegetarianism and charitable donations, but on not one issue was the behavior of ethics professors unequivocally better than that of those in the comparison groups. Moreover, while the ethics professors’ attitude–​behavior consistency was

individual welfare perspective, for individuals to engage with decision-​relevant science in a manner that promotes culturally or politically congenial beliefs. What any individual member of the public thinks about the reality of climate change, the hazards of nuclear waste disposal, or the efficacy of gun control is too inconsequential to influence the risk that that person or anyone he or she cares about faces. Nevertheless, given what positions on these issues signify about a person’s defining commitments, forming a belief at odds with the one that predominates on it within important affinity groups of which such a person is a member could expose him or her to an array of highly unpleasant consequences (Kahan, 2012). Forms of information processing that reliably promote the stakes that individuals have in conveying their commitment to identity defining groups can thus be viewed as manifesting what Anderson (1993) and others (Lessig, 1995; Akerlof and Kranton, 2000; Cohen, 2003; Hillman, 2010; Stanovich, 2013) have described as expressive rationality. If ideologically motivated reasoning is expressively rational, then we should expect those individuals who display the highest reasoning capacities to be the ones most powerfully impelled to engage in it (Kahan et al., 2012). This study now joins the rank of a growing list of others that fit this expectation and that thus supports the interpretation that ideologically motivated reasoning is not a form of bounded rationality, but instead a sign of how it becomes rational for otherwise intelligent people to use their critical faculties when they find themselves in the unenviable situation of having to choose between crediting the best available evidence or simply being who they are.” (2017, 77, emphasis in original). 27   I say that this finding is consistent with Schwitzgebel and Cushman’s research on the presumption that professional philosophers rate relatively high in cognitive sophistication. I  do not know whether this is actually true. At the least, I suspect that it is true of common beliefs about professional philosophers.

Ethics

176

strongest on some issues—​like voting—​it was weakest on others—​like making charitable donations.

5. Conclusion These arguments are not at all tantamount to the radical view that deliberation has no role, or even an unimportant role, in making our spontaneous reactions more virtuous. Rather, they show that deliberation is neither necessary nor always recommended for ethical action. This leaves open the possibility that some forms of deliberation are better than others.28 But it forecloses the possibility that the way to ensure that our implicit attitudes are ethical is always to scrutinize them, Alfred-​like. This we often ought to do, but it isn’t always necessary and it can be costly. The question remains, then: What ought we to do in these situations? How can we effectively cultivate better “instincts” for acting both spontaneously and ethically, Belinda-​like?

  See Elizabeth Anderson (2005) for a compelling comment on the value of creating more effective “deliberative contexts” for combating the shortcomings of some moral heuristics. 28

7

The Habit Stance

In the preceding chapter, I argued that deliberation is neither necessary nor always recommended for ethical action. One way to gloss this claim is to think in terms of Dennett’s distinction between “stances” for predicting behavior. Dennett (1989) popularized the terms “physical stance,” “design stance,” and “intentional stance”. These terms refer to ways of making predictions about what entities in the world will do. The physical stance is the basic orientation of the natural sciences. If you want to predict what a rock will do when I drop it from my hand, you’ll use the physical stance (or some lay approximation of it). That is, you’ll use what you know about how gravity affects objects in order to make a prediction about what the rock will do (namely, fall toward the earth). You won’t worry about what the rock has been designed to do, unless you’re an extreme creationist or believe in an archaic teleological version of physics. Nor will you worry about the rock’s wanting or hoping or desiring to fall to the earth, since most  people  don’t  think rocks have intentional states like these. If you want to predict what a toaster will do when you press the start button, however, you probably won’t focus on the underlying physics of heat and electricity, nor again will you focus on what you imagine the toaster’s hopes or fears to be. Rather, because the toaster is an artifact, you’ll focus on what it was designed to do. You’ll do this because it’s effective and reliable to predict what the toaster will do on the basis of your understanding of what it was designed to do. Your understanding of its design might be wrong, but taking the design stance is still probably your best bet. Finally, if you want to make a prediction about what a person will do—​say, what Selma will do if she hates her job—​you are best off focusing on familiar features of her mind. She is likely to show up late, complain about her boss, maybe quit, and so on. Jerry  Fodor illustrates the appeal of the intentional stance: “If you want to know where my physical body will be next Thursday, mechanics—​our best science of middle-​sized objects after all, and reputed to be pretty good in its field—​is no use to you at all. Far the best way to find out (usually, in practice, the only way to find out) is: ask me!” (1987, 6, emphasis in original). Each stance can be taken toward one and the same entity, with variable degrees of success. It won’t do much good to take the intentional stance toward rocks and

177

178

Ethics

toasters, but a neuroscientist might make very successful predictions about human behavior by taking the physical stance. (This doesn’t take a neuroscientist, of course. Taking the physical stance, I can predict that if I feed you a lot of caffeine, you will act energetically.) Similarly, evolutionary psychologists might make predictions about human emotions by taking the design stance. For example, we have evolved to feel disgusted by germs and pathogens that can harm us (Kelly, 2013). This leads to a design-​stance prediction that you will feel disgusted if I offer you a handful of rotting food. In arguing that deliberation is neither necessary nor always recommended for ethical action, one could say that I am arguing against taking the intentional stance alone toward oneself. Roughly, by this I mean that, in endeavoring to improve the virtuousness of our implicit attitudes, we should not treat them as rational states to be reasoned with. Admittedly, this is a bit of a stretch of Dennett’s concept. Taking the intentional stance doesn’t mean focusing on an agent’s deliberations per se or on making predictions about the effects of various self-​regulation strategies. Dennett’s stances are tools for making predictions about what entities will do, by treating those entities as if their behavior were driven just by physical forces, functional design, or intentional states.1 What is adaptable from Dennett, though, is the broad distinction between predictions that focus on an entity’s explicit mental states—​those states capable of figuring into deliberation and practical reasoning—​and predictions that don’t. This adaptation is useful when we are considering what kinds of interventions for improving our implicit attitudes are effective and for conceptualizing the attitude we take toward ourselves when aspiring to self-​improvement.2 At the same time, the ethics of implicit attitudes is a matter neither of adopting the physical stance alone toward oneself nor of adopting the design stance alone toward oneself. Implicit attitudes are intentional states with cognitive and affective components. The actions they underwrite reflect upon us; they are examples of what we care about. These qualities of implicit attitudes recommend against regulating them by treating them as if they were governed by the laws of physics alone. They also recommend against treating them as if they were designed to perform certain fixed functions.

1   The “as if ” is important for allowing Dennett room to endorse physicalism. The point of these stances is not to distinguish entities that are and aren’t made of, or governed by, physical forces. The point is rather about making the most accurate and efficient predictions of behavior. 2   I am indebted to Louise Antony (2016) for the idea of characterizing various interventions for changing implicit attitudes in terms of Dennett’s stances. Note that the relevant distinction here is not between stances that maintain an engaged, first-​person perspective and stances that take up a disengaged, third-​person perspective toward one’s implicit attitudes. In the way that I will use the concept of “stances,” all stances will involve taking certain attitudes toward one’s implicit attitudes. These are ways of treating our implicit attitudes when we try to change them. So even taking the intentional stance toward one’s implicit attitudes involves adopting a third-​person perspective on them.

The Habit Stanc e

179

While improving our implicit attitudes is not reducible to taking the intentional, physical, or design stance, it involves elements of each. Cultivating more virtuous implicit attitudes is in part intentional, physical, and design-​focused, in other words. In recognition of William James’s point that “our virtues are habits as much as our vices” (1899, 64) (and in keeping with the tradition that any decent work of philosophical psychology must quote James), I will call the most promising hybrid of these stances the habit stance.3 The habit stance is in part intentional, because improving our implicit attitudes ineliminably involves goal-​setting and adopting particular motives. It is in part physical, because improving our implicit attitudes necessarily involves rote repetition and practice, activities that operate on the basis of brutely causal processes. And it is in part design, because improving our implicit attitudes requires both appreciating what they are designed by evolution to do and appreciating how to design our environments and situations to elicit the right kinds of spontaneous responses.4 In this context, adopting the habit stance means cultivating better implicit attitudes—​and hence better spontaneous decisions and actions—​by treating them as if they were habits. In this chapter, I describe what it means to take the habit stance in endeavoring to improve the virtuousness of our implicit attitudes. I do so by appealing to the most empirically well-​supported and promising interventions for implicit attitude change. One virtue of this approach is that it skirts a worry about the “creepiness” of implicit attitude change interventions. The creepiness worry is that these interventions will be widely rejected because they seem akin to a kind of brainwashing. Some interventions involve rote repetition of associations, and some are even presented subliminally. On their own, these techniques seem to be ways of taking the physical stance alone toward attitude change, which does have a Clockwork Orange ring to it. Understanding these techniques in the broader context of the habit stance, however, should alleviate the creepiness worry. Treating our implicit attitudes as if they were habits means treating them as part of who we are, albeit a part distinct from our ordinary, conscious beliefs and values. Of course, research on implicit social cognition is relatively new, which means that research on implicit attitude change is even newer. While it is clear that implicit attitudes are malleable, there is much to learn about the most effective techniques for changing them. First I’ll discuss three general approaches that increasingly appear to be well supported in both lab-​based and field studies (§1). Each represents a different element of habit change, that is, a way of taking the habit stance toward oneself. Respectively, I’ll outline rote practice (§1.1), pre-​commitment (§1.2),   Thanks to Alex Madva for suggesting this concept.   Understood this way, the idea of the habit stance marks a step beyond what others have rightly noted about states like implicit attitudes, that they are reducible to neither “reasons” nor “causes” (Gendler, 2012; Dreyfus, 2007a). This is true, and our efforts to improve them should similarly not be reduced to targeting either of these alone. 3 4

Ethics

180

and context regulation (§1.3). These are not the only effective strategies for the self-​ regulation of implicit attitudes, nor will they necessarily prove to be the most effective. Future research will tell. But what they illustrate is the value and importance of the habit stance, and in particular how this stance is composed of elements of the others (i.e., of the intentional, physical, and design stances). Then I’ll consider objections to taking the habit stance in this way (§2). Some objections are primarily empirical; they are about the broadness and durability of implicit attitude change interventions. Another is not empirical. It is about the nature of praise, in particular whether the reshaping of one’s attitudes and behavior in the ways I describe counts as a genuine form of ethics.

1. Techniques Research on self-​regulation is immensely broad, denoting more a set of assumptions about techniques for self-​ improvement than a particular target set of unwanted behaviors. Two assumptions are particularly salient in the field. One is that approaches to ethical self-​cultivation can and should be subjected to empirical scrutiny. I embrace this assumption in what follows. The second is that the relationship between self-​regulation and self-​control is extremely tight. I reject this assumption. In doing so, I cast a wider net in considering the most effective techniques for improving our implicit attitudes, wider, that is, than a focus on self-​control strategies alone would allow. “Self-​regulation” and “self-​control” are not settled terms in the research literature. But roughly, self-​regulation refers to the general process of managing one’s thoughts, feelings, and behavior in light of goals and standards (e.g., Carver and Scheier 1982; Fujita 2011). Self-​control refers more narrowly to impulse inhibition (e.g., Mischel et al., 1988) or, as Angela Duckworth puts it, to “the voluntary regulation of behavioral, emotional, and attentional impulses in the presence of momentarily gratifying temptations or diversions.”5 Many researchers see self-​regulation and self-​ control, understood in roughly these terms, as very tightly linked. In their widely cited meta-​analysis, for example, Denise T. D. de Ridder and colleagues say that, despite important differences between competing theories, “researchers agree that self-​control focuses on the efforts people exert to stimulate desirable responses and

  Duckworth’s definition differs from Mischel’s in the sense that she does not emphasize the inhibition of impulses in the service of resisting temptation. One can exhibit self-​control, on her definition, by avoiding situations in which one will feel unwanted impulses. See https://​sites.sas.upenn. edu/​duckworth/​pages/​research. Note also that others challenge these definitions of self-​regulation and self-​control. See, e.g., Jack Block (2002), who advances a roughly Aristotelian conception of self-​ control, as a capacity that admits of deficiencies as well as excesses. For an elaboration of these issues, as well as of the examples I present in the text, see Brownstein (ms). 5

The Habit Stanc e

181

inhibit undesirable responses and that self-​control thereby constitutes an important prerequisite for self-​regulation” (2012, 77). Others take a stronger stance, arguing that self-​control is not just a prerequisite for self-​regulation, but that it inevitably promotes it. In what they call their “manual of the sanities”—​a positive psychology handbook describing contemporary research on strengths of character—​Christopher Peterson and Seligman argue that “there is no true disadvantage of having too much self-​control” (2004, 515). Likewise, Baumeister and Jessica Alquist argue that “trait self-​control . . . appears to have few or no downsides” (2009, p. 115). The implied premise of these claims is that self-​control has no downsides for self-​regulation, that is, for the agent’s ability to manage her thoughts, feelings, and behavior in pursuit of her goals. There are several reasons to reject the idea that self-​regulation and self-​control are so tightly linked, however. One reason is that the benefits of self-​control appear to accrue differently to people based on factors like race and socioeconomic status (SES). Research suggests that the benefits of self-​control are mixed for low-​SES youth, in particular low-​SES black youth. Gregory Miller and colleagues (2015), for example, show that for low-​SES black teenagers, high trait self-​control predicts academic success and psychosocial health, but at the expense of epigenetic aging (i.e., a biomarker for disparities between biological and chronological age). “To the extent that they had better self-​control,” the authors write, “low-​SES children went on to experience greater cardiometabolic risk as young adults, as reflected on a composite of obesity, blood pressure, and the stress hormones cortisol, epinephrine, and norepinephrine” (2015, 10325). Gene Brody and colleagues (2013) arrive at similar conclusions, finding that low-​SES black youth with high self-​control, while achieving more academically than low-​SES black youth with low self-​control, also experience more allostatic load (i.e., stress on the body, which in turn predicts the development of chronic diseases and health disparities). High self-​control may also be maladaptive for people with low SES. Sara Heller and colleagues provide an illustrative vignette of the comparative benefits and consequences of persistence (which is a central theme in research on self-​control) for advantaged and disadvantaged people: [I]‌magine a relative promises to pick up a teenager from school, but right now it is not working out—​15 minutes after school lets out, the ride is still not there. For a youth from an affluent background the adaptive response is probably to wait (persist), because the adult will eventually show up and the teen will be spared the cost of having to walk or bus home. In school, if that youth is struggling to learn some difficult material the optimal response is also to keep trying (persist); if needed, eventually a teacher or parent or peer will help the youth master the material. Now imagine a youth from a disadvantaged area where things can be more chaotic and unpredictable. When the youth is waiting for a ride after school that is

182

Ethics

running late, the adaptive response to things not working out may be to start walking home (explore a more promising strategy). When the youth is struggling with schoolwork the automatic response could be either to just move on, or to persist, depending partly on whether they think of this as the same situation as someone being late picking them up from school (for example if they think “this is yet another situation where I can’t rely on others”). (2015, 10–11) There are also counterexamples that challenge the idea that self-​regulation and self-​control are always tightly linked. Self-​regulation is sometimes attained without suppressing occurrent impulses or resisting temptations, such as when one successfully manages competing thoughts and feelings while playing sports (Fujita, 2011). Shooting a free throw in basketball, for instance, can involve suppressing impulsive feelings of fear about missing the shot, but it need not. And it is likely that the best shooters don’t suppress these feelings of fear; rather, they simply don’t feel them. Sometimes one achieves self-​regulation by acting on the basis of one’s impulses. Alfred and Belinda, from Chapter  6, offer a good example of this. Both, we can presume, share the long-​term intention to be healthy and sensible, and both also enjoy spontaneously eating ice cream for dinner from time to time. Only Belinda, however, has good instincts for when and where to spontaneously eat ice cream for dinner. In other words, only Belinda has a good feel for when to act on the basis of her impulses and temptations. She seems better self-​regulated than Alfred, who cannot let himself indulge without carefully scrutinizing his decision (in such a way, as I discussed earlier, that he ruins the idea of spontaneously eating ice cream for dinner). In other words, Alfred seems to exert more self-​control than Belinda, but Belinda seems better self-​regulated than Alfred. As I have said, avoiding the assumption that self-​regulation necessarily involves effortful self-​control enables me to cast a wider net in considering the most effective techniques for improving our implicit attitudes. I begin with the simplest: rote practice.

1.1  Rote Practice Arguably the most ineliminable form of self-​regulation of implicit attitudes is also the least glamorous. The fact is that simple, repetitive practice is effective for shaping and reshaping these states. This is clear across a number of domains. K. Anders Ericsson first made the argument that it takes about ten thousand hours to become an expert in some domain (Ericsson et  al., 1993). Gladwell (2011) popularized this so-​called ten-​thousand-​hour rule, although it isn’t at all clear that ten thousand hours is the right number (as discussed later). Building on Ericsson and others’ research on chess grandmasters, composers, and athletes, Gladwell argued that almost no one succeeds at elite levels of skilled action on the basis of innate

The Habit Stanc e

183

talent alone. Rather, “achievement is talent plus preparation” (Gladwell, 2013). In particular, achievement in domains like these is talent plus thousands of hours of preparation, give or take. Often, this preparation involves simple repetition. This might seem unsurprising in the realm of sports. Andre Agassi (2010), for example, describes his emptying basket after basket of tennis balls as a child, hitting serve after serve after serve. Agassi’s tyrannical father presumed that anyone who hit a million balls as a child would become a great player. This is false, of course, since very few players, no matter how many balls they hit, could become as great as Agassi. But the point is that even Agassi wouldn’t have been great without having put in endless hours of rote practice. Research suggests this is the case in more cerebral skilled activities too, like chess and musical composition. John Hayes (1985), for example, found that almost all famous classical composers created their best works only after they had been composing for at least ten years. While this surely included much contemplation about the nature of successful composition, careful consideration of successful and unsuccessful scores, and so on, much of it also involved simply going through the process of composing over and over again. The ten-​thousand-​hour rule has received a lot of criticism. For one there appear to be counterexamples. Apparently a significant percentage of professional basketball players in Australia reached expertise with far fewer than ten thousand hours of practice  (Epstein, 2013). The quicker-​to-​expertise phenomenon also appears to be common in high jumping, sprinting, and darts (Epstein, 2013). Others have developed techniques for accelerated skill learning.6 Moreover, other things seem to have a significant impact on success in sports, such as having grown up in a small rather than large city and having spent time as a child engaged in structured activities that promote general self-​regulatory skills, such as patience and grit (rather than activities more narrowly focused on skill development; for review see Berry et al., 2008). A recent meta-​analysis even finds that deliberate practice accounts for only 18% of the variance in sports performance and, more striking still, for only 1% of the variance of performance for elite-​level athletes (Macnamara et al., 2016). These critiques are legitimate, but they don’t undermine the idea that rote practice is an essential element of skill development. Some of the apparent counterexamples are of highly skilled but not elite-​level performers (e.g., professional basketball players in Australia, not National Basketball Association players in the United States). Others pertain to activities that are not particularly complex, such as darts. In the case of measuring variance in performance due to deliberate practice, there is debate about the correct definition of “practice.” Ericsson suggests that deliberate practice in sports involves “one-​on-​one instruction of an athlete by

  See, e.g., Ferriss (2015).

6

Ethics

184

a coach, who assigns practice activities with explicit goals and effective practice activities with immediate feedback and opportunities for repetition” (2016, 352). Brooke Macnamara and colleagues, in their meta-​analysis, employ a much broader understanding of practice, including activities like weight training and watching film. Neither of these approaches speaks to the role of rote practice in skill development. Surely such repetitive action is insufficient for expertise. But it is consistent with the evidence that it is nearly always necessary.7 This is not a new discovery in other areas of life. Confucius’s Analects place great emphasis on the rote practice of ritual activities (Li). Practice is central to living in accord with what Confucius calls “the Way” (Dao). For example, in Analects 8.2, “The Master said, ‘If you are respectful but lack ritual you will become exasperating; if you are careful but lack ritual you will become timid; if you are courageous but lack ritual you will become unruly; if you are upright but lack ritual you will become inflexible’ ” (Confucius, 2003, p. 78). Performance of ritual covers a variety of activities in the Analects. On the Confucian picture, these rituals and rites serve to form moral character and habits, which in turn help to create social harmony (Li, 2006). Sarkissian (2010a) has combined these insights with recent research in social psychology and neuroscience in arguing that prolonged ritual practice facilitates spontaneous yet ethical behavior through the creation of somatic neural markers. In short, these are affective tags that mark particular behavioral routines as positive or negative (Damasio, 1994). Sarkissian writes: The accrual of these markers over time fine-​tunes and accelerates the decision-​making process; at the limit, the correct course of action would come to mind immediately, with compelling emotional valence . . . familiarity with a broad range of emotions, facilitated through exposure to literature, art, and social rituals, will allow one to perceive values in a wide range of scenarios, thus improving the likelihood of responding appropriately in any particular situation. (2010a, 7) Somatic marker theory has been combined with theories of feedback-​error learning, of the sort I discussed in Chapter 2 (Holroyd et al., 2003). This nicely connects my account of the functional architecture of implicit attitudes with established and plausible theories of habit and self-​regulation. The most head-​on evidence attesting to the importance of rote practice for implicit attitude change, however, comes from research on changing implicit biases. Kerry Kawakami and colleagues have demonstrated that biased approach and avoidance tendencies can be changed through bare-​bones rote practice. In their research, this involves training participants to associate counterstereotypes with social groups.

  See Gladwell (2013).

7

The Habit Stanc e

185

For example, in the training condition in Kawakami et al. (2007a), participants were shown photographs of men and women, under which both gender-​stereotypic (e.g., “sensitive” for women) and gender-​counterstereotypic (e.g., “strong” for women) information was written. Participants were asked to select the trait that was not culturally associated with the social group represented in the picture. Participants practiced fairly extensively, repeating this counterstereotype identification a total of 480 times. The effect of practicing counterstereotypical thinking in this way was a significant change in participants’ behavior. In the evaluation phase of the experiment, participants made hypothetical hiring decisions about male and female candidates, as well as rated the candidates in terms of stereotypical and counterstereotypical traits. Kawakami and colleagues have varied the social groups and traits used as prompts in other studies, as well as the behavioral outcome measures. For example, using this procedure, Kawakami and colleagues (2000) asked participants to negate black-​athletic stereotypes. They were able to completely reverse biased participants’ implicit attitudes. Moreover, variations in the training technique have also proved effective. Kawakami et al. (2007b) used a procedure in which participants pulled a joystick toward themselves when they were presented with black faces and pushed the joystick away from themselves when presented with white faces. The notion guiding this technique originates in research on embodied cognition. Gestures representing physical avoidance—​pushing something away from one’s body—​can signify mental avoidance—​effectively saying no to that thing. Likewise, gestures representing physical approach—​pulling something toward oneself—​can signify acceptance of that thing (Chen and Bargh, 1999). Rote practice is at the heart of this paradigm, throughout its many variations. It is crucial that participants in these experiments simply practice associating stigmatized social groups with counterstereotypes repeatedly. One way to think of this, recommended by Madva (2017), is as the “contact hypothesis in a bottle.” In short, the contact hypothesis—​originally proposed by Gordon Allport (1954) and extensively researched since—​proposes that prejudiced attitudes can be changed by intergroup contact. Put plainly, spending time and interacting with people from social groups other than one’s own promotes egalitarian attitudes and mutual understanding. Evidence for the effectiveness of contact in promoting these ends is substantive, though only under particular conditions. Intergroup contact promotes egalitarian explicit attitudes when both parties are of equal status and when they are engaged in meaningful activities, for example (Pettigrew and Tropp, 2006). Evidence for the effectiveness of intergroup contact in improving implicit attitudes is also substantive, but also under particular conditions (Dasgupta and Rivera, 2008; Dasgupta, 2013). For example, Natalie Shook and Fazio (2008) found in a field study that random assignment to a black roommate led white college students to have more positive implicit attitudes toward black people. Counterstereotype training mimics at least part of the mechanism that drives the effects of intergroup contact:  repeated experiences that strengthen

Ethics

186

counterstereotypical associations. In other words, the intervention reduces one element of effective intergroup contact—​unlearning stereotypes—​down to a simple activity that psychologists can operationalize in the lab and agents can practice quickly over and over again. A  perhaps unexpected yet apt analogy is found in the advent of online poker. One of the central challenges aspiring poker experts traditionally faced was the simple difficulty of seeing enough hands (i.e., logging sufficient hours at the table to receive the incredible number of combinations of cards and contexts that one faces when playing poker). At a live table, the game goes slowly, so thousands of hours are required for extensive practice. Online poker is much faster. It enables players to see at least ten times as many hands per hour. Like counterstereotype training, online poker is not equivalent to live poker; there are important differences, and live-​game pros and online pros have different sets of skills. Similarly, pairing “women” with “math” isn’t the same as doing difficult math problems in mixed-​gender groups. But the bottled versions of both of these activities are useful and effective nonetheless. Kawakami and colleagues’ research nicely exemplifies how complex social attitudes can be reshaped at least in part by the simplest of activities—​repeating the associations and behaviors one wants. This is not reducible to an intentional stance intervention. As I discussed in Chapter 2, the effects of something like rote practice on attitudes and behavior are indicative of the nature of one’s operative mental states. Reflective states like belief paradigmatically change in the face of evidence and reason; they do not paradigmatically change when one simply repeats words or gestures. Indeed, why should repeatedly selecting traits not culturally associated with a particular social group change whether one believes that that trait applies to that group? That said, one must choose this kind of training, so it is not as if the idea of the intentional stance is altogether irrelevant to rote practice interventions.8 Similarly, engaging in rote practice to improve one’s implicit attitudes involves taking the physical stance, but is not reducible to it. The repetition involved is in some sense a way of treating oneself as if one were merely a physical thing, subject to nothing but causal forces. One is simply pushing one’s implicit attitudes around. And yet social contact, for instance, has salutary effects (in both its full and bottled versions) only under conditions that mesh with other concerns of the agent, such as being of equal status with others. Likewise, the emphasis on rote practice

  But see Kawakami et  al. (2007b) for a description of a subliminal counterstereotype training technique, which does not require participants to choose to change their stereotypical associations. Kawakami and colleagues find that participants sometimes resent counterstereotype training, and thus they endeavored to design a less obtrusive intervention. It is noteworthy, though, that while participants who resented counterstereotype training, and briefly showed ironic effects of the training (i.e., showed more stereotypic responding on subsequent tasks), they subsequently demonstrated less biased responding after time. It seems as if, once their resentment abated, they demonstrated the more lasting effects of the intervention (i.e., less stereotypic responding). 8

The Habit Stanc e

187

in Confucian ethics is aimed at shaping the way that one perceives and acts upon values. This is clearly irreducible to a physical stance ethics. And finally, while rote practice certainly takes advantage of the ways in which we have evolved—​in particular the way in which our minds are akin to categorization machines that update in the face of changing experiences (Gendler, 2011)—​rote practice is irreducible to a design stance intervention too. The point of practicing a particular behavior is not to fulfill some function we have acquired through evolution. Rather, it is to cultivate better spontaneous responses to situations. Doing this is akin to cultivating better habits, which involves intentional, physical, and design elements, but is reducible to none of these.

1.2  Pre-​Commitment In Chapter 5, I briefly mentioned Ulysses’ strategy of instructing his crew to bind him to the mast of his ship so that he could resist the Sirens’ song. I called this a form of pre-​commitment. Ulysses wanted to resist the song; he knew he wouldn’t be able to resist it; so he made a plan that denied himself a choice when the moment came. In one sense, this strategy clearly reflected Ulysses’ beliefs, values, and intentions. If you wanted to predict that he would have used it, you would want to adopt the intentional stance. In another sense, though, Ulysses took the physical stance toward himself. He saw that he would be unable to resist the song on the basis of his willpower. Instead, he relied on the physical force of the ropes and the mast to keep him in place. If you wanted to predict whether Ulysses would in fact resist the Sirens’ song, you would want to test the strength of the rope rather than the strength of his resolve. Ulysses’ technique was crude, literally relying on binding himself by force. More subtle versions of self-​regulation via pre-​commitment have since been devised. Principal among them—​and perhaps most intriguing for psychological reasons—​ are techniques that regulate one’s attention through pre-​commitment. Consider implementation intentions. These are “if–​then” plans that appear to be remarkably effective for redirecting attention in service of achieving a wide range of goals. Implementation intentions specify a goal-​directed response that an individual plans to perform when she encounters an anticipated cue. In the usual experimental scenario, participants who hold a goal, “I want to X!” (e.g., “I want to eat healthy!”) are asked to supplement their goal with a plan of the form, “and if I  encounter opportunity Y, then I  will perform goal-​directed response Z!” (e.g., “and if I get take-​out tonight, then I will order something with vegetables!”). Forming an implementation intention appears to improve self-​regulation in (for example) dieting, exercising, recycling, restraining impulses, maintaining focus (e.g., in sports), avoiding binge drinking, combating implicit biases, and performing well on memory, arithmetic, and Stroop tasks (Gollwitzer and Sheeran, 2006).

Ethics

188

It is worth digging a little deeper into the pathways and processes that allow if–​then planning to work, given how remarkably effective and remarkably simple this form of self-​regulation appears to be.9 Two questions are salient in particular. First, why think that implementation intentions are a form of self-​regulation via pre-​commitment, in particular involving the redirecting of attention? Second, why think that self-​regulation of this kind reflects the habit stance? Peter Gollwitzer and Paschal Sheeran (2006) argue that adopting an implementation intention helps a person to become “perceptually ready” to encounter a situation that is critical to that person’s goals. Becoming perceptually ready to encounter a critical cue is a way of regulating one’s attention. Perceptual readiness has two principle features: it involves increasing the accessibility of cues relevant to a particular goal and automatizing one’s behavioral response to those cues. For example, performance on a shooter bias test—​where one’s goal is to “shoot” all and only those individuals shown holding weapons in ambiguous pictures—​is improved when one adopts the implementation intention “and if I see a gun, then I will shoot!” (Mendoza et al., 2010) Here the relevant cue—​“gun”—​is made more accessible—​and the intended response—​to shoot when one sees a gun—​is made more automatic. Gollwitzer and colleagues explain this cue–​response link in associative terms:  “An implementation intention produces automaticity immediately through the willful act of creating an association between the critical situation and the goal-​directed response” (2008, 326). It is precisely this combination of willfully acting automatically that makes implementation intentions fascinating. I’ll say more about the automatization of behavioral response in a moment. It seems that being “perceptually ready” is tied in particular to the relative accessibility of goal-​relevant cues when one has adopted an implementation intention. Researchers have demonstrated what they mean by cue accessibility using a number of tasks. Compared with controls, subjects who adopt if–​then plans have better recall of specified cues (Achtziger et al., 2007); have faster reactions to cues (Aarts et al., 1999); and are better at identifying and responding to cued words (Parks-​ Stamm et al., 2007). It appears that the critical cues specified and hence made more accessible by adoption of implementation intentions can be either external (e.g., a word, a place, or a time) or internal (e.g., a feeling of anxiety, disgust, or fear). All of this suggests that adopting implementation intentions enhances the salience of critical cues, whether they are internal or external to the subject. Cues, in this context, become Features for agents. In some cases, salience is operationally defined. In these cases, for a cue to be accessible just means for the subject to respond to it quickly and/​or efficiently, regardless of whether the subject sees the cue consciously or perceives it in any particular way. It is possible, though, that the

  See Gollwitzer and Sheeran (2006) for review of average effect sizes of implementation intention interventions. 9

The Habit Stanc e

189

perceptual content of the cue changes for the subject, at the level of her perceptual experience. For example, if I am in a state—​due to having adopted an implementation intention—​where I am more likely to notice words that begin with the letter “M,” I might literally see things differently from what I would have seen had I merely adopted the goal of looking for words that begin with the letter “M.”10 In both cases, implementation intentions appear to be a form of self-​regulation via the pre-​planned redirecting of one’s attention. Why think that this is a way of taking the habit stance? Without pre-​commitment to the plan—​ which appears to represent an intentional stance ethics—​ implementation intentions can’t get off the ground. Indeed, implementation intentions are tools to improve goal striving. Just as Ulysses consciously and intentionally chose to bind himself to the mast, if–​then planners must consciously and intentionally choose to act in way Z when they encounter cue Y. But the analogy cuts both ways. Ulysses had to follow through with literally binding himself. In an important sense, he had to deny himself agency in the crucial moment. If–​then planning seems to rely upon a related, but more subtle version of denying oneself choices and decisions in the crucial moments of action. This is the automatization of behavioral response. The idea is that if–​then planning makes it more likely that one just will follow the plan, without evaluating, doubting, or (re)considering it. More generally, this is the idea of pre-​commitment. It treats one’s future self as a thing to be managed in the present, so that one has fewer choices later.11 One could imagine Alfred benefiting from adopting a plan like “If I see ice cream bars at the grocery store, then I’ll buy them!”12 Perhaps doing so would help him to avoid destroying his reasons to be spontaneous by deliberating about those reasons. We can find further reason to think that attention-​regulation via pre-​commitment involves, but is not irreducible to, the intentional stance by considering related self-​regulation strategies that don’t work. Adding justificatory force to one’s implementation intentions appears to diminish their effectiveness. Frank Wieber and colleagues (2009) show that the behavior response of subjects who were instructed to adopt an if–​then plan that included a “why” component—​for example, “If I am sitting in front of the TV, then I will eat fruit because I want to stay healthy!” (emphasis added)—​returned to the level obtained in the goal-​intention-​only condition. Being reminded of one’s reasons for striving for a goal seems to undermine the effectiveness of adopting an implementation intention, in other words. Wieber

  See Chapter 2 for discussion of different versions of this possibility, some of which involve cognitive penetration of perception and some of which don’t. 11   See Bratman (1987) on how intentions can serve to foreclose deliberation. 12   As I discuss in §2, the dominant focus in research on self-​regulation is on combating impulsivity. But there are those of us like Alfred who are not too myopic, but are “hyperopic” instead. We (I admit) struggle to indulge even when we have good reason to do so. For research on hyperopic decision-​ making, see Kivetz and Keinan (2006), Keinan and Kivetz (2011), and Brownstein (ms). 10

190

Ethics

and colleagues found this using both an analytic reasoning study and a two-​week weight-​loss study. It would be interesting to see if “if–​then–​why planning” has similarly detrimental effects in other scenarios. While implementation intentions clearly aren’t reducible to a physical stance intervention, there is evidence that their effectiveness is tied to surprisingly low-​ level physical processes. Implementation intentions appear to have effects on the very beginning stages of perceptual processing. This emerges from research on the role of emotion in if–​then planning. Inge Schweiger Gallo and colleagues (2009) have shown that implementation intentions can be used to control emotional reactivity to spiders in phobic subjects. Schweiger Gallo and colleagues’ paper is the only one I know of that offers a neurophysiological measure of emotion regulation using implementation intentions. I mention this because they find that implementation intentions diminish negative emotional reactions to spiders very early in the perceptual process, within 100 msec of the presentation of the cue. Compared with controls and subjects in the goal-​only condition, subjects who adopted if–​then plans that specified an “ignore” reaction to spiders showed lower activity in the P1 component of visual cortex. This suggests that subjects are not merely controlling their response to negative feelings; they are downregulating their fear itself, using what James Gross (2002) calls an “antecedent-​based” self-​regulation strategy (antecedent to more controlled processes).13 Adopting an implementation intention is an example of regulating one’s future behavior by making it the case that one pays attention to one thing rather than another or by changing how one sees things. While this involves both intentional and physical stance elements, as I’ve argued, one could also see this kind of self-​ regulation strategy as reflective of the design stance. Pre-​commitment involves “hacking” one’s future behavior. It takes advantage of the sort of creatures that we are, in particular that we can forecast how we will and won’t behave in the future;

13   This example is unlike many better-​known cases in which implementation intentions have powerful effects on behavior, cases in which the self-​regulation of emotion does not appear to drive the action. Cases in which if–​then plans promote the identification of words that start with the letter “M,” for example, or performance on Stroop tasks or IATs, are not cases in which negative emotions are explicitly restrained. In these cases, there is no obvious emotional content driving the subject’s response to the cue. But as I discuss in Chapter 2, there is the possibility that low-​level affect plays a pervasive role in visual processing. It is possible, then, that cues specified by implementation intentions come to be relatively more imperatival for agents. In cases where one’s goal is to block emotional reactions, as in spider phobia, the imperatival quality of goal-​relevant cues may be diminished. In other cases, when one’s goal is to react to “M” words, for example, the imperatival quality of the goal-​relevant cue may be increased. It is worth noting that leading implementation intention researchers Thomas Webb and Paschal Sheeran (2008) make room for something like what I’m suggesting. They note that it is an open question whether “forming an if–​then plan could influence how much positive affect is attached to specified cues and responses, or to the cue–​response link, which in-​turn could enhance the motivational impact of these variables” (2008, 389).

The Habit Stanc e

191

that we are “set up to be set off ” (see Chapter 4) by particular kinds of stimuli (e.g., sugar, threats, disgusting things); and that how likely we are to achieve our goals is perhaps surprisingly susceptible to minor variations in the form of our plans (e.g., implementation intention researchers insist that including the exclamation point at the end of if–​then plans matters—​that is, “if Y, then Z!” rather than “if Y, then Z”).14 As before, in the case of rote practice, the idea of the habit stance captures the nature of these kinds of interventions better than any one of the intentional, physical, or design stances alone. Gollwitzer has described implementation intentions as “instant habits,” and although the “instant” part is a bit tongue in cheek, it does not seem far off. Habits are, ideally, expressions of our goals and values, but not just this. They are useful precisely because they leave our goals and values behind at the crucial moment, just as Ulysses left his autonomy behind by tying himself to the mast. One cannot see why they work in this way without adopting the physical and design stances too, without understanding, in the case of implementation intentions, how early perceptual processing works and how we have evolved to respond to particular cues in particular ways. For these reasons, self-​regulating our implicit attitudes via pre-​commitment is best understood as an ethical technique born of treating ourselves as if we were habit-​driven creatures.

1.3  Context Regulation Melissa Bateson and colleagues (2006) show that a subtle cue suggesting that one is being watched increases cooperative behavior.15 This “Watching Eyes Effect” is striking. Simply placing a picture of a pair of eyes near an “honor box” used to collect money for communal coffee in a university break room appears to cause people to leave three times more money than they otherwise would. It is even possible that these generous coffee drinkers are affected by the watching eyes without consciously noticing them. Behavioral economists have devised a number of analogous techniques for increasing prosocial behavior—​tipping, honesty, charity, friendliness, and so on (e.g., Ariely, 2011). These strategies are ways of changing small but apparently consequential features of the environment. They have been expanded upon and even promoted into public policy in the form of “nudge” technologies. New York City’s ban on large sodas offers a vivid example. This policy builds upon now classic psychological research, such as the “Bottomless Bowl” experiment, which showed that people consume far more soup when they are unknowingly eating from a self-​ refilling bowl (Wansink et al., 2005). The core idea of the soda ban is that, while putting no limit on how much soda people can drink (since they are free to order as

  T. Webb (pers. com.).   See also Haley and Fessler (2005) for similar results on a lab-​based task.

14 15

Ethics

192

many sodas as they want), the policy encourages more moderate consumption by removing the cue triggering overconsumption (i.e., the large cup). Richard Thaler and Cass Sunstein (2008) describe policies like these as efforts to engineer the “choice architecture” of social life. Such policies, as well as default plans for things like retirement saving and organ donation, nudge people toward better behavior through particular arrangements of the ambient environment. Nudge policies are politically controversial, since they raise questions about autonomy and perfectionism, but they are psychologically fascinating.16 The particular variables that moderate their effectiveness—​or combinations of variables—​are revealing. For example, David Neal and colleagues (2011) have shown that people who habitually eat popcorn at the movies will eat stale unappetizing popcorn even if they’re not hungry, but only when the right context cues obtain. People eat less out of habit if they are not in the right place—​for example, in a meeting room rather than at a cinema—​or if they cannot eat in their habitual way—​for example, if they are forced to eat with their nondominant hand. Identifying the context cues relevant to different domains of self-​regulation is crucial. Ideas like these, of manipulating subtle elements of the context, have been used to promote the self-​regulation of implicit attitudes. Gawronski and Cesario (2013) argue that implicit attitudes are subject to “renewal effects,” which is a term used in animal learning literature to describe the recurrence of an original behavioral response after the learning of a new response. As Gawronski and Cesario explain, renewal effects usually occur in contexts other than the one in which the new response was learned. For example, a rat with a conditioned fear response to a sound may have learned to associate the sound with an electric shock in context A (e.g., its cage). Imagine then that the fear response is counterconditioned in context B (e.g., a different cage). An “ABA renewal” effect occurs if, after the rat is placed back in A (its original cage), the fear response returns. Gawronski and Cesario argue that implicit attitudes are subject to renewal effects like these. For example, a person might learn biased associations while hanging out with her friends (context A), effectively learn counterstereotypical associations while taking part in a psychology experiment (context B), then exhibit behaviors consistent with biased associations when back with her friends. Gawronski and Cesario discuss several studies (in particular, Rydell and Gawronski, 2009; Gawronski et al., 2010) that demonstrate in controlled laboratory settings renewal effects like these in implicit attitudes. The basic method of these studies involves an impression formation task in which participants are first presented with valenced information about a target individual who is pictured against a background of a particular color. This represents context A. Then, the same target individual is presented with oppositely valenced information against a background of a different color, representing

  See Waldron (2104); Kumar (2016a).

16

The Habit Stanc e

193

context B. Participants’ evaluations of the target are then assessed using an affective priming task in which the target is presented against the color of context A. In this ABA pattern, participants’ evaluations reflect what they learned in context A. Gawronski and Cesario report similar renewal effects (i.e., evaluations consist­ ent with the valence of the information that was presented first) in the patterns AAB (where the original information and new information are presented against the same background color A, and evaluations are measured against a novel background B) and ABC (where original information, new information, and evaluation all take place against different backgrounds). While the literature Gawronski and Cesario discuss emphasizes the return of undesirable, stereotype-​consistent attitudes in ABA, AAB, and ABC patterns, they also discuss patterns of context change in which participants’ ultimate evaluations of targets reflect the counterconditioning information they learned in the second block of training. These are the ABB and AAA patterns. The practical upshot of this, Gawronski and Cesario suggest, is that one ought to learn counterstereotyping information in the same context in which one aims to be unbiased (ABB and AAA renewal).17 And what counts as the “same” context can be empirically specified. Renewal effects appear to be more responsive to the perceptual similarity of contexts than they are to conceptual identity or equivalence. So it is better, for example, to learn counterstereotyping information in contexts that look like one’s familiar environs than it is to learn them in contexts that one recognizes to be conceptually equivalent. It may matter less that a de-​biasing intervention aimed at classroom interactions is administered in another “classroom,” for example, than that it is administered in another room that is painted the same color as one’s usual classroom. Finally, Gawronski and Cesario suggest that if it is not possible to learn counterstereotyping interventions in the same or similar context in which one aims to be unbiased, one ought to learn counterstereotyping interventions across a variety of contexts. This is because both ABA and ABC renewal is weaker when counterattitudinal information is presented across a variety of contexts rather than just one. The reason for this, they speculate, is that fewer contextual cues are incorporated into the agent’s representation of the counterattitudinal information when the B context is varied. A greater variety of contexts signals to the agent that the counterattitudinal information generalizes to novel contexts.

  A  common critique of implicit bias interventions is that they are too focused on changing individuals’ minds, rather than on changing institutions, political arrangements, unjust economics, etc. (cf. Huebner, 2009; Haslanger, 2015). Sometimes this critique presents social activism and self-​ reformation as mutually exclusive, when in fact they are often compatible. The idea of learning counterstereotypical information in the same context in which one hopes to act in unbiased ways represents a small, but very practical way of combining “individual” and “institutional” efforts for change. The relationship between individuals and institutions is reciprocal. Changing the context affects what’s in our minds; and what’s in our minds shapes our willingness to change the context. 17

194

Ethics

These studies suggest that minor features of agents’ context—​like the background color against which an impression of a person is formed—​can influence the activation of implicit attitudes, even after those attitudes have been “unlearned.” These are striking results, but they are consistent with a broad array of findings about the influence of context and situation on the activation and expression in behavior of implicit attitudes. Context is, of course, a broad notion. Imagine taking an IAT. The background color against which the images of the target subjects are presented is part of the context. Perhaps before having taken the IAT, the experimenter asks the subject to imagine herself as a manager at a large company deciding whom to hire. Having imagined oneself in this powerful social role will have effects on one’s implicit evaluations (as discussed later), and these effects can be thought of as part of one’s context too. Similarly, perhaps one had a fight with one’s friend before entering the lab and began the task feeling an acute sense of disrespect, or was hungry and jittery from having drunk too much caffeine, and so on. As I use the term, “context” can refer to any stimulus that moderates the way an agent evaluates or responds behaviorally to a separate conditioned stimulus. Anything that acts, in other words, as what theorists of animal learning call an “occasion setter” can count as an element of context.18 A standard example of an occasion setter is, again, an animal’s cage. A rat may demonstrate a conditioned fear response to a sound when in its cage, but not when in a novel environment. Similarly, a person may feel or express biased attitudes toward members of a social group only when in a particular physical setting, when playing a certain social role, when feeling a certain way, or the like. In Chapter 3, I discussed physical, conceptual, and motivational context cues that shape the way implicit attitudes unfold. These involved the relative lightness or darkness of the ambient environment (Schaller et  al., 2003); varying the category membership of targets on tests of implicit attitudes (Mitchell et  al., 2003; Barden et  al., 2004); and inducing salient emotions (Dasgupta et al., 2009). Each of these kinds of findings presents a habit stance opportunity for the cultivation of better implicit attitudes. As I mentioned previously, research suggests that one should learn counterstereotypical information in a context that is physically similar to the one in which one aims to be unbiased. Changing the physical context in this way is a way of treating our implicit attitudes as if they were habits. It stems from our long-​term reflective goals; it operates on us as physical entities, whose behaviors are strongly affected by seemingly irrelevant features of our situation; and it is design-​focused, akin to the “urban planning” of our minds. 18   I am indebted to Gawronski and Cesario (2013) for the idea that context acts as an occasion setter. On occasion setting and animal learning, see Schmajuk and Holland (1998).

The Habit Stanc e

195

Interventions that focus on conceptual elements of context are similar. For example, research suggests that perceiving oneself as high-​status contributes to more biased implicit attitudes. Ana Guinote and colleagues (2010) led participants in a high-​power condition to believe that their opinions would have an impact on the decisions of their school’s “Executive Committee,” and these participants showed more racial bias on both the IAT and Affect Misattribution Procedure (AMP) than those in a low-​power condition, who were led to believe that their opinions would not affect the committee’s decisions. These data should not be surprising. It is not hard to imagine a person who treats her colleagues fairly regardless of race, for example, but (unwittingly) grades her students unfairly on the basis of race. Perhaps being in the superordinate position of professor activates this person’s prejudices while being in an equal-​status position with her colleagues does not. To combat these tendencies, one could devise simple strategies to diminish the salience of superordinate status. Perhaps the chair of the department could occupy a regular office rather than the fancy corner suite. Or perhaps she could adopt a relevant implementation intention, such as “When I feel powerful, I will think, ‘Be fair!’ ” These also look to be habit stance interventions, irreducible to Dennett’s more familiar stances, but instead a hybrid of all three. So, too, with motivational elements of context. In addition to salient emotions like disgust, “internal” versus “external” forms of motivation selectively affect implicit attitudes. People who aim to be unbiased because it’s personally important to them demonstrate lower levels of implicit bias than people who want to appear unbiased because they are concerned to act in accord with social norms (Plant and Devine, 1998; Devine et  al., 2002; for a similar measure see Glaser and Knowles, 2008). In the broader context of self-​regulation, Marin Milyavskaya and colleagues (2015) find that people with intrinsic (or “want-​to”) goals—​such as the desire to eat healthy food in order to live a long life—​have lower levels of spontaneous attraction to goal-​disruptive stimuli (such as images of unhealthy food) than do people with external (or “have-​to”) goals—​such as the desire to eat healthy food in order to appease one’s spouse. The measure of spontaneous attraction in this research is both IAT and AMP. Milyavskaya and colleagues found that intrinsic, want-​to motivation is responsible for the effect. External or have-​to motivation is unrelated to one’s automatic reactions to disruptive stimuli. This is important because it is suggestive of the kinds of interventions for implicit attitude change that are likely to be effective. It seems that we should try to adopt internal kinds of motivation. While this is far from surprising to common sense, it speaks to the nature of the habit stance. Internal forms of motivation seem hard to simply adopt in the way that one can simply choose to adopt a goal. Instead, internal motivation must itself be cultivated in the way of habit creation, much as knowing how and when to deliberate is itself in part a nondeliberative skill (Chapter 6).

Ethics

196

2. Objections One worry about context-​regulation strategies in particular is that they seem to be very fine-​grained. It seems as if there are a million different situational cues that would need to be arranged in such-​and-​such a way as to shape and activate the implicit attitudes we want. Moreover, it’s possible that different combinations of different situations will lead to unpredictable outcomes. I think the only thing to do in the face of these worries is await further data. Much more research is needed in order to home in on the most powerful contextual motivators, effective combinations of situational cues, and so on. This point applies in general to the other habit stance interventions I’ve recommended, all of which are provisionally supported by the extant data. I don’t think this implies waiting to employ these strategies, though, since the extant data are the best data we’ve got. Rather, it simply means keeping our confidence appropriately modest. There are broader worries about the habit stance techniques I’ve discussed, however. Some of these are also empirical (§2.1). Are these techniques broadly applicable, such that what works in the lab works across a range of real-​life situations? And are the effects of these techniques durable? Will they last, or will agents’ unwanted implicit attitudes return once they are bombarded with the images, temptations, and solicitations of their familiar world? Another worry is not empirical (§2.2). It is that these self-​regulation techniques do not produce genuinely ethical, praiseworthy action. Perhaps they are instead merely tricks for acting in ways that agents with good ethical values already want to act. Are they perhaps a kind of cheating, akin to taking performance-​enhancing drugs for ethical action?

2.1  Durability and Generality Some have argued that techniques like those I’ve described are unlikely to be effective outside of psychology laboratories (e.g., Alcoff, 2010; Anderson, 2012; Devine et al. 2012; Huebner, 2016; Mandelbaum, 2015b; Mendoza et al., 2010; Stewart and Payne, 2008; Olson and Fazio, 2006; Wennekers, 2013).19 There are several reasons for this. One is a “bombardment” worry: once agents leave the lab, they will be bombarded by stereotypical images and temptations, and these will eventually overwhelm or reverse any changes in their implicit attitudes. This amounts to a concern with the durability of the effects of habit stance techniques. Perhaps because of bombardment, but perhaps also for other reasons, the effects of these interventions will simply be too weak to make a meaningful difference in the real world. Another reason critics have given has to do with generality: perhaps implicit attitudes toward members of particular groups can be retrained, the worry goes, but there are many   See Madva (2017) for discussion.

19

The Habit Stanc e

197

socially stigmatized groups in the world, and the goal of any substantive ethics of implicit attitudes should be to create broad dispositional ethical competencies. The idea here is that these techniques seem to have too narrow a scope. Much of this criticism can be adjudicated only empirically. How long-​lasting the effects of the kinds of attitude-​change techniques I’ve discussed can be is an open question. There is some reason for optimism. Reinout Wiers and colleagues (2011; replicated by Eberl et al., 2012) significantly diminished heavy drinkers’ approach bias for alcohol, as measured by the IAT, one year after lab-​based avoidance training using a joystick-​pulling task akin to those described earlier in Kawakami and colleagues’ (2007b) research (§1.1). Dasgupta and Asgari (2004) found that the implicit gender biases of undergraduate students at an all-​women’s college were reduced over the course of one year and that this reduction in implicit bias was mediated by the number of courses taken from female (i.e., counterstereotypical) professors (for a related study, see Beaman et  al., 2009). Moreover, adopting an implementation intention has been shown to affect indirect measures of attitudes three months past intervention (Webb et al., 2010). And, finally, Patricia Devine and colleagues (2012) demonstrated dramatically reduced IAT scores in subjects in a twelve-​week longitudinal study using a combination of the aforementioned interventions.20 Despite these promising results, however, none of these studies have investigated the durability of interventions as an isolated independent variable in an extended longitudinal study.21 Doing so is the next step in testing the durability of interventions like these. A helpful distinction to take into account for future research may be between those interventions designed to change the associations underlying one’s implicit attitudes and those interventions designed to heighten agents’ control over the activation of those associations.22 Originally, many prejudice-​reduction interventions were association-​based (i.e., aimed at changing the underlying associations). 20   However, see Forscher et al. (2016) for a comparatively sobering meta-​analysis of the stability of change in implicit attitudes after interventions. See the Appendix for brief discussion. 21   The exception is Webb et al. (2010). See also Calvin Lai et al. (2016), who found that nine rapid interventions that produced immediate changes in IAT scores had no significant lasting effects on IAT scores several hours to several days later. This finding suggests that a magic bullet—​i.e., a rapid and simple intervention—​for long-​term prejudice reduction is unlikely to exist. But see later in the text for discussion about more complex multipronged approaches to implicit attitude change, which I believe are more likely to create lasting change, particularly if they involve repeated practice of interventions within daily life settings. 22   I  draw this distinction from Lai et  al. (2013), although I  note that the distinction is in some respects blurry. Identifying changes in underlying association is tricky because agents’ control over activated associations influences indirect measures like the IAT. Process-​dissociation techniques like the Quad Model (Conrey et al., 2005) distinguish the influence of activated associations and control over them, but these techniques are based on statistical assumptions that are relative rather than absolute. Nevertheless, the distinction is useful for roughly categorizing kinds of interventions based on their presumed mechanisms for affecting behavior.

Ethics

198

Counterstereotype training, for example, is designed to change implicit attitudes themselves. So, too, is evaluative conditioning (Olson and Fazio, 2006) and increasing individuals’ exposure to images, film clips, and mental imagery depicting members of stigmatized groups acting in stereotype-​discordant ways (Dasgupta and Greenwald, 2001; Wittenbrink et al., 2001; Blair et al., 2002). Control-​based techniques are different in that they are alleged to prevent the expression of implicit attitudes without necessarily altering the underlying associations. As Saaid Mendoza and colleagues (2010, 513) put it: “Given recent research demonstrating that goal-​ driven responses can be engaged spontaneously with little deliberation (Amodio and Devine, 2010), it appears fruitful to also consider interventions that target the engagement of control, in addition to focusing on changing automatic associations.” Control-​based strategies have been buoyed by research showing that volitional control can be automatic, for example, through chronic goal-​setting (Moskowitz et al., 1999)  and nondeliberative goal pursuit (Amodio et  al., 2008). Implementation intentions are thought to be control-​based in this sense. Process dissociation analysis—​a statistical technique for pulling apart the various psychological contributions to performance on measures like the IAT23—​suggests that implementation intentions enhance controlled processing but do not affect automatic stereotyping itself (Mendoza et  al., 2010). Similarly, according to the Self-​Regulation of Prejudice (SRP) model (Monteith, 1993; Monteith et al., 2002), individuals who are motivated to control their prejudiced responses can create “cues for control” so that they learn to notice their prejudiced responses and the affective discomfort caused by the inconsistency of those responses with their egalitarian goals. The SRP is by definition a control-​based strategy; it requires either “top-​down” deliberative conflict monitoring or “bottom-​up” automated conflict monitoring between intact prejudiced associations and egalitarian intentions. This distinction between association-​and control-​based interventions may be relevant given that one or the other of these kinds of techniques may prove more durable. One possibility is that, in absolute terms (i.e., regardless of attitude or behavioral measure), control-​based strategies will have longer-​lasting effects on indirect measures of attitudes as well as on behavior, compared with association-​based interventions. Control-​based strategies offer individuals ways to implement the goals that many people possess already, many of which are inherently long-​term (e.g., getting tenure, eating healthy) and are made more accessible through intervention (Webb and Sheeran, 2008). This prediction is in keeping with extant data on the durability of interventions based on implementation intentions (e.g., Webb et  al., 2010). By contrast, association-​based strategies may be overridden by renewed exposure to stereotype-​consistent images in daily life. A  rival hypothesis, however, is that control-​based strategies will be less durable in absolute terms than association-​based   See the discussion of the Quad Model (Conrey et al., 2005) in Chapter 6.

23

The Habit Stanc e

199

strategies because control-​based strategies rely on individuals being motivated to implement them (not to mention being in conditions favorable to self-​control, such as being fed and well-​slept). For example, Devine and colleagues (2012) found that individuals who report being more concerned about discrimination are more likely to use intervention strategies and show greater reduction in implicit bias over time. This finding suggests that the durability of control-​based strategies may be limited, because individuals’ motivation to be unbiased can be temporary or inconsistent (e.g., because the goal to act unbiased can become deactivated after individuals satisfy it; Monin and Miller, 2001). Association-​based interventions might therefore be more durable than control-​based interventions if the effectiveness of the former do not depend on the sustained activation of individuals’ goals. While the evidence is nascent but promising that habit stance techniques can have lasting effects on implicit attitudes, it is indeed not yet clear how broad these effects can be. Implementation intentions, for example, seem to be most effective when they are very specific. One must commit oneself to noticing a particular cue—​ for example, “If I see a gun!”—​and enacting a specific behavioral response—​“then I will shoot!” But, of course, there are myriad other situations in which a relevant association—​in this case, a black–​danger association—​can manifest. One wants not just to perform better on a shooter bias test or to shoot more accurately if one were a police officer. If on a jury, one wants to deliberate without being influenced by the Afrocentricity of the defendant’s facial features (Eberhardt et  al., 2006); while walking down the street, one wants to display friendly, not aggressive or defensive, micro-​behavior toward black people (Dovidio et al., 2002); when interacting with children, one wants to avoid perceiving black boys as older and more prone to criminality than white boys (Goff, 2014). An “If I see a gun, then I will shoot!” plan is unlikely to improve one’s behavior in all (or any) of these situations. As Stewart and Payne (2008, 1334) write, “The social import of stereotypes is that they draw sweeping generalizations based on broad social categories. The most useful antistereotyping strategy would be one whose remedy is equally sweeping, and applies to the entire category.” As with the worry about durability, it is an empirical question how broad the effects of habit stance interventions can be. In some cases, testing this is straightforward. In the case of implementation intentions, for example, one can look to see just how broad a formulation might work (e.g., “If she is talking, then I won’t!”).24 It is also important to be reminded of how new this research is. Researchers initially believed that implicit attitudes were relatively static and difficult to change (Bargh, 1999; Devine, 1989; Wilson et al., 2000), and it has been only since around the year 2000—​with some exceptions—​that significant research effort has been put into investigating interventions. So it is reasonable to hope that big breakthroughs   Thanks to Louise Antony for this example.

24

200

Ethics

are still to come. Moreover, there is already some evidence that the effects of some habit stance techniques may be broader than one might initially expect. For example, Gawronski and colleagues (2008) found that counterstereotype race training (specifically, training participants to affirm counterstereotypes—​e.g., “intelligent” and “wealthy”—​about black people) reduced their implicit racial prejudice. That is, learning to affirm specific counterstereotypes led participants to implicitly like black people more. Liking is far broader than stereotyping. When we like or dislike a group, we act in many specific ways consistent with this attitude. What this suggests is that targeting specific implicit attitudes in interventions may affect the suite of attitudes to which they are related. We can find additional evidence for the potential broadness of these kinds of techniques by looking again at the difference between association-​and control-​ based interventions. If a person is generally less likely to automatically stereotype people on the basis of race, this should have more widespread effects on behavior across a range of contexts, even when the person lacks the motivation or opportunity to control it. As such, it is possible that association-​based interventions are likely to have greater effects on a wider range of behaviors than control-​based interventions (Kawakami et al., 2000). On the other hand, control-​based interventions may have larger effects on “niche-​specific” behavior. Ultimately, durable and broadly effective strategies for changing and regulating implicit attitudes will likely take a multipronged approach. This is especially likely as circumstances change or as one moves into new environments, where the demands of the situation require recalibrating one’s associations. When slower court surfaces were introduced in professional tennis, for example, players presumably had to exert top-​down control at first in order to begin the process of learning new habits. But this was also presumably accompanied by association-​based retraining, such as the rote repetition of backcourt shot sequences (rather than net-​attacking sequences). Indeed, Devine and colleagues (2012) label their multipronged approach to long-​term implicit attitude change a “prejudice habit breaking intervention.” The next step is to test the extent to which specific interventions work and then to test how they might be combined. Combining various interventions might be mutually reinforcing in a way that makes their combination stronger than the sum of the parts, perhaps by “getting the ball rolling” on self-​regulation. Relatedly, future research may (and should) consider whether different forms of presentation of interventions affect participants’ use of these interventions outside the laboratory. Does it matter, for instance, if an intervention is described to participants as a form of control, change, self-​control, self-​improvement, or the like? Will people be less motivated to use self-​regulatory tools that are described as “changing attitudes” because of privacy concerns or fears about mental manipulation, or simply because of perceptions of the difficulty of changing their attitudes? Will interventions that appeal to one’s sense of autonomy be more successful? These open questions point to the possibility of fruitful discoveries to come, some of

The Habit Stanc e

201

which will hopefully alleviate current reasonable worries about habit stance techniques for implicit attitude change.

2.2 Cheating A different kind of broadly “Kantian” worry focuses on the nature of “moral credit” and virtue.25 There are (at least) two different (albeit related) ways to understand this worry. I have discussed versions of both worries earlier, in particular in Chapters 4 and 5. The discussion here focuses on how these worries apply to my account of the habit stance. One version of the worry is that actions based on “mere” inclinations can be disastrous because they aren’t guided by moral sensibilities. As a result, an approach to the self-​regulation of implicit attitudes focused on habit change, without a specific focus on improving moral sensibilities, would be limited and perhaps even counterproductive. Barbara Herman (1981, 364–​365) explicates the Kantian concern about “sympathy” unguided by morality in this way. She imagines a person full of sympathy for others who sees someone struggling, late at night, with a heavy package at the back door of the Museum of Fine Arts. If such a person acts only on the basis of an immediate inclination to help others out, then she might end up abetting an art thief. Herman’s point is that even “good” inclinations can lead to terrible outcomes if they’re not guided by a genuinely moral sense. (This way of putting the worry might be too consequentialist for some Kantians.) She puts the point strongly: “We need not pursue the example to see its point: the class of actions that follow from the inclination to help others is not a subset of the class of right or dutiful actions” (1981, 365). The second way to understand this worry focuses on what makes having a moral sense praiseworthy. Some argue that mere inclinations cannot, by definition, be morally praiseworthy, because they are unguided by moral reasons. The key distinction is sometimes drawn in terms of the difference between acting “from virtue” and acting “in accord with virtue.” A person who acts from virtue acts for the right (moral) reasons. Contemporary theorists draw related distinctions. For example, Levy (2014) argues that acting from virtue requires one to be aware of the morally relevant features of one’s action (see Chapter 5). Acting from virtue, in other words, can be thought of as acting for moral reasons that one recognizes to be moral reasons. Both versions of what I’m calling the broadly “Kantian” worry seem to apply to the idea of the habit stance. Perhaps even with the most ethical implicit attitudes, a person will be no better off than Herman’s sympathetic person. After all, even the

  I place “Kantian” in scare quotes in order to emphasize that the following ideas may or may not reflect the actual ideas of Immanuel Kant. 25

202

Ethics

most ethical implicit attitudes will give rise to spontaneous reactions, and these reactions seem tied to the contexts in which they were learned. Their domain of skillful and appropriate deployment might be worryingly narrow, then. Moreover one might worry that adopting the habit stance does not require one to act from virtue. There is little reason to think that rote practice, pre-​commitment, and context regulation put one in a position of acting for moral reasons that one recognizes to be moral. Nor do these strategies seem poised to boost one’s awareness of any particular moral reasons for action. Regarding the first worry, I think things are considerably more complex than Herman’s example ostensibly illustrating the pitfalls of misguided inclination suggests. Her example of the sympathetic person who stupidly abets an art thief is a caricature. In reality, most people’s sympathetic inclinations are not blunt, one-​size-​fits-​all responses to the world. Rather, most people’s “mere” inclinations themselves can home in on key cues that determine whether this is a situation requiring giving the person in need a hand or giving the police a call. Indeed, if anything, it strikes me that the greatest difficulty is not usually in deciding, on the basis of moral sense, whether to help or hinder what another person is trying to do, although, of course, situations like this sometimes arise. What’s far more difficult is simply taking action when it’s morally required. Adopting the habit stance in order to cultivate better spontaneous responses is directly suited to solving this problem. Of course, this does not mean that our implicit attitudes always get it right (as I’ve been at pains to show throughout this book). As Railton puts it: Statistical learning and empathy are not magic—​like perception, they can afford only prima facie, defeasible epistemic justification. And—​again, like perception itself—​they are subject to capacity limitations and can be only as informative as the native sensitivities, experiential history, and acquired categories or concepts they can bring to bear. If these are impoverished, unrepresentative, or biased, so will be our statistical and empathic responses. Discrepancy-​reduction learning is good at reducing the effects of initial biases through experience (“washing out priors”), but not if the experiences themselves are biased in the same ways—​as, arguably, is often the case in social prejudice. It therefore is of the first importance to epistemology and morality that we are beings who can critically scrutinize our intuitive responses. (2014, 846) But, like me, Railton defends a view of inclination according to which our spontaneous responses are not “dumb” one-​size-​fits-​all reflexes. His view is elaborated in terms of the epistemic worth of intuition and focuses on identifying the circumstances in which our unreasoned intuitions are and are not likely to be reliable.

The Habit Stanc e

203

My defense of the practical intelligence that can be embodied in intuition is not meant to encourage uncritical acceptance of “intuitions.” Rather, it seeks to identify actual processes of learning and representation that would enable us to see more clearly where our intuitions might be expected to be more reliable, but also where they might be expected to be less. (2014, 846) One way to understand the aim of this chapter is in terms of identifying some key conditions under which our implicit attitudes can be expected to be reliable in this sense. A related response to the first version of the worry draws inspiration from the recent debate over “situationism” and virtue ethics. In short, virtue ethicists argue that morality stems from the cultivation of virtuous and broad-​based character traits (e.g., Hursthouse, 1999). But critics have argued that virtuous and broad-​based character traits do not exist (Harman, 1999; Doris, 2002). The reason for this, the critics argue, is that human behavior is pervasively susceptible to the effects of surprising features of the situations in which we find ourselves. The situationist critics argue that exposure to seemingly trivial things—​like whether one happens to luckily find a dime (Isen and Levin, 1972) or whether one happens to be in a hurry (Darley and Batson, 1973)—​ is much better at predicting a person’s behavior than are her putative character traits. Supposedly mean people will act nicely if they find a lucky dime, and supposedly nice people will act meanly if they’re in a rush. In other words, people don’t typically have virtuous and broad-​based character traits. Rather, their behavior is largely a reflection of the situation in which they find themselves. Of course, defenders of virtue ethics have responded in a number of ways (e.g., Kamtekar, 2004; Annas, 2008). The similarity between the situationist debate and the first “Kantian” worry about habit stance techniques for implicit attitude change is this: in both cases, critics worry that there is no “there” there. In the case of situationism, critics argue that the broad-​based, multitrack character traits at the heart of virtue ethics don’t really exist. If these don’t exist, then human behavior seems to be like grass blowing in the wind, lacking the core thing that virtue ethicists purport guides right action. The worry about mere inclination is analogous. Without online guidance of behavior by some overarching, reflective, moral sense, we will similarly be left rudderless, again like grass blowing in the wind. This is what we are to take away from Herman’s example. The sympathetic person has good motives but is essentially rudderless, bluntly doling out empathy everywhere, even where it’s inappropriate. In the case of situationism, the fact is, though, that character traits do exist. And this is instructive about implicit attitudes. There is a well-​established science of character. It identifies five central traits, which appear to be culturally universal and relatively stable across the life span ( John and Srivastava, 1999): openness, conscientiousness, extroversion, agreeableness, and neuroticism.26 The core of the debate about situationism and virtue ethics is not, therefore, whether broad-​based traits   For a review of the current science of character and personality, see Fleeson et al. (2015).

26

204

Ethics

exist. Rather, the core of the debate is (or should be) about whether the broad-​ based traits that do exist belong on any list of virtues (Prinz, 2009). The Big Five are not virtues per se. They are dispositions to take risks, be outgoing, feel anxious, and so on. Crucially, they can cut both ways when it comes to ethics. Anxiety can lead one to be extremely cowardly or extremely considerate. Even “conscientiousness,” which sounds virtuous, is really just a disposition to be self-​disciplined, organized, and tidy. And certainly some of history’s most vicious people have been conscientious in this sense. That said, the Big Five are not just irrelevant to virtue. Virtues may be built out of specific combinations of character traits, deployed under the right circumstances. Research may find matrices of traits that line up closely with particular virtues. Similarly, what some call a moral sense might be constructed out of the small shifts in attitudes engendered by habit stance techniques. For example, practicing approach-​oriented behavior toward people stereotyped as violent, using Kawakami-​style training, is not, just as such, virtuous. Herman might imagine a white person approaching a black man who clearly wants to be left alone; that is, an approach intuition unguided by moral sense. But practicing approach-​oriented behavior in the right way, over time, such that the learning mechanisms embedded in one’s implicit attitudes can incorporate feedback stemming from successes and failures, is not likely to generate this result. Rather, it is more likely to result in a spontaneous social sensibility for when and how to approach just those people whom it is appropriate to approach. Regarding the second version of the worry—​focused on the importance of acting from virtue—​it is important to remember that we typically have very little grasp of the competencies embedded in our implicit attitudes. So it is an extremely high bar to cross to think that our implicit attitudes are praiseworthy only when we are aware of the morally relevant features of our actions. It is also worth recalling the claim of Chapter  4, that implicit attitudes are reflective of agents’ character. The ethical quality of these attitudes, then, reflects on us too. Perhaps this can go some way toward assuaging the worry that we don’t act for explicit moral reasons when we reshape and act upon our implicit attitudes. More broadly, I think it is misguided to worry that acting well is the kind of thing that is susceptible to cheating, at least in the context of considering moral credit and the habit stance. It strikes me that regulating one’s implicit attitudes is more like striving for happiness than it is like pursuing full-​blown morality in this sense. And happiness, it seems to me, is less susceptible to intuitions about cheating than is morality. As Arpaly (2015) put it in a discussion of some people’s hesitance to take psychoactive drugs to regulate mood disorders like depression, out of sense that doing so is tantamount to cheating: You might feel like taking medication would be “cheating,” a shortcut to eudaimonia that doesn’t go through virtue. Wrong! Happiness is not like an award, gained fairly or unfairly. Happiness is more like American

The Habit Stanc e

205

citizenship: some people have it because they were born with it, some perhaps get it through marriage, some have to work for it. It’s not cheating to find a non-​torturous way to get an advantage that other people have from birth. Regulating our implicit attitudes strikes me as being like American citizenship—​ and thus like happiness—​in this way. Our implicit attitudes are often victims or beneficiaries of moral luck, and, all other things being equal, any tactic for improving them seems worthwhile. (Consider also the example of quitting smoking. Are those who quit using nicotine patches rather than going cold turkey any less admirable?) There is, of course, the fact that people often experience greater rewards when they feel as if they worked hard for something. Hiking to the top of Mt. Washington is more rewarding to many people than driving to the top. In this sense, happiness seems susceptible to (perceptions about) cheating. But this is a psychological phenomenon, not a moral one. If data show that implicit attitudes improve only when people feel as if they have worked hard to change them—​in some earnest moral way—​then so be it. The idea of the habit stance may need to be amended to incorporate this hypothetical finding. But this is not a reason to think that one doesn’t deserve moral credit for working to improve one’s implicit attitudes using the habit stance. Of course, I don’t expect these ideas to change the mind of anyone who thinks that adopting the habit stance isn’t genuinely morally worthwhile. This isn’t because Kantians (or “Kantians”) about moral worth are stubborn. I  simply haven’t provided any real argument to obviate the distinction between acting in accord with virtue and acting from virtue. That task is too tall for this domain. But I hope to have at least raised concerns about its applicability in the case of implicit attitudes. Improving these through use of the habit stance is clearly worthwhile, and the kind of worth involved strikes me, at least, as relatively self-​standing.

3. Conclusion I’ve argued for what I call a habit stance approach to the ethical improvement of our implicit attitudes. I have proposed this approach in contrast to the idea, discussed in the preceding chapter, that deliberation is necessary and always recommended for cultivating better implicit attitudes. The habit stance approach largely falls out from the current state of empirical research on what sorts of techniques are effective for implicit attitude change. It also should seem consistent with the account of implicit attitudes I have given, as sui generis states, different in kind from our more familiar beliefs and values, yet reflective nevertheless upon some meaningful part of who we are as agents. It is by treating our implicit attitudes as if they were habits—​packages of thought, feeling, and behavior—​that we can make them better.

8

Conclusion

The central contention of this book has been that understanding the two faces of spontaneity—​its virtues and vices—​requires understanding what I have called the implicit mind. And to do this I’ve considered three sets of issues. In Chapters 2 and 3, I focused on the nature of the mental states that make up the implicit mind. I argued that in many moments of our lives we are not moved to act by brute forces, yet neither do we move ourselves to act by reasoning on the basis of our beliefs and desires. In banal cases of orienting ourselves around objects and other people, in inspiring cases of acting spontaneously and creatively, and in maddening and morally worrying cases where biases and prejudice affect what we do, we enact complex attitudes involving rapid and interwoven thoughts, feelings, motor impulses, and feedback learning. I’ve called these complex states implicit attitudes and have distinguished them from reflexes, mere associations, beliefs, and dispositions, as well as from their closest theoretical cousins, aliefs. In Chapters  4 and 5, I  considered the relationship between implicit attitudes and the self. These states give rise to actions that seem neither unowned nor fully owned. Museumgoers and Huck and police offers affected by shooter bias reveal meaningful things about themselves in their spontaneous actions, I’ve argued. What is revealed may be relatively minor. How the museumgoer makes her way around the large painting tells us comparatively little about her, in contrast to what her opinion as to whether the painting is a masterpiece or a fraud might tell us. Nor do these spontaneous reactions license holding her responsible for her action, in the sense that she has met or failed to meet some obligation or that she is, even in principle, capable of answering for her action. But when even this minor action is patterned over time, involves feelings that reflect upon what she cares about, and displays the right kinds of connections to other elements of her mind, it tells us something meaningful about her. It gives us information about what kind of a character she has, perhaps that in this sort of context she is patient or impatient, an optimizer or satisficer. These aren’t deep truths about her in the sense that they give the final verdict on who she is. Character is a mosaic concept. And the ways in which we are spontaneous is part of this mosaic, even when our spontaneity evades or conflicts with our reasons or our awareness of our reasons for action. 206

Conclu s ion

207

Finally, in Chapters 6 and 7, I examined how ethics and spontaneity interact. How can we move beyond Vitruvius’s unhelpful advice to “trust your instincts . . . unless your instincts are terrible”? I’ve argued that becoming more virtuous in our spontaneity involves planning and deliberation, but that thinking carefully about how and when to be spontaneous is not always necessary, and sometimes it can be distracting and even costly. Retraining our implicit attitudes, sometimes in ways that flatly push against our self-​conception as deliberative agents, is possible and promising. While there are long-​ standing traditions in ethics focused on this, the relevant science of self-​regulation is new. So far, I’ve argued, it tells us that the ethics of spontaneity requires a blend of foci, including what I’ve called intentional, physical, and design elements, and none of these alone. The full package amounts to cultivating better implicit attitudes as if they were habits. All of this is pluralist and incomplete, as I foreshadowed in the Introduction. It is pluralist about the kinds of mental states that lead us to act and that can lead us to act well; about how and what kinds of actions might reflect upon me as an agent; about how to cultivate better implicit attitudes in order to act more virtuously and spontaneously. Incompleteness intrudes at each of these junctions. I have not given necessary and sufficient conditions for a state to be an implicit attitude. Rather, I have sketched the paradigmatic features of implicit attitudes—​their FTBA components—​and argued for their uniqueness in cognitive taxonomy. I have not said exactly when agents ought to be praised or blamed for their spontaneous inclinations. Rather, I  have laid the groundwork for the idea that these inclinations shed light on our character, even if they fall short of being the sorts of actions for which we must answer or be held accountable. And I have not incorporated the ineliminable importance of practical deliberation into my recommendations for implicit attitude change, even though a deeply important element of such change is believing it to be necessary and worthwhile. What I have done, I think, is pushed back against the historical emphasis (in the Western philosophical tradition, at least) on the overriding virtues of deliberation. And I have outlined data-​ supported tactics for cultivating spontaneous inclinations that match what I assume are common moral aims. While alternative interpretations of each of the cases I’ve discussed are available, the shared features of these cases illuminate a pervasive feature of our lives: actions the psychology of which is neither reflexive nor reasoned; actions that reflect upon us as agents but not upon what we know or who we take ourselves to be; and actions the ethical cultivation of which demand not just planning and deliberating but also, centrally, pre-​committing to plans, attending to our contexts, and, as Bruce Gemmel—​the coach of arguably the best swimmer of all time, Katie Ledecky—​ said, just doing the damn work.1   Dave Sheinin writes, “Gemmell reacts with a combination of bemusement and annoyance when people try to divine the ‘secret’ to Ledecky’s success, as if it’s some sort of mathematical formula that can be solved by anyone with a Speedo and a pair of goggles. A few weeks ago, a website 1

Conclusion

208

Many open questions remain, not only at these junctures and in tightening the characteristics of the family resemblance I’ve depicted, but also in connecting this account of the implicit mind to ongoing research that bears upon, and sometimes rivals, the claims I have made along the way. My arguments for the sui generis structure of implicit attitudes draw upon affective theories of perception, for example, but it is still unclear whether all forms of perception are affective in the way some theorists suggest. Similarly, new theories of practical inference with relatively minimalist demands—​compared with the more classical accounts of inference from which I  draw—​may show that implicit attitudes are capable of figuring into certain kinds of rationalizing explanation.2 This bears upon perhaps the largest open question facing Chapters 2 and 3: Under what conditions do implicit attitudes form and change? I have given arguments based on the extant data, but the entire stream of research is relatively young. Future studies will hopefully clarify, for example, whether implicit attitudes change when agents are presented with persuasive arguments, and if they do, why they do. Future theorizing about implicit attitudes and responsibility will likely move beyond the focus I’ve had on individuals’ minds, to consider various possible forms of collective responsibility for unintended harms and how these interface with concepts like attributability and accountability. One avenue may take up a different target: not individuals but collectives themselves. Are corporations, neighborhoods, or even nations responsible for the spontaneous actions of their members in a nonadditive way (i.e., in a way that is more than the sum of the individuals’ own responsibility)? In some contexts this will be a question for legal philosophy. Can implicit bias, for example, count as evidence of disparate impact in the absence of discriminatory intent? In other contexts, this may be a question for evolutionary psychology. As some have theorized about the functional role of disgust and other moral emotions, have implicit attitudes evolved to enforce moral norms? If so, does this mean that these attitudes are in any way morally informative or that groups are more or less responsible for them? In other contexts still, this may be a question about the explanatory power and assumptions embedded in various kinds of social science. Critics of research on implicit bias have focused on  the ostensible limits of psychological explanations of discrimination. For instance, while acknowledging that there is space for attention to implicit bias in social critique, Sally Haslanger argues that it is “only a small space,” because “the focus on individuals (and their attitudes) occludes the injustices that pervade the structural and cultural context and the ways called SwimmingScience.net promoted a Twitter story called ‘40 Must Do Katie Ledecky Training Secrets.’ Gemmell couldn’t let that go by unchallenged. ‘Tip #41,’ he tweeted in reply. ‘Just do the damn work.’ ” https://​www.washingtonpost.com/​sports/​olympics/​how-​katie-​ledecky-​became-​better-​at-​ swimming-​than-​anyone-​is-​at-​anything/​2016/​06/​23/​01933534-​2f31-​11e6-​9b37-​42985f6a265c_​ story.html.   See, e.g., Buckner (2017).

2

Conclu s ion

209

that the context both constrains and enables our action. It reinforces fictional conceptions of autonomy and self-​determination that prevents us from taking responsibility for our social milieu (social meanings, social relations, and social structures)” (2015, 10). I think my account of implicit attitudes provides means for a less fictional account of autonomy than those Haslanger might have in mind, but vindicating this would take much work. An intriguing set of questions facing the practical ethics of spontaneity focuses on the concept of self-​trust. Whether and when we trust others has moral stakes, as moral psychologists like Patricia Hawley (2012) and Meena Krishnamurthy (2015) have shown. Do these stakes apply equivalently in the case of self-​trust? What are the general conditions under which we ought to trust ourselves, as some theorists suggest is the hallmark of expertise? Self-​trust of the sort I imagine here is in tension with what I take to be one of the imperatives of practical deliberation, which is that it represents a check against the vices of our spontaneous inclinations. Being deliberative is, in some ways, an expression of humility, of recognizing that we are all subject to bias, impulsivity, and so on. But are there forms of deliberation that perhaps skirt this tension? I have emphasized the nondeliberative elements of coaching in skill learning, but perhaps other features are more conducive to a reflective or quasi-​ intellectualist orientation. Historians of philosophy may find some elements in an Aristotelian conception of motivation, for example, which some say distinguishes skill from virtue; perhaps fresher approaches may be found in non-​Western ethical traditions. I ended the Introduction by suggesting that I would be satisfied by convincing the reader that a fruitful way to understand both the virtues and vices of spontaneity is by understanding the implicit mind, even if some of the features of the implicit mind as I  describe it are vague, confused, or flat-​out wrong. Another way to put this is that in identifying the phenomenon of interest and offering an account of it, I incline more toward lumping than splitting. Crudely—​as a lumper like me would say—​lumping involves answering questions by placing phenomena into categories that illuminate broad issues. Lumpers focus more on similarities than differences. Splitters answer questions by identifying key differences between phenomena, with the aim of refining definitions and categories. Lumping and splitting are both necessary for making intellectual progress, I believe. If this work inspires splitters more skilled than me to refine the concept of the implicit mind, in the service of better understanding what we do when we act spontaneously, I’ll be deeply satisfied.

Appendix

ME A SURES, METHODS, AND PSYCHOLOGICAL SCIENCE

I briefly described how implicit attitudes are measured in psychological science in the Introduction. In my opinion, the ability to measure implicit attitudes represents one of the major advancements in the sciences of the mind in the twentieth century. But controversies surround both implicit attitude research and the sciences of the mind writ large.1 In this appendix, I explain how the Implicit Association Test (IAT) works in more detail and compare it with other indirect measures of attitudes (§1). Then, I describe and discuss critiques of some of the psychometric properties of the IAT, which is the most widely used measure of implicit attitudes, and identify additional current open questions facing IAT research (§2). This discussion leads into a broader one about the status of psychological science, in particular the reproducibility of experimental results in social psychology (§3). My aim in discussing the replication crisis is not to adjudicate its significance or to make novel recommendations to researchers, but rather to explain the principles I have used in writing this book, principles underwriting the confidence I have in the experimental research I’ve presented.

1.  The Measurement of Implicit Attitudes When discussing research on implicit attitudes (as they are usually understood in psychology), I have relied mostly on IAT research. The IAT is a reaction time meas­ ure. It assesses participants’ ability to sort words, pictures, or names into categories as fast as possible, while making as few errors as possible. In the following examples, 1   In this appendix, I do not explicitly discuss all of the areas of research presented in this book (e.g., I do not discuss methodological issues facing research on expertise and skill acquisition). While I mean the broad discussion of replicability and methodological principles to cover these areas, I  focus on psychometric issues pertaining to research on implicit social cognition.

211

Appendix

212

the correct way to sort the name “Michelle” would be left (Figure A.1) and right (Figure A.2), and the correct way to sort the word “Business” would be left (Figure A.3) and right (Figure A.4). One computes an IAT score by comparing speed and error rates on the “blocks” (or sets of trials) in which the pairing of concepts is consistent with common stereotypes (Figures A.1 and A.3) to the speed and error rates on the blocks in which the pairing of the concepts is inconsistent with common stereotypes (Figures A.2 and A.4).2 Most people are faster and make fewer errors on stereotype-​consistent trials than on stereotype-​inconsistent trials. While this “gender–​career” IAT pairs concepts (male and career), other IATs, such as the black–​w hite race evaluation IAT, pair a concept with an evaluation (e.g., black and “bad”).3 Other IATs test implicit attitudes toward body size, age, sexual orientation, and so on (including more relatively banal targets, like brand preferences). More than 16 million unique participants had taken an IAT as of 2014 (B. A. Nosek, pers. com.). One review (Nosek et al., 2007), which examined the results of over 700,00 subjects’ scores on the black-​white race evaluation IAT, found that more than 70% of white participants more easily associated black faces with negative words (e.g., war, bad) and white faces with positive words (e.g., peace, good) than the inverse (i.e., black faces with positive words and white faces with negative words). The researchers consider this an implicit preference for white faces over black faces. In this study, black participants on average showed a very slight preference for black faces over white faces. This is roughly consistent with other studies showing that approximately 40% of black participants demonstrate an implicit in-​group preference for black faces over white faces, 20% show no preference, and 40% demonstrate an implicit out-​group preference for white faces over black faces (Nosek et al., 2002, 2007; Ashburn-​Nardo et al., 2003; Dasgupta, 2004; Xu et al., 2014). Although the IAT remains the most popular indirect measure of attitudes, it is far from the only one.4 A  number of variations of priming tasks are widely used   This is how an IAT “D score” is calculated. There are other ways of scoring the IAT too.   See the discussion in Chapter 2 of the view that these two types of measures assess two separate constructs: implicit stereotypes and implicit evaluations (or prejudices). 4   Throughout, I have referred to the IAT and other measures of implicit attitudes as “indirect.” In Chapter 1, I said that these tests are indirect in the sense that people are not asked about their feelings or thoughts directly. Sometimes the term “implicit measure” is used in the literature, rather than “indirect measure.” I follow the recommendation of Jan De Houwer and colleagues (2009) that the terms “direct” and “indirect” be used to describe characteristics of measurement techniques and the terms “implicit” and “explicit” to describe characteristics of the psychological constructs assessed by those techniques. Note, though, that “direct” and “indirect” can also refer to different kinds of explicit measures. For example, a survey that asks, “What do you think of black people?” is explicit and direct, while one that asks, “What do you think about Darnel?” is explicit and indirect (because the judgment is explicit, but the content of what is being judged [i.e., race] is inferred). The distinction between direct and indirect 2 3

Male or Career

Female or Family

Michelle

Figure A.1 

Female or Career

Male or Family

Michelle

Figure A.2 

Female or Family

Male or Career

Business

Figure A.3 

Female or Career

Male or Family

Business

Figure A.4 

Appendix

215

(e.g., evaluative priming (Fazio et al., 1995), semantic priming (Banaji and Hardin, 1996), and the Affect Misattribution Procedure (AMP; Payne et al., 2005)). A “second generation” of categorization-​based measures has also been developed in order to improve psychometric validity. For example, the Go/​No-​go Association Task (GNAT; Nosek and Banaji, 2001) presents subjects with one target object rather than two in order to determine whether preferences or aversions are primarily responsible for scores on the standard IAT (e.g., on a measure of racial attitudes, whether one has an implicit preference for whites or an implicit aversion to blacks; Brewer, 1999). I have relied mostly on the IAT, but also, to a lesser degree, on the AMP, not only because these are among the most commonly used measures of implicit attitudes, but also because reviews show them to be the most reliable indirect measures of attitudes (Bar-​Anan and Nosek, 2014; Payne and Lundberg, 2014).5 In assessing seven indirect measures, Bar-​Anan and Nosek (2014) used the following evaluation criteria: • Internal consistency (i.e., the consistency of response across items within the test) • Test-​retest reliability (i.e., the stability of test results within subjects over time) • Sensitivity to group differences (i.e., whether test results reflect expected differences in response between groups, such as how black and white participants score on the black–​white race evaluation IAT) • Correlation with other indirect and direct measures of the same topics • Measurement of single-​category evaluation (i.e., how well the measure can discriminate evaluations of distinct categories, such as liking white people vs. disliking black people) • Sensitivity to non-​extreme attitudes (i.e., how sensitive the measure is to meaningful differences in response when extreme responses have been removed from the data set) • Effects of data exclusion (i.e., how likely participants are to follow the instructions and complete the measure appropriately) I discuss some of these evaluation criteria in the following section. measures is also relative rather than absolute. Even in some direct measures, such as personality inventories, subjects may not be completely aware of what is being studied. It is important to note, finally, that in indirect tests subjects may be aware of what is being measured. One ought not to conflate the idea of assessing a construct with a measure that does not presuppose introspective availability with the idea of the assessed construct being introspectively unavailable (Payne and Gawronski, 2010).   Bar-​Anan and Nosek (2014) are less sanguine about the reliability of the AMP once outliers with strong explicit attitudes toward targets are removed from the sample. Payne and Kristjen Lundberg (2014) present several plausible replies to this critique, however. 5

216

Appendix

2. Psychometrics There are a number of challenges facing IAT research. I focus on those that I believe to be the most significant and that have arisen in the philosophical literature. There is, I believe, significant room for improvement in the design of the IAT. One of my hopes is that the account of implicit attitudes I have presented will instigate such improvements. As I discuss later (§2.3), IAT measures can be improved by targeting more specific attitudes in more specific contexts.

2.1  Correlation between Indirect Measures In Chapter  3, I  discussed the concern that indirect measures of attitudes do not correlate strongly with each other. If a set of measures are valid representations of the same construct, then they should, ceteris paribus, correlate with one another. However, I argued in Chapter 3 that weak correlations between some indirect attitude measures appear to reflect differences in the content of what is being measured (e.g., self-​esteem, race, or political evaluations), with the weakest correlations found when the most complex concepts are targeted. A second possibility is that not all indirect measures are as valid as others (Bar-​ Anan and Nosek, 2014; Payne and Lundberg, 2014). One should not expect valid measures to correlate with measures with weaker psychometric properties. One finding that seems to speak against this possibility, however, is that the most well-​ validated measures—​variations of the IAT and the AMP—​don’t always strongly correlate. This suggests that low correlations between indirect measures aren’t only due to some measures having more validity than others. However, it is not clear that comparisons of the IAT and the AMP have controlled for the content of what was measured, so even this point must be taken cautiously. A third option for explaining weak correlations between some indirect measures, as Bar-​Anan and Nosek (2014) and Machery (2016) suggest, is that different measures, or subsets of measures, reflect different components of implicit cognition. The AMP, for example, works on the premise of a three-​step process (Loersch and Payne, 2016). A prime (e.g., a black face) stimulates the accessibility of a general concept (e.g., danger). That concept is then misattributed by the subject to the perception of a target (e.g., a degraded image of either a gun or a pliers). The misattributed content of the prime is then used by the subject to answer the question asked by the measure (e.g., What is that, a gun or a pair of pliers?). On the face of it, what this procedure entails is significantly different from what happens in a categorization task, like the IAT. Many instantiations of the AMP also use primes that are highly affectively arousing for targeted subjects, such as images of men kissing for heterosexual subjects. All of this is suggestive of the proposal that different measures or subsets of measures reflect different components of implicit cognition. This isn’t devastating for implicit attitude

Appendix

217

research, of course. One possibility is that it favors a dispositional view of implicit attitudes like Machery’s (2016; see the discussion in Chapter 3). Another possibility is that models of implicit attitudes that take them to be mental states that occur can come to make principled predictions about the conditions under which indirect measures will diverge. I speculate that this may be one virtue to come of the FTBA formula of implicit attitudes I have proposed. For example, I argued in Chapter 3 that the affective intensity of implicit attitudes—​the salience of a felt tension—​is a function of content-​specific, person-​specific, and context-​specific variables. Controlling for these variables across comparisons of indirect measures might reveal predictable correlations. For example, the correlation between an AMP using highly affective images of same-​sex couples kissing and an attitude IAT might become stronger, while the correlation between this AMP and a stereotyping IAT (the affective activation of which is lower than that of the attitude IAT) may become weaker.

2.2  Test-​Retest Reliability I also discussed in Chapter 3 the concern that indirect measures typically have low to moderate test-​retest reliability. This suggests that these measures may not reflect stable features of agents. Perhaps what indirect measures reveal are on-​the-​fly constructions that predominantly reflect situational variables. However, I  also mentioned in Chapter  3 that research by Gschwendner and colleagues has demonstrated one way in which IAT scores may become more stable over time within individuals. Gschwendner and colleagues (2008) assessed German participants’ implicit evaluations of German versus Turkish faces on an IAT and varied the background context during each block of the text (i.e., they manipulated the blank space on the computer screen immediately below the target images and attribute words). Participants in the experimental condition saw a picture of a mosque, while participants in the control condition saw a picture of a garden. Gschwendner and colleagues then compared the stability of participant scores over a two-​week period. The intra-​individual test-​retest reliability of the IAT tends to be low to moderate (.51 in one meta-​analysis; Hofmann et al., 2005), but the addition of the background picture in Gschwendner and colleagues’ study had a dramatic influence on this. Participants in the control condition had a low stability coefficient—​.29—​but participants in the experimental conditions had a high stability coefficient—​.72. This finding is methodologically significant for its ability to generate temporally stable IAT results. It should, I believe, dampen down the fear that the IAT reflects nothing more than on-​the-​fly constructions. Moreover, this research reflects some of the core principles of my account of implicit attitudes. In embedding images into the background of the IAT materials, Gschwendner and colleagues effectively brought the testing context into closer alignment with the content of the test. They

Appendix

218

incorporated the very elements into the measure that my account of implicit attitudes posits as components of them (e.g., context-​and content-​specific variables).6 It is important to note that Gschwendner and colleagues also found an interaction between chronic accessibility of the relevant concept in the experimental condition, but not in the control condition (i.e., participants for whom the concept Turkish is chronically accessible had greater test-​retest stability when the image of the mosque rather than the image of the garden was embedded in the IAT). This, too, speaks to the durability of test scores by improving features of the measure. And the very features being improved are those that reflect person-​specific variables—​such as the chronic availability of the concept Turkish—​that I’ve emphasized. The broad point here is not simply to defend the status quo. The work of Gschwendner and colleagues (2008) is suggestive of how IAT research can be improved. Targeting person-​specific and context-​specific features of attitudes can help to improve psychometric validity, for example, test-​retest reliability. This improvement may come at the expense of domain generality. That is, the increased ability to predict behavior given contextual constraints may entail that the measure won’t necessarily be predictive absent those constraints. I take this to represent a trade-​off facing experimental psychology generally, not a decrease in explanatory power as such. Measures that apply across a variety of contexts are less likely to have strong correlation coefficients, while measures that apply to more specific circumstances are more likely to be predictive, but only under those conditions.7

2.3  Predictive Validity The widest concern about indirect measures focuses on their ability to predict real-​world behavior. Critics have argued that the IAT in particular predicts behavior poorly, so much so that “the IAT provides little insight into who will discriminate against whom, and provides no more insight than explicit measures of bias” (Oswald et  al., 2013, 18). This conclusion emerges from Frederick Oswald and colleagues’ (2013) meta-​analysis of forty-​six published and unpublished reports, the overall finding of which was a correlational effect size of .148. This contrasts with Greenwald and colleagues’ (2003, 2009) meta-​analyses, which suggested that racially discriminatory behavior is better predicted by IAT measures than by self-​ report measures. Understanding the differences between these meta-​analyses is

  Another way to put this is that the embedded images reduce noise in the measure by holding fixed the meaning or value of the situation for participants. Thanks to Jonathan Phillips for this idea. 7   This is a version of the principles of correspondence (Ajzen and Fishbein, 1970, 1977)  and compatibility (Ajzen, 1998; Ajzen and Fishbein, 2005). The core idea of these principles is that the predictive power of attitudes increases when attitudes and behavior are measured at the same level of specificity. For example, attitudes about birth control pills are more predictive of the use of birth control pills than are attitudes about birth control (Davidson and Jaccard, 1979). 6

Appendix

219

important. Once they are understood, I do not believe that Oswald and colleagues’ normative claim—​that the IAT is a poor tool that provides no insight into discriminatory behavior—​is warranted. First, predicting behavior is difficult. Research on implicit social cognition partly arose out of the recognition that self-​report measures of attitudes don’t predict behavior very well. This is particularly the case when the attitudes in question are about socially sensitive topics, such as race. Greenwald and colleagues (2009) report an average attitude–​behavior correlation of .118 for explicit measures of black–​white racial attitudes.8 It is important to establish this baseline for comparison. It may be a mark of progress for attitude research even if indirect measures of attitudes have relatively small correlations with behavior. More important, the fact that even self-​report measures of attitudes don’t predict behavior very well is not cause to abandon such measures. Rather, since the 1970s, researchers have recognized that the key question is not whether self-​reported attitudes predict behavior, but rather when self-​reported attitudes predict behavior. One important lesson from this research is that attitudes better predict behavior when there is correspondence between the attitude object and the behavior in question (Ajzen and Fishbein, 1977). For example, while generic attitudes toward the environment do not predict recycling behavior very well, specific attitudes toward recycling do (Oskamp et al., 1991).9 A wealth of theoretical models of attitude–​ behavior relations elaborate on issues like this and make principled predictions about when attitudes do and do not predict behavior. According to dual-​process models, the predictive relations of self-​reported and indirectly measured attitudes to behavior should depend on (a) the type of behavior; (b) the conditions under which the behavior is performed; and (c) the characteristics of the person who is performing the behavior.10 From the perspective of these theories, meta-​analyses that ignore theoretically derived moderators are likely to find poor predictive relations between attitudes (whether self-​reported or indirectly measured) and behavior. Oswald et al. (2013) make exactly this mistake. They included any study in which a race IAT and a behavioral outcome measure were used, but they did not differentiate between behavioral outcomes that should or should not be predicted on theoretical grounds. For example, recall from Chapter 2 Amodio and Devine’s (2006) finding that the standard race IAT predicted how much white participants liked a black student, but it did not predict how white participants expected a black student to perform on a sports trivia task. They also found that a stereotyping IAT, which measured 8   Other reviews have estimated relatively higher attitude–​behavior correlations for explicit prejudice measures. Kraus (1995) finds a correlation of .24 and Talaska et al. (2008) find a correlation of .26. 9   See also footnote 7. 10   See, e.g., the “Reflective Impulse Model” (RIM; Strack and Deutsch, 1994) and “Motivation and Opportunity as Determinants” (MODE; Fazio, 1990).

Appendix

220

associations between black and white faces and words associated with athleticism and intelligence, predicted how white participants would expect a black student to perform on a sports trivia task, but failed to predict white students’ likability ratings of a black student. Amodio and Devine predicted these results on the basis of a theoretical model distinguishing between “implicit stereotypes” and “implicit prejudice.” If Amodio and Devine had reported the average correlation between their IATs and behavior, they would have found the same weak relationship reported by Oswald et al. (2013). However, this average correlation would conceal the insight that predictive relations should be high only for theoretically “matching” types of behavior. Because they included any study that arguably measured some form of discrimination, regardless of whether there was a theoretical basis for a correlation, Oswald and colleagues included all of Amodio and Devine’s (2006) IAT findings in their analysis. That is, they included the failure of the evaluative race IAT to predict how participants described the black essay writer, as well as how participants predicted another black student would perform on an SAT task compared with a sports trivia task. Likewise, Oswald and colleagues included in their analysis the failure of Amodio and Devine’s stereotyping IAT to predict seating-​distance decisions and likability ratings of the black essay writer. In contrast, Greenwald et al. (2009) did not include these findings, given Amodio and Devine’s theoretical basis for expecting them. Amodio and Devine predicted what the two different kinds of IAT wouldn’t predict, in other words. Oswald and colleagues include this as a failure of the IAT to predict a discriminatory outcome. In contrast, Greenwald and colleagues count this as a theoretically motivated refinement of the kinds of behavior IATs do and don’t predict.11   Oswald and colleagues (2015) contest Greenwald et al.’s (2014) analysis. They argue that their approach to inclusion criteria is more standard than Greenwald et al.’s (2009) approach. At issue is whether IAT researchers’ theoretically motivated predictions of results should be taken into account. For example, Oswald et al. (2015) contrast the findings of Rudman and Ashmore (2007) with those of Amodio and Devine (2006). They write, “[Rudman and Ashmore (2007)] predicted that an IAT measuring an attitude would predict stereotyping, and reported a statistically significant correlation in support of this prediction. In contrast, Amodio and Devine (2006) predicted that a racial attitude IAT would not predict stereotyping, and reported a set of nonsignificant correlations to support their prediction. Had we followed an inclusion rule based on the ‘author-​provided rationale’ for each of these studies, then all of the statistically significant effects would have been coded as supporting the IAT—​ even though some yielded inconsistent or opposing results—​and all of the statistically nonsignificant results would have been excluded. This was how the Greenwald et al. (2009) meta-​analysis handled inconsistencies” (Oswald et al., 2015, 563). This is, however, not a fully convincing reply. Consider the studies. Rudman and Ashmore (2007) predicted, and confirmed, that the standard racial attitude IAT would predict self-​reported verbal forms of discrimination and scores on an explicit measure of racial attitudes (the Modern Racism Scale; McConahay, 1986), whereas an IAT measure of black–​violent associations would better predict self-​reported behavioral forms of social exclusion (see Chapter  5, footnote 5). This is plausible given the content of the specific stereotypes in question. Black–​violent 11

Appendix

221

This point is not specific to the theoretically tendentious distinction between implicit stereotypes and implicit prejudice.12 Consider Justin  Levinson, Robert Smith, and Danielle Young (2014), who developed a novel IAT that found a tendency for respondents to associate white faces with words like “merit” and “value” and black faces with words like “expendable” and “worthless.” This meas­ ure predicted, among other things, that mock jurors with stronger “white–​value/​ black–​worthless” associations were comparatively more likely to sentence a black defendant to death rather than life in prison. Prima facie, this correlation suggests that the race–​value IAT is tracking, at least to some extent, something like a disposition to devalue black lives. This suggestion is supported by the fact that another IAT that measured associations between white and black faces and words like “lazy” and “unemployed” did not predict death sentencing. These measures capture different implicit associations and should predict different behavior. Moreover, this point fits the framework for understanding the nature of implicit attitudes for which I’ve argued. Consider Rooth and colleagues’ finding that implicit work-​performance stereotypes predicted real-​world hiring discrimination against both Arab Muslims (Rooth, 2010) and obese individuals (Agerström and Rooth, 2011) in Sweden. Employers who associated these social groups with laziness and incompetence were less likely to contact job applicants from these groups for an interview. In both cases, the indirect measure significantly predicted hiring

associations are coherently related to threat perception and social exclusion. Amodio and Devine (2006) predicted, and confirmed, that the standard racial attitudes IAT would be uncorrelated with the use of stereotypes about intelligence and athletic ability, but that a specific “mental–​physical” IAT would be. This, too, is plausible, given the match between the specific stereotypes captured by the measure and the behavioral outcomes being assessed (e.g., picking a teammate for a sports trivia task). More broadly, Rudman and Ashmore’s (2007) and Amodio and Devine’s (2006) use of different implicit stereotyping measures makes Oswald et al.’s (2015) direct comparison of them problematic. In other words, Oswald and colleagues’ claim that these are equivalent measures of implicit stereotypes with inconsistent findings is too blunt. Note again, however, that relations between putative implicit stereotypes and implicit prejudice are more complex, in my view, than these analyses suggest. Madva and Brownstein (2016) propose an “evaluative stereotyping” IAT that might more successfully predict behavioral manifestations of stereotypes about race, intelligence, and physicality. Oswald and colleagues (2015) double down on their claims by noting that Oswald et al. (2013) also included failures of black–​white racial attitude IATs to predict discrimination toward white people. They draw upon the true claim that in-​group favoritism is a significant feature of implicit bias, arguably as important as out-​group derogation (or even more so according to some; e.g., Greenwald and Pettigrew, 2014). But this point does not justify Oswald et al.’s (2013) inclusion policy given typical outcome measures, such as shooting and hiring decisions, and nonverbal insults. It is hardly a failure of IATs that they do not predict discriminatory behavior originating from white subjects toward white targets in these domains.   See Madva and Brownstein (2016) for detailed discussion and critique of the two-​type view of implicit cognition. 12

222

Appendix

discrimination over and above explicit measures of attitudes and stereotypes, which were uncorrelated or were very weakly correlated with the IATs. The predictive power of the obesity IAT was particularly striking, because explicit measures of anti-​obesity bias did not predict hiring discrimination at all—​even though a full 58% of participants openly admitted a preference for hiring normal-​weight over obese individuals.13 This study is significant not just because the indirect measure outperformed the self-​report measure, but arguably because it did so by homing in on specific affectively laden stereotypes (lazy and incompetent) that are relevant to a particular behavioral response (hiring) in a particular context (hiring Arabs or people perceived as obese). This is in keeping with the points I made in § 2.3 about improving the psychometric properties of indirect measures by targeting the co-​ activation of specific combinations of FTBA relata. The virtue of Oswald and colleagues’ approach is that it avoids cherry-​picking findings that support a specific conclusion. It also confirms that attitudes are relatively poor predictors if person-​, context-​, and behavior-​specific variables are ignored. But the main point is that this is to be expected. In fact, it would be bizarre to think otherwise, that is, to think that a generic measure of racial attitudes like the IAT would predict a wide range of race-​related behavior irrespective of whether such a relation can be expected on theoretical grounds. When the variables specified by theoretical models of implicit attitudes are considered, it is clear that indirect measures of attitudes are scientifically worthwhile instruments. For example, Cameron, Brown-​Iannuzzi, and Payne (2012) analyzed 167 studies that used sequential priming measures of implicit attitudes. They found a small average correlation between sequential priming tasks and behavior (r = .28). Yet correlations were substantially higher under theoretically expected conditions and lower under conditions where no relation would be expected. Cameron and colleagues identified their moderators from the fundaments of three influential dual-​process models of social cognition.14 While these models differ in important ways, they converge in predicting that indirect measures will correspond more strongly with behavior when agents have low motivation or little opportunity to engage in deliberation or when implicit associations and deliberatively considered propositions are consistent with each other. Moreover, in contrast to Greenwald et al. (2009), Cameron and colleagues did not simply take the stated expectations of the authors of the included studies for granted in coding moderators. Rather, the dual-​process moderators were derived a priori from the theoretical literature. 13   For additional research demonstrating how implicit and explicit attitudes explain unique aspects of behavior, see Dempsey and Mitchell (2010), Dovidio et al. (2002), Fazio et al. (1995), Galdi et al. (2008), and Green et al. (2007). 14   Specifically, from MODE (Fazio, 1990), APE (“Associative-​Propositional Evaluation”; Gawronski and Bodenhausen, 2006), and MCM (“Meta-​Cognitive Model”; Petty, Briñol, and DeMarree, 2007).

Appendix

223

Finally, in considering the claim that the IAT provides little insight into who will discriminate against whom, it is crucial to consider how tests like the IAT might be used to predict behavior. IAT proponents tend to recommend against using the IAT as a diagnostic tool of individual attitudes. At present, the measure is far from powerful enough, on its own, to classify people as likely to engage in discrimination. Indeed, I have been at pains to emphasize the complexity of implicit attitudes. But this does not necessarily mean that the IAT is a useless tool. Greenwald and colleagues (2014) identify two conditions under which a tool that measures statistically small effects can track behavioral patterns with large social significance. One is when the effects apply to many people, and the other is when the effects are repeatedly applied to the same person. Following Samuel Messick (1995), Greenwald and colleagues refer to this as the “consequential validity” of a measure. They provide the following example to show how small effects that apply to many people can be significant for predicting discrimination: As a hypothetical example, assume that a race IAT measure has been administered to the officers in a large city police department, and that this IAT meas­ ure is found to correlate with a measure of issuing citations more frequently to Black than to White drivers or pedestrians (profiling). To estimate the magnitude of variation in profiling explained by that correlation, it is necessary to have an estimate of variability in police profiling behavior. The estimate of variability used in this analysis came from a published study of profiling in New  York City (Office of the Attorney General, 1999), which reported that, across 76 precincts, police stopped an average of 38.2% (SD = 38.4%) more of each precinct’s Black population than of its White population. Using [Oswald and colleagues’ (2013)] r = .148 value as the IAT–​profiling correlation generates the expectation that, if all police officers were at 1 SD below the IAT mean, the city-​wide Black–​W hite difference in stops would be reduced by 9,976 per year (5.7% of total number of stops) relative to the situation if all police officers were at 1 SD above the mean. Use of [Greenwald and colleagues’ (2009)] larger estimate of r = .236 increases this estimate to 15,908 (9.1% of city-​wide total stops). (Greenwald et al., 2015)15 15   See the critical discussion of this example in Oswald et al. (2015), where it is argued that inferences about police officers cannot be drawn given that the distribution of IAT scores for police officers is unknown. This strikes me as unmoving, given both that Greenwald and colleagues present the example explicitly as hypothetical and that there is little reason to think that police officers would demonstrate less anti-​black bias on the IAT compared with the average IAT population pool. Moreover, Greenwald and colleagues’ general point about small effect sizes having significant consequences has been made elsewhere, irrespective of the details of this particular example. Robert Rosenthal, for example, (1991; Rosenthal and Rubin, 1982) shows that an r of .32 for a cancer treatment, compared with a placebo, which accounts for only 10% of variance, translates into a survival rate of 66% in the treatment group compared with 34% in the placebo group.

Appendix

224

This analysis could be applied to self-​report measures too, of course. But the effect sizes for socially sensitive topics are even smaller with these. This suggests that a measure with a correlational effect size of .236 (or even .148) can contribute to our understanding of patterns of discriminatory behavior. So, too, is this the lesson when discriminatory impact accumulates over time by repeatedly affecting the same person (e.g., in hiring, testing, healthcare experiences, and law enforcement). With repetition, even a tiny impact increases the chances of significantly undesirable outcomes. Greenwald and colleagues draw an analogy to a large clinical trial of the effect of aspirin on the prevention of heart attacks: The trial was terminated early because data analysis had revealed an unexpected effect for which the correlational effect size was the sub-​small value of r = .035. This was “a significant (P < 0.00001) reduction [from 2.16% to 1.27%] in the risk of total myocardial infarction [heart attack] among those in the aspirin group” (Steering Committee of the Physicians’ Health Study Research Group, 1989). Applying the study’s estimated risk reduction of 44% to the 2010 U.S. Census estimate of about 46 million male U.S. residents 50 or older, regular small doses of aspirin should prevent approximately 420,000 heart attacks during a 5-​year period. (2015, p. 558) The effect of taking aspirin on the likelihood of having a heart attack for any particular person is tiny, but the sub-​small value of the effect was significant enough to terminate data analysis in order to advance the research for use in public policy.16 The comparatively larger effect sizes associated with measures of implicit attitudes similarly justify taking immediate action.

2.4  Other Open Questions Significant challenges remain, of course, for research on implicit bias. One of the most daunting is the difficulty of designing interventions with durable effects. Calvin Lai and colleagues (2016) found that nine interventions that immediately reduced implicit preferences as measured by IAT had no significant effects after a delay of several hours to several days. The interventions tested in this study, however, were all relatively constrained in time and scope. That is, the interventions themselves were not long-​lasting and no interventions took a multifaceted approach. For example, in one intervention participants viewed twenty black faces paired with positive words and twenty white faces paired with negative words, and in another intervention participants played a simulated dodgeball game with interracial teammates. These are relatively simple and quick activities. And in no condition did participants do both

  For further discussion, see Valian (1998, 2005).

16

Appendix

225

of these activities. This isn’t a critique of Lai and colleagues’ analysis. Their interventions were quick and simple by design, in order to make it easy to administer and in order to facilitate comparisons between interventions. Their review helps to show what probably won’t work and moreover indicates that creating lasting implicit attitude change likely demands relatively robust interventions. It is also important to note that implicit attitude research is itself relatively new and that the effort to find interventions with lasting effects is even newer. For example, Patrick Forscher and colleagues (2016) reviewed 426 studies involving procedures for changing implicit bias, but only 22 of the studies in their sample collected longitudinal data. It may be an unreasonable expectation that feasible implicit attitude change interventions with durable effects could be discovered more or less in the fifteen years researchers have been focused on this. Some patience is appropriate. As before, in consideration of the psychometric properties of indirect measures, my hope is that my account of implicit attitudes could inspire new directions in research on effective interventions for implicit bias. I applaud Devine and colleagues’ (2012) habit-​ based approach, but perhaps it didn’t go far enough. It did not include, for example, the kind of rote practice of egalitarian responding found in Kawakami’s research (see Chapter 7). I suspect that more effective interventions will have to be more robust, incorporating repeated practice over time like this. This is akin to what athletes do when they practice. Just as a core feature of skill acquisition is simply doing the work—​ that is, putting in the effort over and over—​acquiring more egalitarian habits may be less the result of divining some hitherto unknown formula than, at least in large part, just putting in the time and (repeated) effort.17

3.  Replication in the Psychological Sciences In contrast to some promising results (e.g., Devine et al., 2012), the difficulty of creating reliably lasting changes in implicit attitudes speaks to a broader concern about ongoing research in the sciences of the mind. The so-​called replication crisis has destabilized many researchers’ confidence in what were previously thought to be well-​established beliefs in experimental psychology. While concerns about replicability have been percolating in psychology (and elsewhere) for some time (e.g., Meehl, 1990; Cohen, 1990), they exploded onto the public scene in light of concurrent events. These included discoveries of outright fraud in some high-​profile labs, the identification of potentially widespread questionable research practices (e.g., “p-​ hacking”), growing concerns about the difficulty of publishing null results and the related “file drawer” problem, and failures to replicate seminal discoveries (e.g., in

  See Chapter 8, footnote 1.

17

Appendix

226

research on priming, such as in Bargh et al., 1996).18 These events led researchers to attempt large-​scale well-​organized efforts to replicate major psychological findings. The findings—​for example, of the Open Science Collaboration’s (OSC) (2015) “Estimating the Reproducibility of Psychological Science”—​were not encouraging. The OSC attempted to replicate one hundred studies from three top journals but found that the magnitude of the mean effect size of replications was half that of the original effects. Moreover, while 97% of the original studies had significant results, only 36% of the replications did. These and other findings are deeply worrying. They raise serious concerns about the accuracy of extant research. They also point to problems for future research that may be very difficult to solve. The solutions to problems embedded in significance testing, causal inference, and so on are not yet clear.19 One thing that is important to note is that these are not problems for psychology alone. Replication efforts of landmark studies in cell biology, for example, were successful 11 and 25% of the time, as noted in two reports (Begley and Ellis, 2012; Prinz et al., 2011). Indeed, what is noteworthy about psychology is probably not that it faces a replication crisis, but rather how it has started to respond to this crisis, with rigorous internal debate about methodology, reforming publication practices, and the like. The founding of the Society for the Improvement of Psychological Science, for example, is very promising.20 Michael Inzlicht ominously writes, for example: I lost faith in psychology. Once I saw how our standard operating procedures could allow impossible effects to seem possible and real, once I understood how honest researchers with the highest of integrity could inadvertently and unconsciously bias their data to reach erroneous conclusions at disturbing rates, once I  appreciated how ignoring and burying null results can warp entire fields of inquiry, I finally grasped how broken the prevailing paradigm in psychology (if not most of science) had become. Once I  saw all these things, I could no longer un-​see them. But, he continues: I feel optimistic about psychology’s future. There are just so many good things afoot right now, I can’t help but feel things are looking up: Replications are increasingly seen as standard practice, samples are getting larger and larger,   For a timeline of events in the replication crisis, see http://​andrewgelman.com/​2016/​09/​21/​ what-​has-​happened-​down-​here-​is-​the-​winds-​have-​changed/​. 19   An excellent encapsulation of these and other concerns is found in Sanjay Srivastava’s (2016) fake, but also deadly serious “Everything Is Fucked: The Syllabus.” 20   See the society’s mission statement at https://​mfr.osf.io/​render?url=https://​osf.io/​jm27w/​?act ion=download%26direct%26mode=render. 18

Appendix

227

pre-​registration is something that is becoming more common, faculty applicants are increasingly asked what they are personally doing to improve their science, scientists are increasingly posting their data and analysis code, old methods are being challenged and new ones recommended, and there now exists an entire society devoted to improving our field.21 Of course, while these efforts are likely to improve future psychological science, they don’t indicate how much confidence we ought to have in extant studies. My view is that one can be cautiously confident in presenting psychological research in a context like this by adhering to a few relatively basic principles (none of which are the least bit novel to researchers in psychology or to philosophers working on these topics). As with most principles, though, things are complicated. And cautious confidence by no means guarantees the right outcomes. For example, studies with a large number of participants are, ceteris paribus, more valuable than studies with a small number of participants. And so I have tried to avoid presenting the results of underpowered studies. Indeed, this is a core strength of IAT research, much of which is done with online samples. As a result, many of the studies I discuss (when focused on research on implicit attitudes) have tremendous power to detect significant effects, given sample sizes in the thousands and even sometimes in the hundreds of thousands. As a methodological principle, however, there are complications stemming from the demand that all psychological research require large samples. One complication is that large samples are sometimes difficult or impossible to obtain. This may be due to research methodology (e.g., neural imaging research is often prohibitively expensive to do with large samples) or to research topics (e.g., some populations, such as patients with rare diseases, are difficult to find). While there have been Herculean efforts to locate difficult to find populations (e.g., Kristina Olson’s research in the Transyouth Project),22 in some cases the problem may be insurmountable. A related complication stems from other kinds of costs one pays in order to obtain large samples. There are downsides, for example, to studies using online participants. People in these participant pools are self-​selecting and may not be representative of the population at large.23 Their testing environment is also not well controlled. The tension between the importance of obtaining large samples and the costs associated with online samples is one that methodologists will continue to work through. Another seemingly simply, but ultimately not uncomplicated, principle is focusing on sets of studies rather than on any one individual study. It is generally bad 21   See http://​michaelinzlicht.com/​getting-​better/​2016/​8/​22/​the-​unschooling-​of-​a-​faithful​mind. 22   See http://​depts.washington.edu/​transyp/​. 23   Of course, this may be a problem facing psychology as a whole. See Henrich et al. (2010). For additional worries about attrition rates in online samples, see Zhou and Fishbach (2016).

Appendix

228

practice to take any one study as definitive of anything. Meta-​analyses tend to be more reliable. But complications and concerns abound here too. Sometimes, as discussed in §2.3, multiple meta-​analyses have conflicting results. This can be the result of legitimate differences in analytic principles (e.g., principles guiding inclusion criteria). Comparing meta-​analyses or sets of replication efforts across subareas of research is also complicated, given potentially legitimate differences between common research practices. For example, the OSC found that social psychology fared worse than other subdisciplines, such as cognitive psychology. By the OSC’s metric, only fifteen of fifty-​five social psychology effects could be replicated, whereas twenty-​one of forty-​two effects in cognitive psychology could. This may be due in part to differences in experimental design common within these fields. As the authors note, within-​subjects designs are more common in cognitive psychology, and these often have greater power to detect significant effects with equivalent numbers of participants. This leaves open the question whether social psychologists ought to alter their research designs or whether there are features of social life—​ the object of study of social psychology—​that require between-​subjects designs or other, more comparatively risky practices. While some of the complications facing meta-​analyses have to do with open questions like these, other concerns are more unambiguous. A meta-​analysis of a set of unreliable studies will itself yield unreliable results. This is the so-​called garbage in, garbage out problem (Inzlicht et al., 2015). The file drawer problem—​that is, the problem of including only studies that find effects and leaving aside studies that don’t—​can also render meta-​analyses unreliable. Sometimes this problem is obvious, such as when a meta-​analysis includes only published studies. Psychology journals typically do not publish null results, so including only published studies can serve as a proxy for the file drawer problem. Even when unpublished studies are included, as Inzlicht points out, another indication that the file drawer problem has affected a meta-​analysis is that there is an association between the number of participants in the included studies and the effect sizes of those studies. Unbiased samples should show no such association.24 It is important not to confuse this problem with the idea that multiple studies that fail to demonstrate a statistically significant effect confirm the absence of an effect, however. A  set of studies free from major biases can indicate a significant effect when pooled properly, even if each study on its own finds no significant effect. This points to the enduring importance of meta-​analyses. As Steven Goodman and colleagues point out in a meta-​analysis of the effect of tamoxifen on breast cancer survival (Early Breast Cancer Trialists Collaborative Group, 1988):

  See http://​soccco.uni-​koeln.de/​cscm-​2016-​debate.html.

24

Appendix

229

In this pooled analysis, 25 of 26 individual studies of tamoxifen’s effect were not statistically significant. Naïvely, these nonsignificant findings could be described as having been replicated 25 times. Yet, when properly pooled, they cumulatively added up to a definitive rejection of the null hypothesis with a highly statistically significant 20% reduction in mortality. So the proper approach to interpreting the evidential meaning of independent studies is not to assess whether or not statistical significance has been observed in each, but rather to assess their cumulative evidential weight. (Goodman et  al., 2016, p. 3) Thus while relying on meta-​analyses will not by any stretch solve the problems facing psychological science and while meta-​analyses can have their own problems, they continue to have a central role to play in adjudicating the credence one ought to have in a body of research. They can play this role best when researchers evaluate the design and structure of meta-​analyses themselves (as they are now doing). A third principle to which I have tried to hew closely—​and is particularly germane in the case of implicit attitude research—​is to identify reasons to expect features of the context to affect the outcomes of studies. This follows from my account of implicit attitudes as states with FTBA components. It figures into my recommendations for creating IATs with greater predictive validity. And it also speaks to broad issues in the replication crisis. It is clear from decades of research that social attitudes and behavior are persistently affected by the conceptual, physical, and motivational elements of agents’ contexts (see Chapters 3 and 7 and, for a review, see Gawronski and Cesario, 2013). In one sense, this suggests that we should expect many efforts to replicate psychological experiments to fail, given the myriad cultural, historical, and contextual features that could influence the outcome. Of course, replication under specified circumstances is a core tenet of science in general. In psychological science, the ideal is to identify outcome-​affecting variables that are psychologically meaningful for principled reasons. For example, consider the finding that the ambient light of the room in which one sits affects the activation of implicit racial biases (Schaller et al., 2003). A principled explanation of the specific moderating contextual factors is available here, I believe. It stems from the connection between an agent’s cares and the selective activation of her implicit attitudes (see Chapters 3 and 4). Schaller and colleagues’ findings obtained only for agents with chronic beliefs in a dangerous world. The dangerousness of the world is something the agent cares about (as chronic beliefs are certainly sufficient to fix cares). This care is connected to the activation of the agent’s implicit biases, given that ambient darkness is known to amplify threat perception (e.g., Grillon et al., 1997) and that black faces are typically seen by white people as more threatening than white faces (e.g., Hugenberg and Bodenhausen, 2003). Likewise predictions could be made based on other factors relevant to agents’ cares. One might expect that the possibilities for action available to an agent, based on

230

Appendix

her physical surroundings, also affect the activation of threat-​related implicit biases. Indeed, precisely this has been found. Consider a second example, regarding related (and much criticized) research on priming. Cesario and Jonas (2014) address the replicability of priming research in their “Resource Computation Model” by identifying conditions under which primes will and won’t affect behavior. They model social behaviors following priming as a result of computational processing of information that determines a set of behavioral possibilities for agents. They describe three sources of such information: (1) social resources (who is around me?); (2)  bodily resources (what is the state of my physiology and bodily position?); and (3) structural resources (where am I and what objects are around me?). I described one of Cesario and Jonas’s experiments in Chapter 2. They documented the effects of priming white participants with the concept “young black male,” contingent upon the participants’ physical surroundings and how threatening they perceived black males to be. The participants were seated either in an open field, which would allow a flight response to a perceived threat, or in a closed booth, which would restrict a flight response. Their outcome measure was the activation of flight versus fight words. Cesario and Jonas found that fight-​related words were activated for participants who were seated in the booth and who associated black men with danger, whereas flight-​related words were activated for participants who were seated in the field and who associated black men with danger.25 The line demarcating principled predictions about outcome-​affecting variables from ad hoc reference to “hidden moderators” is not crystal clear, however. I take the articulation of this line to be an important job for philosophers of science. It is clear enough that one should not attempt to explain away a failure to replicate a given study by searching after the fact for differences between the first and second experimental contexts.26 But I also note that this sort of post hoc rationalization can point the way to fruitful future research, which could help to confirm or disconfirm the proposal. What starts as post hoc rationalization for a failed replication can become an important theoretical refinement of previous theory, given additional research. (Or not! So the research needs to be done!)

4. Conclusion The aforementioned ambiguity over what constitutes a principled explanation of an effect points toward a broader set of issues regarding replication, the psychological 25   My point is not that all priming research can be saved through this approach. I do not know if there are principled explanations of moderators of many forms of priming. 26   For a prescient, helpful, and related critique of post hoc hypothesizing about data, see Kerr (1998).

Appendix

231

sciences, and philosophy. There is much work to do at this juncture for philosophers of science. Aside from questions about replication, there are persistently difficult tensions to resolve in research methodology and interpretation. The comparative value of field studies versus experiments is particularly fraught, I believe. Each offers benefits, costs, and seemingly inevitable trade-​offs.27 With respect to replication, there are trade-​offs between conceptual and direct replications, and moreover it isn’t even entirely clear what distinguishes a successful from an unsuccessful replication. Even more broadly, it is not clear how a successful replication indicates what is and isn’t true. The OSC (2015) writes, for example, “After this intensive effort to reproduce a sample of published psychological findings, how many of the effects have we established are true? Zero. And how many of the effects have we established are false? Zero. Is this a limitation of the project design? No.” The OSC recommends a roughly Bayesian framework, according to which all studies—​originals and replications alike—​simply generate cumulative evidence for shifting one’s prior credence in an idea:28 The original studies examined here offered tentative evidence; the replications we conducted offered additional, confirmatory evidence. In some cases, the replications increase confidence in the reliability of the original results; in other cases, the replications suggest that more investigation is needed to establish the validity of the original findings. Scientific progress is a cumulative process of uncertainty reduction that can only succeed if science itself remains the greatest skeptic of its explanatory claims. These assertions bear upon long-​standing debates in the philosophy of science. Some philosophers of science have begun considering these very questions.29 As with most philosophical questions, clear answers probably won’t be found. But my cautiously optimistic sense, given all that I have discussed, is that the epistemic value of the sciences of the mind, and of the majority of the findings I’ve presented in this book, is secure. I second the OSC’s sense that science is its own greatest skeptic.30 Psychological science in particular may use flawed means for understanding the mind, but these means strike me as comparatively less flawed than other, nonscientific means alone. In this way, one might echo what Winston Churchill putatively said about democracy: that is was the worst form of government—​except for all the others. Psychological science may be the worst way to understand the mind—​ except for all the others.   See, e.g., Berkowitz and Donnerstein (1982) and Falk and Heckman (2009).   See Goodman et al. (2016) on Bayesian approaches to understanding reproducibility. 29   See, e.g., Mayo (2011, 2012). 30   For another statement of cautious optimism, see Simine Vazire’s (2006) blog post “It’s the End of the World as We Know It . . . and I Feel Fine.” 27 28

REFERENCES

Aarts, H., Dijksterhuis, A., & Midden, C. 1999. To plan or not to plan? Goal achievement or interrupting the performance of mundane behaviors. European Journal of Social Psychology, 29, 971–​979. Achtziger, A., Bayer, U., & Gollwitzer, P. 2007. Implementation intentions: Increasing the accessibility of cues for action. Unpublished paper, University of Konstanz. Agassi, A. 2010. Open: An autobiography. New York: Vintage. Agerström, J., & Rooth, D. O. 2011. The role of automatic obesity stereotypes in real hiring discrimination. Journal of Applied Psychology, 96(4), 790–​805. Ajzen, I. 1988. Attitudes, personality, and behavior. Homewood, IL: Dorsey Press. Ajzen, I., & Fishbein, M. 1970. The prediction of behavior from attitudinal and normative variables. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 6, 466–​487. doi:10.1016/​0022-​1031(70)90057-​0. Ajzen, I., & Fishbein, M. 1977. Attitude–​behavior relations: A theoretical analysis and review of empirical research. Psychological Bulletin, 84, 888–​918. doi:10.1037/​0033-​2909.84.5.888. Ajzen, I., & Fishbein, M. 2005. The influence of attitudes on behavior. In D. Albarracín, B. T. Johnson, & M. P. Zanna (Eds.), The handbook of attitudes, 173–​221. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Akerlof, G. A., & Kranton, R. E. 2000. Economics and identity. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 115, 715–​753. Alcoff, L. M. 2010. Epistemic identities. Episteme, 7(2), 128–​137. Allport, G. 1954. The nature of prejudice. Cambridge, MA: Addison-​Wesley. Amodio, D. M., & Devine, P. G. 2006. Stereotyping and evaluation in implicit race bias: Evidence for independent constructs and unique effects on behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 91(4), 652. Amodio, D. M., & Devine, P. G. 2009. On the interpersonal functions of implicit stereotyping and evaluative race bias: Insights from social neuroscience. In R. E. Petty, R. H. Fazio, & P. Briñol (Eds.), Attitudes:  Insights from the new wave of implicit measures, 193–​226. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Amodio, D. M., & Devine, P. G. 2010. Regulating behavior in the social world: Control in the context of intergroup bias. In R. R. Hassin, K. N. Ochsner, & Y. Trope (Eds.), Self control in society, mind, and brain, 49–​75. New York: Oxford University Press. Amodio, D. M., Devine, P. G., & Harmon-​Jones, E. 2008. Individual differences in the regulation of intergroup bias: The role of conflict monitoring and neural signals for control. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 94, 60–​74. Amodio, D. M., & Hamilton, H. K. 2012. Intergroup anxiety effects on implicit racial evaluation and stereotyping. Emotion, 12, 1273–​1280. Amodio, D. M., & Ratner, K. 2011. A memory systems model of implicit social cognition. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 20(3), 143–​148.

233

234

References

Anderson, E. 1993. Value in ethics and economics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Anderson, E. 2005. Moral heuristics: Rigid rules or flexible inputs in moral deliberation? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28(4), 544–​545. Anderson, E. 2012. Epistemic justice as a virtue of social institutions. Social Epistemology, 26(2), 163–​173. Andrews, K. 2015, September 30. Naïve normativity. http://​philosophyofbrains.com/​2014/​09/​ 30/​naive-​normativity.aspx. Annas, J. 2008. The phenomenology of virtue. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 7, 21–​34. Antony, L. 2016. Bias:  Friend or foe? Reflections on Saulish skepticism. In M. Brownstein & J. Saul (Eds.), Implicit bias and philosophy: Vol. 1, Metaphysics and epistemology, 157–​190. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Apfelbaum, E. P., Sommers, S. R., & Norton, M. I. 2008. Seeing race and seeming racist? Evaluating strategic colorblindness in social interaction. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 95, 918–​932. Argyle, M., Alkema, F., & Gilmour, R. 1971. The communication of friendly and hostile attitudes by verbal and non-​verbal signals. European Journal of Social Psychology, 1(3), 385–​402. Ariely, D. 2011. The upside of irrationality. New York: Harper Perennial. Aristotle. 2000. Nicomachean ethics (R. Crisp, Ed. & Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Arnold, M. 1960. Emotion and personality. New York: Columbia University Press. Arpaly, N. 2004. Unprincipled virtue: An inquiry into moral agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Arpaly, N. 2015. Book review of Consciousness and moral responsibility. Australasian Journal of Philosophy. doi: 10.1080/​00048402.2014.996579. Arpaly, N. 2015. Philosophy and depression. Web log comment. http://​dailynous.com/​2015/​02/​ 23/​philosophy-​and-​depression/​. Arpaly, N., & Schroeder, T. 1999. Praise, blame and the whole self. Philosophical Studies, 93(2), 161–​188. Arpaly, N., & Schroeder, T. 2012. Deliberation and acting for reasons. Philosophical Review, 121(2), 209–​239. Ashburn-​Nardo, L., Knowles, M. L., & Monteith, M. J. 2003. Black Americans’ implicit racial associations and their implications for intergroup judgment. Social Cognition, 21(1), 61–​87. Ashburn-​Nardo, L., Voils, C. I., & Monteith, M. J. 2001. Implicit associations as the seeds of intergroup bias:  How easily do they take root? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81(5), 789. Bahill, A., & LaRitz, T. 1984. Why can’t batters keep their eyes on the ball? A laboratory study of batters tracking a fastball shows the limitations of some hoary baseball axioms. American Scientist, 72(3), 249–​253. Banaji, M. R. 2013. Our bounded rationality. In J. Brockman (Ed.), This explains everything: Deep, beautiful, and elegant theories of how the world works, 94–​95. New York: Harper Perennial. Banaji, M. R., & Greenwald, A. G. 2013. Blindspot:  Hidden biases of good people. New  York:  Delacorte Press. Banaji, M., & Hardin, C. 1996. Automatic stereotyping. Psychological Science, 7, 136–​141. Bar-​Anan, Y., & Nosek, B. 2014. A comparative investigation of seven implicit attitude measures. Behavioral Research, 46, 668–​688. Barden, J., Maddux, W., Petty, R., & Brewer, M. 2004. Contextual moderation of racial bias: The impact of social roles on controlled and automatically activated attitudes. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 87(1), 5–​22. Bargh, J. A. 1999. The cognitive monster: The case against the controllability of automatic stereotype effects. In S. Chaiken & Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual-​process theories in social psychology, 361–​ 382. New York: Guilford Press. Bargh, J. A., Chen, M., & Burrows, L. 1996. Automaticity of social behavior: Direct effects of trait construct and stereotype-​activation on action. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 71, 230–​244.

References

235

Bargh, J. A., Gollwitzer, P. M., Lee-​Chai, A., Barndollar, K., & Trotschel, R. 2001. The automated will: Unconscious activation and pursuit of behavioral goals. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81, 1004–​1027. Baron, J. (2008), Thinking and deciding. New York: Cambridge University Press. Barrett, L. F., & Bar, M. 2009. See it with feeling: Affective predictions during object perception. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, 364, 1325–​1334. Barrett, L. F., Oschner, K. N., & Gross, J. J. 2007. On the automaticity of emotion. In J. A. Bargh (Ed.), Social psychology and the unconscious: The automaticity of higher mental processes, 173–​ 218. Philadelphia: Psychology Press. Barry, M. 2007. Realism, rational action, and the Humean theory of motivation. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 10, 231–​42. Bartsch, K., & Wright, J. C. 2005. Toward an intuitionist account of moral development. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28(4), 546–​547. Bateson, M., Nettle, D., & Roberts, G. 2006. Cues of being watched enhance cooperation in a real-​ world setting. Biology letters, 2(3), 412–​414. Baumeister, R., & Alquist, J. 2009. Is there a downside to good self-​control? Self and Identity, 8(2–​3), 115–​130. Baumeister, R., Bratslavsky, E., Muraven, M., & Tice, D. 1998. Ego depletion: Is the active self a limited resource? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 74(5), 1252. Bealer, G. 1993. The incoherence of empiricism. In S. Wagner & R. Warner (Eds.), Naturalism: A critical appraisal, 99–​183. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. Beaman, L., Chattopadhyay, R., Duflo, E., Pande, R., & Topalova, P. 2009. Powerful women: Does exposure reduce bias? Quarterly Journal of Economics, 124(4), 1497–​1540. Bechara, A., Damasio, H., Tranel, D., & Damasio, A. 1997. Deciding advantageously before knowing the advantageous strategy. Science, 275, 1293–​1295. Bechara, A., Damasio, H., Tranel, D., & Damasio, A. 2005. The Iowa Gambling Task and the Somatic Marker Hypothesis: Some questions and answers. Trends in Cognitive Science, 9(4), 159–​162. Beck, J. S. 2011. Cognitive behavioral therapy, second edition:  Basics and beyond. New  York: Guilford Press. Begley, C., & Ellis, L. 2012. Drug development:  Raise standards for preclinical cancer research. Nature, 483, 531–​533. doi: 10.1038/​483531a. Beilock, S. 2010. Choke: What the secrets of the brain reveal about getting it right when you have to. New York: Free Press. Beilock, S. L., Wierenga, S. A., & Carr, T. H. (2002). Expertise, attention, and memory in sensorimo­ tor skill execution: Impact of novel task constraints on dual-​task performance and episodic memory. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology: Section A, 55(4), 1211–​1240. Bennett, J. 1974. The conscience of Huckleberry Finn. Philosophy, 49, 123–​134. Berger, J. 2012. Do we conceptualize every color we consciously discriminate? Consciousness and Cognition, 21(2), 632–​635. Berkowitz, L., & Donnerstein, E. 1982. External validity is more than skin deep:  Some answers to criticisms of laboratory experiments. American Psychologist, 37(3), 245–​257. doi: http://​ dx.doi.org/​10.1037/​0003-​066X.37.3.245. Berridge, K., & Winkielman, P. 2003. What is an unconscious emotion? The case for unconscious “liking.” Cognition and Emotion, 17(2), 181–​211. Berry, J., Abernethy, B., & Côté, J. 2008. The contribution of structured activity and deliberate play to the development of expert perceptual and decision-​making skill. Journal of Sport and Exercise Psychology, 30(6), 685–​708. Bhalla, M., & Proffitt, D. R. 1999. Visual–​motor recalibration in geographical slant perception. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 25(4), 1076. Blair, I. 2002. The malleability of automatic stereotypes and prejudice. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 6, 242–​261.

236

References

Blair, I., Ma, J., & Lenton, A. 2001. Imagining stereotypes away: The moderation of implicit stereotypes through mental imagery. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81, 828. Block, J. 2002. Personality as an affect-​processing system:  Toward an integrative theory. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Bourdieu, P. 1990. In other words:  Essays towards a reflexive sociology. Stanford, CA:  Stanford University Press. Bratman, M. 1987. Intentions, plans, and practical reason. Stanford, CA:  Center for the Study of Language and Information. Bratman, M. 2000. Reflection, planning, and temporally extended agency. Philosophical Review, 109(1), 38. Brewer, M. B. 1999. The psychology of prejudice: Ingroup love and outgroup hate? Journal of Social Issues, 55(3), 429–​444. Briñol, P., Petty, R., & McCaslin, M. 2009. Changing attitudes on implicit versus explicit measures: What is the difference? In R. Petty, R. Fazio, and P. Briñol (Eds.), Attitudes: Insights from the new implicit measures, 285–​326. New York: Psychology Press. Brody, G. H., Yu, T., Chen, E., Miller, G. E., Kogan, S. M., & Beach, S. R. H. 2013. Is resilience only skin deep? Rural African Americans’ socioeconomic status—​related risk and competence in preadolescence and psychological adjustment and allostatic load at age 19. Psychological Science, 24(7), 1285–​1293. Brownstein, M. 2014. Rationalizing flow: Agency in skilled unreflective action. Philosophical Studies, 168(2), 545–​568. doi: 10.1007/​s11098-​013-​0143-​5. Brownstein, M. 2015, February. Implicit bias. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Spring 2015 ed. (E. Zalta, Ed.). http://​plato.stanford.edu/​entries/​implicit-​bias/​. Brownstein, M. 2016. Implicit bias, context, and character. In M. Brownstein & J. Saul (Eds.), Implicit bias and philosophy: Vol. 2, Moral responsibility, structural injustice, and ethics, 215–​234. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Brownstein, M. 2017. Implicit attitudes, social learning, and moral credibility. In J. Kiverstein (Ed.), The Routledge handbook on philosophy of the social mind, 298–​319. New York: Routledge. Brownstein, M. Self-​control and overcontrol: Conceptual, ethical, and ideological issues in positive psychology. Unpublished paper. Brownstein, M., & Madva, A. 2012a. Ethical automaticity. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 42(1), 67–​97. Brownstein, M., & Madva, A. 2012b. The normativity of automaticity. Mind and Language, 27(4), 410–​434. Brownstein, M. & Michaelson, E. 2016. Doing without believing: Intellectualism, knowing-​how, and belief attribution. Synthese, 193(9), 2815–​2836. Brownstein, M., & Saul, J. (Eds.). 2016. Implicit bias and philosophy: Vol. 2, Moral responsibility, structural injustice, and ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bryan, W. L., & Harter, N. 1899. Studies on the telegraphic language: The acquisition of a hierarchy of habits. Psychological Review, 6(4), 345–​375. Buchsbaum, D., Gopnik A., & Griffiths, T. L. 2010. Children’s imitation of action sequences is influenced by statistical evidence and inferred causal structure. Proceedings of the 32nd Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Buckner, C. 2011. Two approaches to the distinction between cognition and “mere association.” International Journal of Comparative Psychology, 24(4), 314–​348. Buckner, C. 2017. The rationality of intuitive inference. Rational inference:  The lowest bounds. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. doi: 10.1111/​phpr.12455 Buon, M., Jacob, P., Loissel, E., & Dupoux, E. 2013. A non-​mentalistic cause-​based heuristic in human social evaluations. Cognition, 126(2), 149–​ 155. doi:  10.1016/​ j.cognition.2012.09.006. Byrne, A. 2009. Experience and content. Philosophical Quarterly, 59(236), 429–​451. doi: 10.1111/​ j.1467-​9213.2009.614.x.

References

237

Cameron, C. D., Brown-​Iannuzzi, J. L., & Payne, B. K. (2012). Sequential priming measures of implicit social cognition: A meta-​analysis of associations with behavior and explicit attitudes. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 16, 330–​350. Cameron, C., Payne, B., & J. Knobe. 2010. Do theories of implicit race bias change moral judgments? Social Justice Research, 23, 272–​289. Carey, S. 2009. The origin of concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Carlsson, R., & Björklund, F. 2010. Implicit stereotype content: Mixed stereotypes can be measured with the implicit association test. Social Psychology, 41(4), 213–​222. Carruthers, P. 2009. How we know our own minds:  The relationship between mindreading and metacognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, 121–​138. Carruthers, P. 2013. On knowing your own beliefs: A representationalist account. In N. Nottelmann (Ed.), New essays on belief: Constitution, content and structure, 145–​165. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan. Carver, C. S., & Harmon-​Jones, E. 2009. Anger is an approach-​related affect: Evidence and implications. Psychological Bulletin, 135, 183–​204. Carver, C. S., & Scheier, M. F. 1982. Control theory: A useful conceptual framework for personality—​ social, clinical, and health psychology. Psychological Bulletin, 92, 111–​135. Cath, Y. 2011. Knowing how without knowing that. In J. Bengson & M. Moffett (Eds.), Knowing-​ how: Essays on knowledge, mind, and action, 113–​135. New York: Oxford University Press. Cesario, J., & Jonas, K. 2014. Replicability and models of priming: What a resource computation framework can tell us about expectations of replicability. Social Cognition, 32, 124–​136. Cesario, J., Plaks, J. E., & Higgins, E. T. 2006. Automatic social behavior as motivated preparation to interact. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 90, 893–​910. Chan, D. 1995. Non-​intentional actions. American Philosophical Quarterly, 32, 139–​151. Chemero, A. 2009: Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Chen, M., & Bargh, J. A. 1999. Consequences of automatic evaluation: Immediate behavioral predispositions to approach or avoid the stimulus. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 25, 215–​224. Clark, A. 1997. Being there. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Clark, A. 1999. An embodied cognitive science? Trends in Cognitive Science, 3(9), 345–​351. Clark, A. 2007. Soft selves and ecological control. In D. Spurrett, D. Ross, H. Kincaid, and L. Stephens, (eds.), Distributed cognition and the will. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Clark, A. 2015. Surfing uncertainty:  Prediction, action, and the embodied mind. Oxford:  Oxford University Press. Cohen, G. L. 2003. Party over policy: The dominating impact of group influence on political beliefs. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 85, 808–​822. Cohen, J. 1990. Things I have learned so far. American Psychologist, 45(12), 1304–​1312. Colombetti, G. 2007. Enactive appraisal. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, 527–​546. Confucius. 2003. Analects. (E. Slingerland, Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett. Conrey, F., Sherman, J., Gawronski, B., Hugenberg, K., & Groom, C. 2005. Separating multiple processes in implicit social cognition: The Quad-​Model of implicit task performance. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 89, 469–​487. Corbetta, M., and Shulman, G. L. 2002. Control of goal-​directed and stimulus-​driven attention in the brain. Nature Reviews: Neuroscience, 3, 201–​215. doi: 10.1038/​nrn755. Correll, J., Park, B., Judd, C., & Wittenbrink, B. 2002. The police officer’s dilemma: Using race to disambiguate potentially threatening individuals. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 83, 1314–​1329. Correll, J., Park, B., Judd, C. M., & Wittenbrink, B. 2007. The influence of stereotypes on decisions to shoot. European Journal of Social Psychology, 37(6), 1102–​1117. Correll, J., Wittenbrink, B., Crawford, M. T., & Sadler, M. S. 2015. Stereotypic vision:  How stereotypes disambiguate visual stimuli. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 108(2), 219–​233.

238

References

Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. 2000. Evolutionary psychology and the emotions. In M. Lewis & J. M. Haviland-​Jones (Eds.), Handbook of emotions, 2d ed., 91–​115. New York: Guilford Press. Critcher, C., Inbar, Y., & Pizarro, D. 2013. How quick decisions illuminate moral character. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 4(3), 308–​315. Crockett, M. 2013. Models of morality. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17(8), 363–​366. Csikszentmihalyi, M. 1990. Flow: The psychology of optimal experience. New York: Harper & Row. Currie, G., & Ichino, A. 2012. Aliefs don’t exist, though some of their relatives do. Analysis, 72(4), 788–​798. Cushman, F. 2013. Action, outcome, and value: A dual-​system framework for morality. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 17(3), 273–​292. Cushman, F., Gray, K., Gaffey, A., & Mendes, W. B. 2012. Simulating murder: The aversion to harmful action. Emotion, 12(1), 2. Damasio, A. 1994. Descartes’ error: Emotion, reason, and the human brain. New York: Putnam’s. Danziger, S., Levav, J., & Avnaim-​Pesso, L. 2011. Extraneous factors in judicial decisions. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 108(17), 6889–​6892. Dardenne, B., Dumont, M., & Bollier, T. 2007. Insidious dangers of benevolent sexism: Consequences for women’s performance. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 93(5), 764. Darley, J., and Batson, C. 1973. From Jerusalem to Jericho: A study of situational and dispositional variables in helping behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 27, 100–​108. Dasgupta, N. 2004. Implicit ingroup favoritism, outgroup favoritism, and their behavioral manifestations. Social Justice Research, 17(2), 143–​168. Dasgupta, N. 2013. Implicit attitudes and beliefs adapt to situations: A decade of research on the malleability of implicit prejudice, stereotypes, and the self-​concept. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 47, 233–​279. Dasgupta, N., & Asgari, S. 2004. Seeing is believing: Exposure to counterstereotypic women leaders and its effect on automatic gender stereotyping. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 40, 642–​658. Dasgupta, N., DeSteno, D., Williams, L. A., & Hunsinger, M. 2009. Fanning the flames of prejudice: The influence of specific incidental emotions on implicit prejudice. Emotion, 9(4), 585. Dasgupta, N., & Greenwald, A. 2001. On the malleability of automatic attitudes: Combating automatic prejudice with images of admired and disliked individuals. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81, 800–​814. Dasgupta, N., & Rivera, L. 2008. When social context matters:  The influence of long-​term contact and short-​term exposure to admired group members on implicit attitudes and behavioral intentions. Social Cognition, 26, 112–​123. Davidson, A. R., & Jaccard, J. J. 1979. Variables that moderate the attitude–​behavior relation: Results of a longitudinal survey. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 37, 1364–​ 1376. doi: 10.1037/​0022-​ 3514.37.8.1364. Daw, N. D., Gershman, S. J., Seymour, B., Dayan, P., & Dolan, R. J. 2011. Model-​based influences on humans’ choices and striatal prediction errors. Neuron, 69, 1204–​1215. D’Cruz, J. 2013. Volatile reasons. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91(1), 31–​40. De Becker, G. 1998. The gift of fear. New York: Dell. De Coster, L., Verschuere, B., Goubert, L., Tsakiris, M., & Brass, M. 2013. I suffer more from your pain when you act like me: Being imitated enhances affective responses to seeing someone else in pain. Cognitive, Affective, & Behavioral Neuroscience, 13(3), 519–​532. De Houwer, J. 2014. A propositional model of implicit evaluation. Social Psychology and Personality Compass, 8(7), 342–​353. De Houwer, J., Teige-​Mocigemba, S., Spruyt, A., & Moors, A. 2009. Implicit measures: A normative analysis and review. Psychology Bulletin, 135(3), 347–​368. doi: 10.1037/​a0014211. Dempsey, M. A., & and Mitchell, A. A. 2010. The influence of implicit attitudes on consumer choice when confronted with conflicting product attribute information. Journal of Consumer Research, 37(4), 614–​625.

References

239

Dennett, D. C. 1989. The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Deutsch, R., Gawronski, B., & Strack, F. 2006. At the boundaries of automaticity: Negation as reflective operation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 91, 385–​405. Devine, P. 1989. Stereotypes and prejudice: Their automatic and controlled components. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 56, 5–​18. Devine, P., Forscher, P., Austin, A., & Cox, W. 2012. Long-​term reduction in implicit race bias: A prejudice habit-​ breaking intervention. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 48(6), 1267–​1278. Devine, P. G., Plant, E. A., Amodio, D. M., Harmon-​Jones, E., & Vance, S. L. 2002. The regulation of explicit and implicit race bias: The role of motivations to respond without prejudice. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 82, 835–​848. de Waal, F. 2016. Are we smart enough to know how smart animals are? New York: W. W. Norton. Deweese-​Boyd, I. 2006/​2008. Self-​deception. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. (E. N. Zalta, Ed.). http://​plato.stanford.edu/​entries/​self-​deception/​. Doggett, T. 2012. Some questions for Tamar Szabó Gendler. Analysis, 72(4), 764–​774. Donders, N. C., Correll, J., & Wittenbrink, B. 2008. Danger stereotypes predict racially biased attentional allocation. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 44(5), 1328–​1333. Doris, J. 2002. Lack of character:  Personality and moral behavior. Cambridge:  Cambridge University Press. Doris. J. 2015. Talking to ourselves. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Dovidio, J. F., & Gaertner, S. L (Eds.). 1986. Prejudice, discrimination, and racism: Historical trends and contemporary approaches. New York: Academic Press. Dovidio, J., Kawakami, K., & Gaertner, S. 2002. Implicit and explicit prejudice and interracial interaction. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 82, 62–​68. Dretske, F. 1981. Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Dretske, F. 1986. Misrepresentation. In R. Bogdan (Ed.), Belief: Form, content and function, 17–​36. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Dreyfus, H. 2002a. Intelligence without representation: The relevance of phenomenology to scientific explanation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(4), 367–​383. Dreyfus, H. 2002b. Refocusing the question: Can there be skillful coping without propositional representations or brain representations? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 413–​425. Dreyfus, H. 2005. Overcoming the myth of the mental: How philosophers can profit from the phenomenology of everyday experience. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 79(2), 43–​49. Dreyfus, H. 2007a. Detachment, involvement, and rationality: Are we essentially rational animals? Human Affairs, 17, 101–​109. Dreyfus, H. 2007b. The return of the myth of the mental. Inquiry, 50(4), 352–​365. Dreyfus, H. & Kelly, S. 2007. Heterophenomenology: Heavy-​handed sleight-​of-​hand. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, 45–​55. Duncan, S., & Barrett, L. F. 2007. Affect is a form of cognition: A neurobiological analysis. Cognition and Emotion, 21(6), 1184–​1211. Early Breast Cancer Trialists’ Collaborative Group. 1988. Effects of adjuvant tamoxifen and of cytotoxic therapy on mortality in early breast cancer. New England Journal of Medicine, 319, 1681–​1692. Eberhardt, J. L., Davies, P. G., Purdie-​Vaughns, V. J., & Johnson, S. L. 2006. Looking deathworthy perceived stereotypicality of black defendants predicts capital-​sentencing outcomes. Psychological Science, 17(5), 383–​386. Eberhardt, J., Goff, P., Purdie, V., & Davies, P. 2004. Seeing black: Race, crime, and visual processing,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 87(6), 876. Eberl, C., Wiers, R. W., Pawelczack, S., Rinck, M., Becker, E. S., & Lindenmeyer, J. 2012. Approach bias modification in alcohol dependence: Do clinical effects replicate and for whom does it work best? Developmental Cognitive Neuroscience, 4, 38–​51.

240

References

Egan, A. 2008. Seeing and believing: Perception, belief formation and the divided mind. Philosophical Studies, 140(1), 47–​63. Egan, A. 2011. Comments on Gendler’s “The Epistemic Costs of Implicit Bias.” Philosophical Studies, 156, 65–​79. Elster, J. 2000. Ulysses unbound: Studies in rationality, precommitment, and constraints. Cambridge:  Cambridge University Press. Epstein, D. 2013. The sports gene. New York: Penguin. Ericsson, K. A. 2016. Summing up hours of any type of practice versus identifying optimal practice activities:  Commentary on Macnamara, Moreau, & Hambrick. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 11(3), 351–​354. Ericsson, K. A., Krampe, R., & Tesch-​Römer, C. 1993. The role of deliberate practice in the acquisition of expert performance. Psychological Review, 100(3), 363–​406. Evans, G. 1982. The varieties of reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Evans, J. S.  B., & Frankish, K. E. 2009. In two minds:  Dual processes and beyond. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Evans, J. S. B., & Stanovich, K. E. 2013. Dual-​process theories of higher cognition: Advancing the debate. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8(3), 223–​241. doi: 10.1177/​1745691612460685. Falk, A., & Heckman, J. J. 2009. Lab experiments are a major source of knowledge in the social sciences. Science, 326(5952), 535–​538. doi: 10.1126/​science.1168244. Faraci, D., & Shoemaker, D. 2014. Huck vs. Jojo. In T. Lombrozo & J. Knobe (Eds.), Oxford studies in experimental philosophy, Vol. 1, 7–​26. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Faucher, L. 2016. Revisionism and moral responsibility. In M. Brownstein & J. Saul (Eds.), Implicit bias and philosophy: Vol. 2, Moral Responsibility, Structural Injustice, and Ethics, 115–​146. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Fazio, R. H. (1990). Multiple processes by which attitudes guide behavior: The MODE model as an integrative framework. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 23, 75–​109. Fazio, R. H., Jackson, J. R., Dunton, B. C., & Williams, C. J. 1995. Variability in Automatic Activation as an unobtrusive measure of racial attitudes: A bona fide pipeline? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 69(6), 1013–​1027. Ferriss, T. 2015, 27 April. Tim Ferriss on accelerated learning, peak performance and living the good life. Podcast. http://​thepsychologypodcast.com/​tim-​ferriss-​on-​accelerated-​learning-​ peak-​performance-​and-​living-​the-​good-​life/​. Festinger, L. 1956. A theory of cognitive dissonance. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Firestone, C. 2013. How “paternalistic” is spatial perception? Why wearing a heavy backpack doesn’t—​and couldn’t—​make hills look steeper. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8(4), 455–​473. Firestone, C., & Scholl, B. J. 2014. “Top-​down” effects where none should be found: The El Greco fallacy in perception research. Psychological Science, 25(1), 38–​46. Firestone, C., & Scholl, B. J. 2015. Cognition does not affect perception: Evaluating the evidence for “top-​down” effects. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1, 1–​77. Fischer, J. M., & M. Ravizza. 1998. Responsibility and Control:  A Theory of Moral Responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Flannigan, N., Miles, L. K., Quadflieg, S., & Macrae, C. N. 2013. Seeing the unexpected: Counterstereotypes are implicitly bad. Social Cognition, 31(6), 712–​720. Flavell, J. H., Miller, P. H., & Miller, S. A. 1985. Cognitive development. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-​Hall. Fleeson, W. R., Furr, M., Jayawickream, E., Helzer, E. R., Hartley, A. G., & Meindel, P. 2015. Personality science and the foundations of character. In C. R. Miller, M. Furr, A. Knobel, & W. Fleeson (Eds.), Character: New directions from philosophy, psychology, and theology, 41–​74. New York: Oxford University Press. Fodor, J. A. 1983. The modularity of mind: An essay on faculty psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

References

241

Fodor, J. A. 1987. Psychosemantics: The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Forscher, P. S., Lai, C. K., Axt, J. R., Ebersole, C. R., Herman, M., Devine, P. G., & Nosek, B. A. 2016. Meta-​analysis of change in implicit bias. Open Science Network. https://​osf.io/​b5m97/​. Förster, J., Liberman, N., & Friedman, R. S. 2007. Seven principles of goal activation: A systematic approach to distinguishing goal priming from priming of non-​goal constructs. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 11, 211–​233. Frankfurt, H. 1988. The importance of what we care about. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Frankish, K., & Evans, J. 2009. The duality of mind:  An historical perspective. In J. Evans & K. Frankish (Eds.), In two minds: Dual process and beyond, 1–​29. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Fridland, E. 2015. Automatically minded. Synthese, 1–​27. doi:10.1007/​s11229-​014-​0617-​9. Frijda, N. 1986. The emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Fujita, K. 2011. On conceptualizing self-​control as more than the effortful inhibition of impulses. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 15(4), 352–​366. Gal, D., & Liu, W. 2011. Grapes of wrath:  The angry effects of self-​control. Journal of Consumer Research, 38(3), 445–​458. Galdi, S., Arcuri, L., & Gawronski, B. 2008. Automatic mental associations predict future choices of undecided decision-​makers. Science, 321(5892), 1100–​1102. Gawronski, B., & Bodenhausen, G. V. 2006. Associative and propositional processes in evaluation: An integrative review of implicit and explicit attitude change. Psychology Bulletin, 132(5), 692–​731. Gawronski, B., & Bodenhausen, G. V. 2011. The associative-​propositional evaluation model: Theory, evidence, and open questions. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 44, 59–​127. Gawronski, B., Brannon, S., and Bodenhausen, G. 2017. The associative-​propositional duality in the representation, formation, and expression of attitudes. In R. Deutsch, B. Gawronski, & W. Hofmann (Eds.), Reflective and impulsive determinants of human behavior, 103–​118. New York: Psychology Press. Gawronski, B., & Cesario, J. 2013. Of mice and men: What animal research can tell us about context effects on automatic response in humans. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 17(2), 187–​215. Gawronski, B., Deutsch, R., Mbirkou, S., Seibt, B., & Strack, F. 2008. When “just say no” is not enough: Affirmation versus negation training and the reduction of automatic stereotype activation. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 44(2), 370–​377. Gawronski, B., Hofmann, W., & Wilbur, C. 2006. Are “implicit” attitudes unconscious? Consciousness and Cognition, 15, 485–​499. Gawronski, B., Rydell, R. J., Vervliet, B., & De Houwer, J. 2010. Generalization versus contextualization in automatic evaluation. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 139(4), 683–​701. Gawronski, B., Rydell, R.J., De Houwer, J., Brannon, S.M., Ye, Y., Vervliet, B., & Hu, X. 2017. Contextualized Attitude Change. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology. doi: https://doi. org/10.1016/bs.aesp.2017.06.001 Gawronski, B., & Sritharan, R. 2010. Formation, change, and contextualization of mental associations: Determinants and principles of variations in implicit measures. In B. Gawronski & B. K. Payne (Eds.), Handbook of implicit social cognition: Measurement, theory, and applications, 216–​240. New York: Guilford Press. Gendler, T. S. 2008a. Alief and belief. Journal of Philosophy, 105(10), 634–​663. Gendler, T. S. 2008b. Alief in action (and reaction). Mind and Language, 23(5), 552–​585. Gendler, T. S. 2011. On the epistemic costs of implicit bias. Philosophical Studies, 156, 33–​63. Gendler, T. S. 2012. Between reason and reflex:  Response to commentators. Analysis, 72(4), 799–​811. Gertler, B. 2011. Self-​knowledge and the transparency of belief. In A. Hatzimoysis (Ed.), Self-​ knowledge, 125–​145. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gibran, K. 1923. The prophet. New York, NY: Knopf. Gibson, J. J. 1979. The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Gilbert, D. T. 1991. How mental systems believe. American Psychologist, 46, 107–​119.

242

References

Gino, F., Schweitzer, M. E., Mead, N. L., & Ariely, D. 2011. Unable to resist temptation: How self-​ control depletion promotes unethical behavior. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 115(2), 191–​203. Ginsborg, H. 2011. Primitive normativity and skepticism about rules. Journal of Philosophy, 108(5), 227–​254. Gladwell, M. 2007. Blink. New York: Back Bay Books. Gladwell, M. 2011. Outliers. New York: Back Bay Books. Gladwell, M. 2013, 21 August. Complexity and the ten thousand hour rule. New Yorker. http://​ www.newyorker.com/​news/​sporting-​scene/​complexity-​and-​the-​ten-​thousand-​hour-​rule/​. Glaser, J. C. 1999. The relation between stereotyping and prejudice: Measures of newly formed automatic associations. Doctoral dissertation, Harvard University. Glaser, J., & Knowles, E. 2008. Implicit motivation to control prejudice. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 44, 164–​172. Glasgow, J. 2016. Alienation and responsibility. In M. Brownstein & J. Saul (Eds.), Implicit bias and philosophy: Vol. 2, Moral responsibility, structural injustice, and ethics, 37–​61. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Goff, P. A., Jackson, M. C., Di Leone, B. A. L., Culotta, C. M., & DiTomasso, N. A. 2014. The essence of innocence: Consequences of dehumanizing Black children. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 106(4), 526. Gollwitzer, P., Parks-​Stamm, E., Jaudas, A., & Sheeran, P. 2008. Flexible tenacity in goal pursuit. In J. Shah & W. Gardner (Eds.), Handbook of motivation science, 325–​341. New York: Guilford Press. Gollwitzer, P. M., & Sheeran, P. 2006. Implementation intentions and goal achievement: A meta-​ analysis of effects and processes. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology, 69–​119. New York: Academic Press. Goodman, S., Fanelli, D., & Loannidis, J. P.  A. 2016. What does research reproducibility mean? Science, 8(341), 341–​353. Gopnik, A. 2016, 31 July. What babies know about physics and foreign languages. New York Times. http://​www.nytimes.com/​2016/​07/​31/​opinion/​sunday/​what-​babies-​know-​about-​physics-​ and-​foreign-​languages.html/​. Govorun, O., & Payne, B. K. 2006. Ego-​depletion and prejudice: Separating automatic and controlled components. Social Cognition, 24(2), 111–​136. Green, A. R., Carney, D. R., Pallin, D. J., Ngo, L. H., Raymond, K. L., Iezzoni, L. I., Banaji, M. R. 2007. Implicit bias among physicians and its prediction of thrombolysis decisions for Black and White patients. Journal of General Internal Medicine, 22, 1231–​1238. Greene, J. D. 2013. Moral tribes:  Emotion, reason, and the gap between us and them. New  York:  Penguin. Greene, J., & Haidt, J. 2002. How (and where) does moral judgment work? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6(12), 517–​523. Greenwald, A. G., Banaji, M. R., Rudman, L. A., Farnham, S. D., Nosek, B. A., & Mellott, D. S. 2002. A unified theory of implicit attitudes, stereotypes, self-​esteem, and self-​concept. Psychological Review, 109(1), 3. Greenwald, A. G., Banaji, M. R., & Nosek, B. A. 2014. Statistically small effects of the implicit association test can have societally large effects. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 108, 553–​561. Greenwald, A., McGhee, D., & Schwartz, J. 1998. Measuring individual differences in implicit cognition:  The implicit association test. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 74, 1464–​1480. Greenwald, A. G., Nosek, B. A., & Banaji, M. R. 2003. Understanding and using the implicit association test: I. An improved scoring algorithm. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 85, 197–​216. Greenwald, A. G., & Pettigrew, T. F. 2014. With malice toward none and charity for some: Ingroup favoritism enables discrimination. American Psychologist, 69, 669–​684.

References

243

Greenwald, A., Poehlman, T., Uhlmann, E., & Banaji, M 2009. Understanding and using the implicit association test:  III. Meta-​analysis of predictive validity. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 97(1), 17–​41. Gregg A., Seibt B., & Banaji, M. 2006. Easier done than undone: Asymmetry in the malleability of implicit preferences. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 90, 1–​20. Grillon, C., Pellowski, M., Merikangas, K. R., & Davis, M. 1997. Darkness facilitates acoustic startle reflex in humans. Biological Psychiatry, 42, 453–​460. Gross, J. 2002. Emotion regulation: Affective, cognitive, and social consequences. Psychophysiology, 39, 281–​291. Gschwendner, T., Hoffman, W., & Schmitt, M. 2008. Convergent and predictive validity of implicit and explicit anxiety measures as a function of specificity similarity and content similarity. European Journal of Psychological Assessment, 24(4), 254–​262. Guinote, A., Guillermo, B. W., & Martellotta, C. 2010. Social power increases implicit prejudice. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 46, 299–​307. Hacker, P. 2007. Human nature: The categorical framework. Oxford: Blackwell. Hagger, M.S., Chatzisarantis, N.L.D., Alberts, H., Anggono, C.O., Batailler, C., Birt, A.R., Brand, R., et al. 2016. A multilab preregistered replication of the ego-depletion effect. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 11(4), 546–573. Haley, K., & Fessler, D. M. T. 2005. Nobody’s watching? Subtle cues affect generosity in an anonymous economic game. Evolution and Human Behavior, 26, 245–​256. Harman, G. 1999. Moral philosophy meets social psychology: Virtue ethics and the fundamental attribution error. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 99, 315–​331. Haslanger, S. 2015. Social structure, narrative, and explanation. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 45(1), 1–​15. doi: 10.1080/​00455091.2015.1019176. Hasson, U., & Glucksberg, S. 2006. Does negation entail affirmation? The case of negated metaphors. Journal of Pragmatics, 38, 1015–​1032. Hawley, K. 2012. Trust, distrust, and commitment. Noûs, 48(1), 1–​20. Hayes, J. R. 1985. Three problems in teaching general skills. Thinking and Learning Skills, 2, 391–​406. Heller, S. B., Shah, A. K., Guryan, J., Ludwig, J., Mullainathan, S., & Pollack, H. A. 2015. Thinking, fast and slow? Some field experiments to reduce crime and dropout in Chicago (No. w21178). National Bureau of Economic Research. Helm, B. W. 1994. The significance of emotions. American Philosophical Quarterly, 31(4), 319–​331. Helm, B. W. 2007. Emotional reason: Deliberation, motivation, and the nature of value. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Helm, B. W. 2009. Emotions as evaluative feelings. Emotion Review, 1(3), 248–​255. Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. 2010. The weirdest people in the world? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(2–​3), 61–​83. Herman, B. 1981. On the value of acting from the motive of duty. Philosophical Review, 90(3), 359–​382. Hermans, D., De Houwer, J., & Eelen, P. 2001. A time course analysis of the effective priming affect. Cognition and Emotion, 15, 143–​165. Hertz, S. G., & Krettenauer, T. 2016. Does moral identity effectively predict moral behavior? A meta-​ analysis. Review of General Psychology, 20(2), 129–​140. Hieronymi, P. 2008. Responsibility for believing. Synthese, 161, 357–​373. Hillman, A. L. 2010. Expressive behavior in economics and politics. European Journal of Political Economy, 26, 403–​418. Hofmann, W., Gawronski, B., Gschwendner, T., Le, H., & Schmitt, M. 2005. A meta-​analysis on the correlation between the implicit association test and explicit self-​report measures. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 31(10), 1369–​1385. Holroyd, C. B., Nieuwenhuis, S., Yeung, N., & Cohen, J. D. 2003. Errors in reward prediction are reflected in the event-​related brain potential. Neuroreport, 14(18), 2481–​2484. Holroyd, J. 2012. Responsibility for implicit bias. Journal of Social Philosophy, Special issue: Philosophical Methodology and Implicit Bias, 43(3), 274–​306.

244

References

Holroyd, J. & Sweetman, J. 2016. The heterogeneity of implicit biases. In M. Brownstein & J. Saul (Eds.), Implicit bias and philosophy, Vol. 1:  Metaphysics and epistemology, 80–​103. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hood, H. K., & Antony, M. M. 2012. Evidence-​based assessment and treatment of specific phobias in adults. In T. E. Davis et al. (Eds.), Intensive one-​session treatment of specific phobias, 19–​42. Berlin: Springer Science and Business Media. Hu, X., Gawronski, B., & Balas, R. 2017. Propositional versus dual-​process accounts of evaluative conditioning: I. The effects of co-​occurrence and relational information on implicit and explicit evaluations. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 43(1), 17–​32. Huang, J. Y., & Bargh, J. A. 2014. The selfish goal: Autonomously operating motivational structures as the proximate cause of human judgment and behavior. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 37(2), 121–​135. Huddleston, A. 2012. Naughty beliefs. Philosophical Studies, 160(2), 209–​222. Huebner, B. 2009. Trouble with stereotypes for Spinozan minds. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 39, 63–​92. Huebner, B. 2015. Do emotions play a constitutive role in moral cognition? Topoi, 34(2), 1–​14. Huebner, B. 2016. Implicit bias, reinforcement learning, and scaffolded moral cognition. In M. Brownstein & J. Saul (Eds.), Implicit bias and philosophy, Vol. 1: Metaphysics and epistemology, 47–​79. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hufendiek, R. 2015. Embodied emotions:  A naturalist approach to a normative phenomenon. New York: Routledge. Hugenberg, K., & Bodenhausen, G. V. 2003. Facing prejudice: Implicit prejudice and the perception of facial threat. Psychological Science, 14(6), 640–​643. Hume, D. 1738/​1975. A treatise of human nature. (L. A. Selby-​Bigge, Ed.; 2d ed. revised by P. H. Nidditch). Oxford: Clarendon Press. Hunter, D. 2011. Alienated belief. Dialectica, 65(2), 221–​240. Hursthouse, R. 1999. On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Inbar, Y., Pizarro, D., Iyer, R., & Haidt, J. 2012. Disgust sensitivity, political conservatism, and voting. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 3(5), 537–​544. Inzlicht, M. 2016, 22 August. The unschooling of a faithful mind. http://​michaelinzlicht.com/​ getting-​better/​2016/​8/​22/​the-​unschooling-​of-​a-​faithful-​mind/​. Inzlicht, M., Gervais, W., & Berkman, E. 2015. Bias-​correction techniques alone cannot determine whether ego depletion is different from zero:  Commentary on Carter, Kofler, Forster, & McCullough. Social Science Research Network. doi: http://​dx.doi.org/​10.2139/​ssrn.2659409. Isen, A., & Levin, P. 1972. Effect of feeling good on helping:  Cookies and kindness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 21(3), 384–​388. Ito, T. A., & Urland, G. R. 2005. The influence of processing objectives on the perception of faces: An ERP study of race and gender perception. Cognitive, Affective, and Behavioral Neuroscience, 5, 21–​36. James, W. 1884. What is an emotion? Mind, 9, 188–​205. James, W. 1890. The principles of psychology. New York: Henry Holt and Co. James, W. 1899. The laws of habit. In Talks to teachers on psychology—​and to students on some of life’s ideals, 64–​78. New York: Metropolitan Books/​Henry Holt and Co. doi: http://​dx.doi.org/​ 10.1037/​10814-​008. Jarvis, W. B. G., & Petty, R. E. 1996. The need to evaluate. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 70(1), 172–​194. Jaworska, A. 1999. Respecting the margins of agency: Alzheimer’s patients and the capacity to value. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 28(2), 105–​138. Jaworska, A. 2007a. Caring and internality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74(3), 529–​568. Jaworska, A. 2007b. Caring and full moral standing. Ethics, 117(3), 460–​497. Johansson, P., Hall, L., Sikström, S., & Olsson, A. 2005. Failure to detect mismatches between intention and outcome in a simple decision task. Science, 310, 116–​119.

References

245

John, O. P., & Srivastava, S. 1999. The Big Five trait taxonomy: History, measurement, and theoretical perspectives. In In L. A. Pervin & O. P. John (Eds.), Handbook of personality: Theory and research, 102–​138. New York: Guilford. Johnson, M. K., Kim, J. K., & Risse, G. 1985. Do alcoholic Korsakoff ’s syndrome patients acquire affective reactions? Journal of Experimental Psychology:  Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 11(1), 22–​36. Jordan, C. H., Whitfield, M., & Zeigler-​Hill, V. 2007. Intuition and the correspondence between implicit and explicit self-​esteem. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 93, 1067–​1079. Kahan, D. 2012. Why we are poles apart on climate change. Nature, 488, 255. Kahan, D. M. 2013. Ideology, motivated reasoning, and cognitive reflection. Judgment and Decision Making, 8, 407–​424. Kahan, D. M., Peters, E., Dawson, E. C., & Slovic, P. (2017). Motivated numeracy and enlightened self-​government. Behavioural Public Policy, 1(1), 54–​86. Kahan, D. M., Peters, E., Wittlin, M., Slovic, P., Ouellette, L. L., Braman, D. & Mandel, G. 2012. The polarizing impact of science literacy and numeracy on perceived climate change risks. Nature Climate Change, 2, 732–​735. Kahneman, D. 2003. A perspective on judgment and choice:  Mapping bounded rationality. American Psychologist, 58(9), 697. Kahneman, D. 2011. Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Macmillan. Kamtekar, R. 2004. Situationism and virtue ethics: On the content of our character. Ethics, 114(3), 458–​491. Kawakami, K., Dovidio, J. F., Moll, J., Hermsen, S. & Russin, A. 2000. Just say no (to stereotyping): Effects of training in the negation of stereotypic associations on stereotype activation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78, 871–​888. Kawakami, K., Dovidio, J. F., & van Kamp, S. 2007a. The impact of counterstereotypic training and related correction processes on the application of stereotypes. Group Processes and Intergroup Relations, 10(2), 139–​156. Kawakami, K., Phils, C., Steele, J., & Dovidio, J. 2007b. (Close) distance makes the heart grow fonder:  Improving implicit racial attitudes and interracial interactions through approach behaviors. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 92(6), 957–​971. Kawakami, K., Steele, J. R., Cifa, C., Phills, C. E., & Dovidio, J. F. 2008. Approaching math increases math = me, math = pleasant. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 44, 818–​825. Keinan, A., & Kivetz, R. 2011. Productivity orientation and the consumption of collectable experiences. Journal of Consumer Research, 37(6), 935–​950. Kelly, D. 2013. Yuck! The nature and moral significance of disgust. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Kelly, S. 2005. Seeing things in Merleau-​Ponty. In T. Carman (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Merleau-​Ponty, 74–​110. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kelly, S. 2010. The normative nature of perceptual experience. In B. Nanay (Ed.), Perceiving the world, 146–​159. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kerr, N. L. 1998. HARKing:  Hypothesizing after the results are known. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 2(3), 196–​217. Kidd, C., Palmeri, H., & Aslin, R. N. 2013. Rational snacking: Young children’s decision-​making on the marshmallow task is moderated by beliefs about environmental reliability. Cognition, 126(1), 109–​114. King, M., & Carruthers, P. 2012. Moral responsibility and consciousness. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 9(2), 200–​228. Kishida, K., Saez, I., Lohrenz, T., Witcher, M., Laxton, A., Tatter, S., White, J., et al. 2015. Subsecond dopamine fluctuations in huam striatum encode superposed error signals about actual and counterfactual reward. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. doi:  10.1073/​ pnas.1513619112. Kivetz, R., & Keinan, A. 2006. Repenting hyperopia: An analysis of self-​control regrets. Journal of Consumer Research, 33, 273–​282.

246

References

Klaassen, P., Rietveld, E. & Topal, J. 2010. Inviting complementary perspectives on situated normativity in everyday life. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9, 53–​73. Knobe, J. 2003. Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language. Analysis, 63(279), 190–​194. Knowles, M., Lucas, G., Baumeister, R., & Gardner, W. 2015. Choking under social pressure: Social monitoring among the lonely. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 41(6), 805–​821. Koch, C., & Crick, F. 2001. The zombie within. Nature, 411(6840), 893–​893. Kolling, N., Behrens, T. E. J., Mars, R. B., & Rushworth, M. F. S. 2012. Neural mechanisms of foraging. Science, 366, 95–​98. Korsgaard, C. 1997. The normativity of instrumental reason. In G. Cullity & B. Gaut (Eds.), Ethics and practical reason, 215–​254. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Korsgaard, C. 2009. The activity of reason. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 83, 27–​47. Kraus, S. J. 1995. Attitudes and the prediction of behavior: A metaanalysis of the empirical literature. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 21, 58–​75. doi:10.1177/​0146167295211007. Kriegel, U. 2012. Moral motivation, moral phenomenology, and the alief/​belief distinction. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90(3), 469–​486. Krishnamurthy, M. (2015). (White) tyranny and the democratic value of distrust. Monist, 98(4), 391–​406. Kubota, J., & Ito, T. 2014. The role of expression and race in weapons identification. Emotion, 14(6), 1115–​1124. Kumar, V. 2016a. Nudges and bumps. Georgetown Journal of Law and Public Policy, 14, 861–876. Kumar, V. 2016b. Moral vindications. Cognition, 176, 124–134. Lai, C. K., Hoffman, K. M., & Nosek, B. A. 2013. Reducing implicit prejudice. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 7, 315–​330. Lai, C. K., Skinner, A. L., Cooley, E., Murrar, S., Brauer, M., Devos, T., Calanchini, J., et al. 2016. Reducing implicit racial preferences:  II. Intervention effectiveness across time. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 145, 1001–​1016. Land, M. F., & McLeod, P. 2000. From eye movements to actions: How batsmen hit the ball. Nature Neuroscience, 3(12), 1340–​1345. Lange, C. G. 1885. Om sindsbehvaegelser:  Et psyko-​ fysiologisk studie. Copenhagen:  Jacob Lunds. Reprinted in The emotions (C. G.  Lange & W.  James (Eds.), I.  A. Haupt (Trans.), Baltimore: Williams & Wilkins, 1922. LaPiere, R. T. 1934. Attitudes vs. actions. Social Forces, 13(2), 230–​237. Laplante, D., & Ambady, N. 2003. On how things are said:  Voice tone, voice intensity, verbal content, and perceptions of politeness. Journal of Language and Social Psychology, 22(4), 434–​441. Layden, T. 2010, 8 November. The art of the pass. Sports Illustrated. http://​www.si.com/​vault/​ 2010/​11/​08/​106003792/​the-​art-​of-​the-​pass#. Lazarus, R. S. 1991. Emotion and adaptation. New York: Oxford University Press. Lebrecht, S., & Tarr, M. 2012. Can neural signals for visual preference predict real-​world choices? BioScience, 62(11), 937–​938. Leder, Garson. 2016. Know thyself? Questioning the theoretical foundations of cognitive behavioral therapy. Review of Philosophy and Psychology. doi: 10.1007/​s13164-​016-​0308-​1. Lessig, L. 1995. The regulation of social meaning. University of Chicago Law Review, 62(3), 943–​1045. Levine, L. 1988. Bird: The making of an American sports legend. New York: McGraw-​Hill. Levinson, J. D., Smith, R. J., & Young, D. M. (2014). Devaluing death: An empirical study of implicit racial bias on jury-​eligible citizens in six death penalty states. NYUL Rev., 89, 513–​581. Levy, N. 2011a. Expressing who we are:  Moral responsibility and awareness of our reasons for action. Analytic Philosophy, 52(4), 243–​261. Levy, N. 2011b. Hard luck: How luck undermines free will and moral responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Levy, N. 2012. Consciousness, implicit attitudes, and moral responsibility. Noûs, 48, 21–​40.

References

247

Levy, N., 2014. Neither fish nor fowl: Implicit attitudes as patchy endorsements. Noûs, 49(4), 800–​ 823. doi: 10.1111/​nous.12074. Levy, N. 2017. Implicit bias and moral responsibility:  Probing the data. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. doi: 10.1111/​phpr.12352. Lewicki, P., Czyzewska, M., & Hoffman, H. 1987. Unconscious acquisition of complex procedural knowledge. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 13, 523–​530. Lewis, D. 1973. Causation. Journal of Philosophy, 70(17), 556–​567. Li, C. 2006. The Confucian ideal of harmony. Philosophy East and West, 56(4), 583–​603. Limb, C., & Braun, A. 2008. Neural substrates of spontaneous musical performance: An fMRI study of jazz improvisation. PLoS ONE, 3(2), e1679. Lin, D., & Lee, R. (Producers), & Lord, P., & Miller, C. (Directors). 2014. The lego movie (motion picture). Warner Brothers Pictures. Livingston, R. W., & Drwecki, B. B. 2007. Why are some individuals not racially biased? Susceptibility to affective conditioning predicts nonprejudice toward blacks. Psychology Science, 18(9), 816–​823. Loersch, C., & Payne, B. K. 2016. Demystifying priming. Current Opinion in Psychology, 12, 32–​36. doi:10.1016/​j.copsyc.2016.04.020. Machery, E. 2016. De-​Freuding implicit attitudes. In M. Brownstein & J. Saul (Eds.), Implicit bias and philosophy, Vol. 1:  Metaphysics and epistemology, 104–​ 129. Oxford:  Oxford University Press. Macnamara, B. N., Moreau, D., & Hambrick, D.Z. 2016. The relationship between deliberate practice and performance in sports: A meta-​analysis. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 11(3), 333–​350. Macpherson, F. 2012. Cognitive penetration of colour experience: Rethinking the issue in light of an indirect mechanism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84(1), 24–​62. Macpherson, F. 2016. The relationship between cognitive penetration and predictive coding. Consciousness and Cognition. http://​www.sciencedirect.com/​science/​article/​pii/​ S1053810016300496/​. Madva, A. 2012. The hidden mechanisms of prejudice: Implicit bias and interpersonal fluency. Doctoral dissertation, Columbia University. Madva, A. 2016a. Virtue, social knowledge, and implicit bias. In M. Brownstein & J. Saul (Eds.), Implicit bias and philosophy, Vol. 1: Metaphysics and epistemology, 191–​215. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Madva, A. 2016b. Why implicit attitudes are (probably) not beliefs. Synthese, 193(8), 2659–​2684. Madva, A. 2017. Biased against de-​biasing:  On the role of (institutionally sponsored) self-​transformation in the struggle against prejudice.  Ergo, 4(6). doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.3998/ ergo.12405314.0004.006. Madva, A., & Brownstein, M. 2016. Stereotypes, prejudice, and the taxonomy of the implicit social mind. Noûs. doi: 10.1111/​nous.12182. Mallon, R. 2016. Stereotype threat and persons. In M. Brownstein & J. Saul (Eds.), Implicit bias and philosophy, Vol. 1: Metaphysics and epistemology, 130–​156. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Mandelbaum, E. 2011. The architecture of belief: An essay on the unbearable automaticity of believing. Doctoral dissertation, University of North Carolina. Mandelbaum, E. 2013. Against alief. Philosophical Studies, 165, 197–​211. Mandelbaum, E. 2014. Thinking is believing. Inquiry, 57(1), 55–​96. Mandelbaum, E. 2015a. Associationist theories of thought. In E. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://​plato.stanford.edu/​entries/​associationist-​thought/​. Mandelbaum, E. 2015b. Attitude, association, and inference:  On the propositional structure of implicit bias. Noûs, 50(3), 629–​658. doi: 10.1111/​nous.12089. Mann, D. T. Y., Williams, A. M., Ward, P., & Janelle, C. M. 2007. Perceptual-​cognitive expertise in sport: A meta-​analysis. Journal of Sport & Exercise Psychology, 29, 457–​478. Manzini, P., Sadrieh, A., & Vriend, N. 2009. On smiles, winks and handshakes as coordination devices. Economic Journal, 119(537), 826–​854.

248

References

Martin, J., & Cushman, F. 2016. The adaptive logic of moral luck. In J. Sytsma & W. Buckwalter (Eds.), The Blackwell companion to experimental philosophy, 190–​202. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. Martin, L. L., & Tesser, A. 2009. Five markers of motivated behavior. In G. B. Moskowitz & H. Grant (Eds.), The psychology of goals, 257–​276. New York: Guilford Press. Mayo, D. G. 2011. Statistical science and philosophy of science: Where do/​should they meet in 2011 (and beyond)?” Rationality, Markets and Morals (RMM) Special Topic: Statistical Science and Philosophy of Science, 2, 79–​102. Mayo, D. G. 2012. Statistical science meets philosophy of science, Part  2:  Shallow versus deep explorations. Rationality, Markets, and Morals (RMM), Special Topic:  Statistical Science and Philosophy of Science, 3, 71–​107. McConahay, J. B. 1986. Modern racism, ambivalence, and the modern racism scale. In J. F. Dovidio & S. L. Gaertner (Eds.), Prejudice, discrimination, and racism, 91–​125. San Diego, CA: Academic Press. McLeod, P. 1987. Visual reaction time and high-​speed ball games. Perception, 16(1), 49–​59. Meehl, P. E. 1990. Why summaries of research on psychological theories are often uninterpretable. Psychological Reports, 66, 195–​244. Mekawi, Y., & Bresin, K. 2015. Is the evidence from racial bias shooting task studies a smoking gun? Results from a meta-​analysis. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 61, 120–​130. Mendoza, S. A., Gollwitzer, P. M., & Amodio, D. M. 2010. Reducing the expression of implicit stereotypes:  Reflexive control through implementation intentions. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 36(4), 512–​523. Merleau-​Ponty, M. 1962/​2002. The phenomenology of perception. (C. Smith, trans). New York: Routledge. Messick, S. 1995. Validity of psychological assessment:  Validation of inferences from persons’ responses and performances as scientific inquiry into score meaning. American Psychologist, 50, 41–​749. Miller, G. A. 1956. The magic number seven, plus or minus two: Some limits on our capacity for processing information. Psychological Review, 63, 81–​97. Miller, G. E., Yu, T., Chen, E., & Brody, G. H. 2015. Self-​control forecasts better psychosocial outcomes but faster epigenetic aging in low-​SES youth. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 112(33), 10325–​10330. doi: 10.1073/​pnas.1505063112. Millikan, R. 1995. Pushmi-​pullyu representations. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 185–​200. Millikan, R. 2006. Styles of rationality. In S. Hurley & M. Nudds (Eds.), Rational animals?, 117–​126. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. 1995. The visual brain in action. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. 2008. Two visual systems re-​viewed. Neuropsychologia, 46, 774–​785. Milyavskaya, M., Inzlicht, M., Hope, N., & Koestner, R. 2015. Saying “no” to temptation: Want-​ to motivation improves self-​regulation by reducing temptation rather than by increasing self-​control. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 109(4), 677–​693. doi.org/​10.1037/​ pspp0000045. Mischel, W., Shoda, Y., & Peake, P. 1988. The nature of adolescent competencies predicted by preschool delay of gratification. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 54(4), 687. Mitchell, C. J., De Houwer, J., & Lovibond, P. F. 2009. The propositional nature of human associative learning. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32(2), 183–​198. Mitchell, J. P., Nosek, B. A., & Banaji, M. R. 2003. Contextual variations in implicit evaluation. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 132, 455–​469. Monin, B., & Miller, D. T. 2001. Moral credentials and the expression of prejudice. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81(1), 33. Monteith, M. 1993. Self-​regulation of prejudiced responses: Implications for progress in prejudice-​ reduction efforts. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 65(3), 469–​485. Monteith, M., Ashburn-​Nardo, L., Voils, C., and A. Czopp, A. 2002. Putting the brakes on prejudice: On the development and operation of cues for control. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 83(5), 1029–​1050.

References

249

Montero, B. 2010. Does bodily awareness interfere with highly skilled movement? Inquiry, 53(2), 105–​122. Moran, T., & Bar-​Anan, Y. 2013. The effect of object–​valence relations on automatic evaluation. Cognition and Emotion, 27(4), 743–​752. Moskowitz, G. B. 2002. Preconscious effects of temporary goals on attention. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 38(4), 397–​404. Moskowitz, G. B., & Balcetis, E. 2014. The conscious roots of selfless, unconscious goals. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 37(2), 151. Moskowitz, G. B., & Li, P. 2011. Egalitarian goals trigger stereotype inhibition: A proactive form of stereotype control. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 47(1), 103–​116. Moskowitz, G., Gollwitzer, P., Wasel, W., & Schaal, B. 1999. Preconscious control of stereotype activation through chronic egalitarian goals. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 77, 167–​184. Moskowitz, G. B., Li, P., Ignarri, C., & Stone, J. 2011. Compensatory cognition associated with egalitarian goals. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 47(2), 365–​70. Muller, H., & B. Bashour. 2011. Why alief is not a legitimate psychological category. Journal of Philosophical Research, 36, 371–​389. Muraven, M., Collins, R. L., & Neinhaus, K. 2002. Self-​control and alcohol restraint:  An initial application of the self-​control strength model. Psychology of Addictive Behaviors, 16(2), 113. Nagel, J. 2012. Gendler on alief. Analysis, 72(4), 774–​788. Nanay, B. 2011. Do we see apples as edible? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 92, 305–​322. Nanay, B. 2013. Between perception and action. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Neal, D. T., Wood, W., Wu, M., & Kurlander, D. 2011. The pull of the past: When do habits persist despite conflict with motives? Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 1–​10. doi: 10.1177/​ 0146167211419863. Neenan, M., & Dryden, W. 2005. Cognitive therapy. Los Angeles: Sage. Nesse, R., & Ellsworth, P. 2009. Evolution, emotion, and emotional disorders. American Psychologist, 64(2), 129–​139. Newen, A. 2016. Defending the liberal-​content view of perceptual experience: Direct social perception of emotions and person impressions. Synthese. doi:10.1007/​s11229-​016-​1030-​3. Newman, G., Bloom, P., & Knobe, J. 2014. Value judgments and the true self. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 40(2), 203–​216. Newman, G., De Freitas, J., & Knobe, J. 2015. Beliefs about the true self explain asymmetries based on moral judgment. Cognitive Science, 39(1), 96–​125. Nieuwenstein, M. R., Wierenga, T., Morey, R. D., Wicherts, J. M., Blom, T. N., Wagenmakers, E. J., & van Rijn, H. 2015. On making the right choice: A meta-​analysis and large-​scale replication attempt of the unconscious thought advantage. Judgment and Decision Making, 10, 1–​17. Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. 1977. Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review, 84(3), 231. Noë, A. 2006. Perception in action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Nosek, B. A., & Banaji, M. R. 2001. The go/​no-​go association task. Social Cognition, 19(6), 161–​176. Nosek, B. A., Banaji, M. R., & Greenwald, A. G. 2002. Harvesting intergroup implicit attitudes and beliefs from a demonstration website. Group Dynamics, 6, 101–​115. Nosek, B., Greenwald, A., & M. Banaji. 2007. The implicit association test at age 7: A methodological and conceptual review. In J. A. Bargh (Ed.), Automatic processes in social thinking and behavior, 265–​292. Philadelphia: Psychology Press. Nussbaum, M. 2001. Upheavals of thought:  The intelligence of emotion. Cambridge:  Cambridge University Press. Office of the Attorney General. (1999). The New York City Police Department’s “stop & frisk” practices: A report to the people of the State of New York. Retrieved from www.oag.state.ny.us/​ bureaus/​civil_​rights/​pdfs/​stp_​frsk.pdf. Olson, M., & R. Fazio, 2006. Reducing automatically activated racial prejudice through implicit evaluative conditioning. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 32, 421–​433.

250

References

Open Science Collaboration. (2015). Estimating the reproducibility of psychological science. Science, 349(6251). doi: 10.1126/​science.aac4716. Orlandi, N. 2014. The innocent eye. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ortny, A., Clore, G. L., & Collins, A. 1988. The cognitive structure of emotions. New York: Cambridge University Press. Oskamp, S., Harrington, M. J., Edwards, T. C., Sherwood, D. L., Okuda, S. M., & Swanson, D. C. (1991). Factors influencing household recycling behavior. Environment and Behavior, 23(4), 494–​519. Oswald, F. L., Mitchell, G., Blanton, H., Jaccard, J., & Tetlock, P. E. 2015. Using the IAT to predict ethnic and racial discrimination: Small effects of unknown societal importance. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 108, 562–​571. Oswald, F. L., Mitchell, G., Blanton, H., Jaccard, J., & Tetlock, P. E. 2013. Predicting ethnic and racial discrimination: A meta-​analysis of IAT criterion studies. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 105, 171–​192. Otten, S., & Moskowitz, G. B. 2000. Evidence for implicit evaluative in-​group bias: Affect-​biased spontaneous trait inference in a minimal group paradigm. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 36(1), 77–​89. Papineau, D. 2015. Choking and the yips. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 14(2), 295–​308. Parks-​Stamm, E., Gollwitzer, P., & Oettingen, G. 2007. Action control by implementation intentions: Effective cue detection and efficient response initiation. Social Cognition, 25, 248–​266. Pautz, A. 2010. Why explain visual experience in terms of content? In B. Nanay (Ed.), Perceiving the world, 254–​310. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Payne, B. K., & Cameron, C. D. 2010. Divided minds, divided morals:  How implicit social cognition underpins and undermines our sense of justice. In B. Gawronski & B. K. Payne (Eds.), Handbook of implicit social cognition: Measurement, theory, and applications, 445–​461. New York: Guilford Press. Payne, B. K., Cheng, C. M., Govorun, O., & Stewart, B. D. 2005. An inkblot for attitudes: Affect misattribution as implicit measurement. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 89(3), 277–​293. Payne, B. K., & B. Gawronski, 2010. A history of implicit social cognition: Where is it coming from? Where is it now? Where is it going? In B. Gawronski, and B. Payne (Eds.), Handbook of implicit social cognition: Measurement, theory, and applications, 1–​17. New York: Guilford Press. Payne, K., & Lundberg, K. 2014. The affect misattribution procedure: Ten years of evidence on reliability, validity, and mechanisms. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 8(12), 672–​686. Peacocke, C. 1999. Being known. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Peacocke, C. 2004. The realm of reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pessoa, L. 2008. On the relationship between emotion and cognition. Nature Reviews: Neuroscience, 9, 148–​158. Peters, K. R., & Gawronski, B. (2011). Are we puppets on a string? Comparing the impact of contingency and validity on implicit and explicit evaluations. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 37(4), 557–​569. Peterson, C., & Seligman, M. E. P. 2004. Character strengths and virtues: A classification and handbook. New York: Oxford University Press/​Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Peterson, M.A., & Gibson, B. S. 1991. Directing spatial attention within an object: Altering the functional equivalence of shape descriptions. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 17, 170–​182. Pettigrew, T., & Tropp, L. 2006. A meta-​analytic test of intergroup contact theory. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 90, 751–​783. Pezzulo, G., Rigoli, F., & Friston, K. 2015. Active inference, homeostatic regulation and adaptive behavioural control. Progress in Neurobiology, 134, 17–​35. Plant, E., & Devine, P. 1998. Internal and external motivation to respond without prejudice. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 75(3), 811.

References

251

Plato. 380 bce/​1992. Republic, 443de. Poldrack, R., Sabb, F. W., Foerde, K., Tom, S. M., Asarnow, R. F., Bookheimer, S. Y., & Knowlton, B. J. 2005. The neural correlates of motor skill automaticity. Journal of Neuroscience, 25(22), 5356–​5364. Polonyi, M. 1966/​2009. The tacit dimension. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Port, R. F., & Van Gelder, T. 1995. Mind as motion:  Explorations in the dynamics of cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT press. Preuschoff, K., Bossaerts, P., Quartz, S. R. 2006. Neural differentiation of expected reward and risk in human subcortical structures. Neuron, 5(3), 381–​390. Prinz, F., Schlange, T., & Asadullah, K. 2011. Believe it or not: How much can we rely on published data on potential drug targets? Nature Reviews: Drug Discovery, 10, 712–​713. doi: 10.1038/​ nrd3439-​c1. Prinz, J. 2004. Gut reactions: A perceptual theory of emotion. New York: Oxford University Press. Prinz, J. 2009. The normativity challenge: Cultural psychology provides the real threat to virtue ethics. Journal of Ethics, 13(2–​3), 117–​144. Railton, P. 2009. Practical competence and fluent agency. In D. Sobel & S. Wall (Eds.), Reasons for action, 81–​115. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Railton, P. 2011. Two cheers for virtue, or, might virtue be habit forming? In M. Timmons (Ed.), Oxford studies in normative ethics, Vol. 1, 295–​330. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Railton, P. 2014. The affective dog and its rational tale: Intuition and attunement. Ethics 124(4), 813–​859. Railton, P. 2015. Dual-​process models of the mind and the “Identifiable Victim Effect.” In I. Cohen, N. Daniels, & N. Eyal (Eds.), Identified versus statistical lives: An interdisciplinary perspective, 24–​41. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ramsey, F. P. 1990. Philosophic papers. (D. J. Mellor, Ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rand, D. G., Greene, J. D., & Nowak, M. A. 2012. Spontaneous giving and calculated greed. Nature, 489(7416), 427–​430. Ranganath, K. A., Smith, C. T., & Nosek, B. A. 2008. Distinguishing automatic and controlled components of attitudes from direct and indirect measurement methods. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 44(2), 386–​396. Reber, A. S. 1967. Implicit learning of artificial grammars. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 6(6), 855–​863. Reber, A. S. 1989. Implicit learning and tacit knowledge. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 118(3), 219–​235. Redford, L. & Ratliff, K. 2016. Perceived moral responsibility for attitude-​based discrimination. British Journal of Social Psychology, 55, 279–​296. Reed, B. 2013, 26 July. The view from in here. This American Life. Podcast. http://​www.thisamericanlife.org/​radio-​archives/​episode/​501/​the-​view-​from-​in-​here/​. Reynolds, S. M., & Berridge, K. C. 2008. Emotional environments retune the valence of appetitive versus fearful functions in nucleus accumbens. Nature Neuroscience, 11, 423–​425. Richeson, J., & Nussbaum, R. 2004. The impact of multiculturalism versus color-​blindness on racial bias. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 40(3), 417–​423. Richeson, J., & Shelton, J. 2003. When prejudice does not pay: Effects of interracial contact on executive function. Psychological Science, 14(3), 287–​290. Richetin, J., Perugini, M., Adjali, I., & Hurling, R. 2007. The moderator role of intuitive versus deliberative decision making for the predictive validity of implicit and explicit measures. European Journal of Personality, 21, 529–​546. Rietveld, E. 2008. Situated normativity: The normative aspect of embodied cognition in unreflective action. Mind, 117, 973–​1001. Rietveld, E., & Paglieri, F. 2012. Bodily intentionality and social affordances in context. In F. Paglieri (Ed.), Consciousness in interaction: The role of the natural and social context in shaping consciousness, 207–​226. Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

252

References

Rooth, D. O. 2010. Automatic associations and discrimination in hiring:  Real world evidence. Labour Economics, 17(3), 523–​534. Rosenthal, R. 1991. Meta-​analytic procedures for social research (Rev. ed.). Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Rosenthal, R., & Rubin, D.B. 1982. A simple, general purpose display of magnitude of experimental effect. Journal of Educational Psychology, 74, 166–​169. Rowbottom, D. 2007. “In-​between believing” and degrees of belief. Teorema, 26, 131–​137. Rudman, L. A., & Ashmore, R.D. 2007. Discrimination and the implicit association test. Group Processes & Intergroup Relations, 10, 359–​372. Rydell, R. J., & Gawronski, B. 2009. I like you, I  like you not:  Understanding the formation of context-​dependent automatic attitudes. Cognition and Emotion, 23, 1118–​1152. Ryle, G. 1949. The concept of mind. London: Hutchinson. Salzman, C. D., & Fusi, S. 2010. Emotion, cognition, and mental state representation in amygdala and prefrontal cortex. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 33, 173. Sarkissian, H. 2010a. Confucius and the effortless life of virtue. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 27(1), 1–​16. Sarkissian, H. 2010b. Minor tweaks, major payoffs: The problems and promise of situationalism in moral philosophy. Philosopher’s Imprint, 10(9), 1–​15. Sartre, J. P. 1956/​1993. Being and nothingness. New York: Washington Square Press. Scanlon, T. 1998. What we owe each other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Schaller, M., Park, J. J., & Mueller, A. 2003. Fear of the dark:  Interactive effects of beliefs about danger and ambient darkness on ethnic stereotypes. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 29, 637–​649. Schapiro, T. 2009. The nature of inclination. Ethics, 119(2), 229–​256. Scharlemann, J., Eckel, C., Kacelnik, A., & Wilson, R. 2001. The value of a smile: Game theory with a human face. Journal of Economic Psychology, 22, 617–​640. Schechtman, M. 1996. The constitution of selves. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Schmajuk, N. A., & Holland, P. C. 1998. Occasion setting: Associative learning and cognition in animals. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Schneider, W. & Shiffrin, R. 1977. Controlled and automatic human information processing. I: Detection, search and attention. Psychological Review, 84, 1–​66. Schwartz, N. 2002. Situated cognition and the wisdom of feelings: Cognitive tuning. In L. F. Barrett & P. Salovey (Eds.), The wisdom of feeling, 144–​166. New York: Guilford Press. Schwartz, N., & Clore, G. L. 2003. Mood as information: 20 years later. Psychological Inquiry, 14, 296–​303. Schweiger Gallo, I., Keil, A., McCulloch, K., Rockstroh, B., & Gollwitzer, P. 2009. Strategic automation of emotion regulation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 96(1), 11–​13. Schwitzgebel, E. 2002. A phenomenal, dispositional account of belief. Noûs, 36, 249–​275. Schwitzgebel, E. 2006/​2010. Belief. In E. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://​ plato.stanford.edu/​entries/​belief/​. Schwitzgebel, E. 2010. Acting contrary to our professed beliefs, or the gulf between occurrent judgment and dispositional belief. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 91, 531–​553. Schwitzgebel, E. 2013. A dispositional approach to attitudes: Thinking outside of the belief box. In N. Nottelmann (Ed.), New essays on belief:  Constitution, content and structure, 75–​99. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan. Schwitzgebel, E., & Cushman, F. 2012. Expertise in moral reasoning? Order effects on moral judgment in professional philosophers and non‐philosophers. Mind & Language, 27(2), 135–​153. Schwitzgebel, E., & Rust, J. 2014. The moral behavior of ethics professors: Relationships among self-​ reported behavior, expressed normative attitude, and directly observed behavior. Philosophical Psychology, 27(3), 293–​327. Seligman, M., Railton, P., Baumeister, R., & Sripada, C. 2013. Navigating into the future or driven by the past. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8(2), 119–​141.

References

253

Shepherd, J. 2014. The contours of control. Philosophical Studies, 170(3), 395–​411. Sher, G., 2009, Who knew? Responsibility without awareness. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Sherman, S. J., Rose, J. S., Koch, K., Presson, C. C., & Chassin, L. 2003. Implicit and explicit attitudes toward cigarette smoking: The effects of context and motivation. Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology, 22(1), 13–​39. Shiffrin, R., & Schneider, W. 1977. Controlled and automatic human information processing. II: Perceptual learning, automatic attending, and a general theory. Psychological Review, 84, 127–​190. Shoemaker, D. 2003. Caring, identification, and agency. Ethics, 118, 88–​118. Shoemaker, D. 2011. Attributability, answerability, and accountability: Towards a wider theory of moral responsibility. Ethics, 121, 602–​632. Shoemaker, D. 2012. Responsibility without identity. Harvard Review of Philosophy, 18(1), 109–​132. Shoemaker, D. 2015. Remnants of character. In J. D’Arms & D. Jacobson (Eds.), Moral psychology and human agency, 84–​107. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Shook, N., & Fazio, R. 2008. Interracial roommate relationships an experimental field test of the contact hypothesis. Psychological Science, 19(7), 717–​723. Siegel, S. 2010. The contents of visual experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Siegel, S. 2014. Affordances and the contents of perception. In B. Brograard (Ed.), Does perception have content?, 39–​76. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Siegel, S., & Byrne, A. 2016. Rich or thin? In B. Nanay(Ed.), Current controversies in philosophy of perception. New York: Routledge. Slingerland, E. 2014. Trying not to try: The art and science of spontaneity. New York: Random House. Sloman, S. A. 1996. The empirical case for two systems of reasoning. Psychological Bulletin, 119(1), 3–​22. Smart, J. J. C. 1961. Free-​will, praise and blame. Mind, 70(279), 291–​306. Smith, A. 2005. Responsibility for attitudes: Activity and passivity in mental life. Ethics, 115(2), 236–​271. Smith, A. 2008. Control, responsibility, and moral assessment. Philosophical Studies, 138, 367–​392. Smith, A. 2012. Attributability, answerability, and accountability: In defense of a unified account. Ethics, 122(3), 575–​589. Smith, C. T., & Nosek, B. A. 2011. Affective focus increases the concordance between implicit and explicit attitudes. Social Psychology, 42, 300–​313. Smith, E. 1996. What do connectionism and social psychology offer each other? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 70(5), 893–​912. Smith, E. R., & Lerner, M. 1986. Development of automatism of social judgments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 50(2), 246–​259. Smith, H. 2011. Non-​tracing cases of culpable ignorance. Criminal Law and Philosophy, 5, 115–​146. Smith, H. 2015. Dual-​process theory and moral responsibility. In R. Clarke, M. McKenna, & A. Smith (Eds.), The nature of moral responsibility:  New essays, 175–​210. New  York:  Oxford University Press. Soeter, M., & Kindt, M. 2015. An abrupt transformation of phobic behavior after a post-​retrieval amnesic agent. Biological Psychiatry, 8(12), 880–​886. Solomon, R. 1976. The passions. New York: Doubleday. Sripada, C. 2015. Self-​expression: A deep self theory of moral responsibility. Philosophical Studies, 173(5), 1203–​1232. Srivastava, S. 2016, 11 August. Everything is fucked: The syllabus. https://​hardsci.wordpress.com/​ 2016/​08/​11/​everything-​is-​fucked-​the-​syllabus/​. Steering Committee of the Physicians' Health Study Research Group. (1989). Final report on the aspirin component of the ongoing Physicians' Health Study. New England Journal of Medicine, 321, 129–​135. Stefanucci, J. K., & Proffitt, D. R. 2009. The roles of altitude and fear in the perception of height. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 35(2), 424.

254

References

Sterelny, K. 1995. Basic minds. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 251–​270. Sterelny, K. 2001. Explaining culture: A naturalistic approach. Mind, 110(439), 845–​854. Stewart, B., & Payne, B. 2008. Bringing automatic stereotyping under control:  Implementation intentions as efficient means of thought control. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 34, 1332–​1345. Stich, S. 1978. Belief and subdoxastic states. Philosophy of Science, 45(4), 499–​518. Stoffregen, T. 2003. Affordances as properties of the animal–​environment system. Ecological Psychology, 15, 149–​180. Strack, F., & Deutsch, R. (2004). Reflective and impulsive determinants of social behavior. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 8, 220–​247. Strack, F., Martin, L. L., & Stepper, S. 1988. Inhibiting and facilitating conditions of the human smile: A nonobtrusive test of the facial feedback hypothesis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 54(5), 768. Strawson, P. 1962. Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 187–​211. Strohminger, N., & Nichols, S. 2014. The essential moral self. Cognition, 131(1), 159–​171. Stucke, T., & Baumeister, R. 2006. Ego depletion and aggressive behavior:  Is the inhibition of aggression a limited resource? European Journal of Social Psychology, 36(1), 1–​13. Sunstein, C. R. 2005. Moral heuristics. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28(4), 531–​541. Sutton, J. 2007. Batting, habit and memory: The embodied mind and the nature of skill. Sport in Society, 10(5), 763–​786. Sutton, R. S. 1988. Learning to predict by the method of temporal differences. Machine Learning, 3(9), 44. Talaska, C. A., Fiske, S. T., & Chaiken, S. 2008. Legitimating racial discrimination: A meta-​analysis of the racial attitude—​behavior literature shows that emotions, not beliefs, best predict discrimination. Social Justice Research, 21, 263–​296. doi:10.1007/​s11211-​008-​0071-​2. Terbeck, S., Kahane, G., McTavish, S., Savulescu, J., Cowen, P. J., & Hewstone, M. 2012. Propranolol reduces implicit negative racial bias. Psychopharmacology, 222(3), 419–​424. Thaler, R. & Sunstein, C. 2008. Nudge:  Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New York: Penguin Books. Tiberius, V. 2002. Practical reason and the stability standard. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 5, 339–​53. Tierney, H., Howard, C., Kumar, V., Kvaran, T., & Nichols, S. 2014. How many of us are there? In J. Sytsma (Ed.), Advances in experimental philosophy of mind, 181–​202. New York: Bloomsbury. Tietz, J. 2004, 29 November. Fine disturbances. New Yorker. Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. 1990. The past explains the present: Emotional adaptations and the structure of ancestral environments. Ethology and Sociobiology, 11, 375–​424. Toplak, M., West, R. and Stanovich, K. 2011. The cognitive reflection test as a predictor of performance on heuristics-​and-​biases tasks. Memory & Cognition, 39(7), 1275–​1289. Toppino, T. C. 2003. Reversible-​figure perception: Mechanisms of intentional control. Perception & Psychophysics, 65, 1285–​1295. Toribio, J. 2015. Visual experience:  Rich but impenetrable. Synthese, 1–​ 18. doi:10.1007/​ s11229-​015-​0889-​8. Turvey, E., Shaw, R., Reed, E., & Mace, W. 1981. Ecological laws of perceiving and acting: In reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn. Cognition, 9, 237–​304. Valian, V. 1998. Why so slow? The advancement of women. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Valian, V. 2005. Beyond gender schemas:  Improving the advancement of women in academia. Hypatia 20, 198–​213. Varela, F. J., & Depraz, N. 2005. At the source of time: Valence and the constitutional dynamics of affect. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 12, 61–​81. Vargas, M. 2005. The revisionist’s guide to responsibility. Philosophical Studies, 125(3), 399–​429. Vazire, S. 2006. It’s the end of the world as we know it . . . and I feel fine. http://​sometimesimwrong. typepad.com/​wrong/​2016/​02/​end-​of-​the-​world.html/​.

References

255

Velleman, J. D. 2000. On the aim of belief. In J. D. Velleman (Ed.), The possibility of practical reason, 244–​282. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Velleman, J. D. 2015. Morality here and there. Whitehead Lecture at Harvard University. Vohs, K. D., & Heatherton, T. F. 2000. Self-​regulatory failure:  A resource-​depletion approach. Psychological Science, 11(3), 249–​254. Vohs, K. D., & Baumeister, R. (Eds.). 2011. Handbook of self-​regulation: Research, theory, and applications. New York: Guilford Press. Wagenmakers, E. J., Beek, T., Dijkhoff, L., Gronau, Q. F., Acosta, A., Adams, R. B., Albohn, D. N., et al. 2016. Registered replication report: Strack, Martin, & Stepper (1998). Perspectives on Psychological Science, 11(6), 917–​928. Waldron, J. 2014, 9 October. It’s all for your own good [review of Nudge]. New York Review of Books. http://​ www.nybooks.com/​articles/​archives/​2014/​oct/​09/​cass-​sunstein-​its-​all-​your-​own-​good/​. Wallace, D. F. 1999. Brief interviews with hideous men. New York: Back Bay Books. Wallace, D. F. 2006. How Tracy Austin broke my heart. In Consider the lobster. New York: Little, Brown. Wallace, D. F. 2011. The pale king. New York: Back Bay Books. Wansink, B., Painter, J. E., & North, J. 2005. Bottomless bowls: Why visual cues of portion size may influence intake. Obesity Research, 13(1), 93–​100. Washington, N., & Kelly, D. 2016. Who’s responsible for this? Implicit bias and the knowledge condition. In M. Brownstein & J. Saul (Eds), Implicit bias and philosophy: Vol. 2, Moral responsibility, structural injustice, and ethics, 11–​36. Oxford: University Press. Watson, G. 1975. Free agency. Journal of Philosophy, 72(8), 205–​220. Watson, G. 1996. Two faces of responsibility. Philosophical Topics, 24(2), 227–​248. Webb, T., & Sheeran, P. 2008. Mechanisms of implementation intention effects: The role of goal intentions, self-​ efficacy, and accessibility of plan components. British Journal of Social Psychology, 47, 373–​379. Webb, T., Sheeran, P., & Pepper, A. 2010. Gaining control over responses to implicit attitude tests:  Implementation intentions engender fast responses on attitude-​incongruent trials. British Journal of Social Psychology, 51(1), 13–​32. Wegner, D. 1984. Innuendo and damage to reputation. Advances in Consumer Research, 11, 694–​696. Wegner, D., Schneider, D., Carter, S., & White, T. 1987. Paradoxical effects of thought suppression. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 53(1), 5–​13. Weisbuch, M., Pauker, K., & Ambady, N. 2009. The subtle transmission of race bias via televised nonverbal behavior. Science, 326(5960), 1711–​1714. Wennekers, A. M. 2013. Embodiment of prejudice: The role of the environment and bodily states. Doctoral dissertation, Radboud University. West, R. F., Meserve, R., & Stanovich, K. 2012. Cognitive sophistication does not attenuate the bias blind spot. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 103(3), 506–​519. Wheatley, T., & Haidt, J. 2005. Hypnotic disgust makes moral judgments more severe. Psychological Science, 16(10), 780–​784. Whitehead, A. N. 1911. An introduction to mathematics. New York: Holt. Wicklund, R. A. & Gollwitzer, P. M. 1982. Symbolic self-​completion. New York: Routledge. Wieber, F., Gollwitzer, P., Gawrilow, C., Odenthal, G., & Oettingen, G. 2009. Matching principles in action control. Unpublished manuscript, University of Konstanz. Wiers, R. W., Eberl, C., Rinck, M., Becker, E. S., & Lindenmeyer, J. 2011. Retraining automatic action tendencies changes alcoholic patients’ approach bias for alcohol and improves treatment outcome. Psychological Science, 22(4), 490–​497. Williams, B. 1981. Moral luck:  Philosophical papers, 1973–​ 1980. Cambridge:  Cambridge University Press. Wilson, T. D., Lindsey, S., & Schooler, T. Y. 2000. A model of dual attitudes. Psychological Review, 107, 101–​126. Winkielman, P., Berridge, K. C., & Wilbarger, J. L. 2005. Unconscious affective reactions to masked happy versus angry faces influence consumption behavior and judgments of value. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 31(1), 121–​135.

256

References

Witt, J. K., & Proffitt, D. R. 2008. Action-​specific influences on distance perception:  A role for motor simulation. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 34, 1479–​1492. Witt, J. K., Proffitt, D. R., & Epstein, W. 2004. Perceiving distance:  A role of effort and intent. Perception, 33, 570–​590. Wittenbrink, B., Judd, C. M., & Park, B. 2001. Spontaneous prejudice in context: Variability in automatically activated attitudes. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81(5), 815. Wittgenstein, L. 1966. Lectures and conversations on aesthetics, psychology and religious belief. Oxford: Blackwell. Wolitzky-​Taylor, K. B., Horowitz, J. D., Powers, M. B., & Telch, M. J. 2008. Psychological approaches in the treatment of specific phobias:  A meta-​ analysis. Clinical Psychology Review, 28, 1021–​1037. Woodward, J., & Allman, J. 2007. Moral intuition: Its neural substrates and normative significance. Journal of Physiology–​Paris, 101(4), 179–​202. Wright, C. 2014. On epistemic entitlement. II: Welfare state epistemology. In E. Zardini & D. Dodd (Eds.), Scepticism and perceptual justification, 213–​247. New York: Oxford University Press. Wu, W. 2014a. Against division:  Consciousness, information, and the visual streams. Mind & Language, 29(4), 383–​406. Wu, W. 2014b. Attention. New York: Routledge. Wu, W. 2015. Experts and deviants: The story of agentive control. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 93(1), 101–​126. Wylie, C. D. 2015. “The artist’s piece is already in the stone”: Constructing creativity in paleontology laboratories. Social Studies of Science, 45(1), 31–​55. Xu, K., Nosek, B., & Greenwald, A. G., 2014. Psychology data from the race implicit association test on the project implicit demo website. Journal of Open Psychology Data, 2(1), p.e3. doi: http://​ doi.org/​10.5334/​jopd.ac. Yancy, G. 2008. Black bodies, white gazes: The continuing significance of race. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Yarrow, K., Brown, P., & Krakauer, J. 2009. Inside the brain of an elite athlete: The neural processes that support high achievement in sports. Nature Reviews: Neuroscience, 10, 585–​596. Zajonc, R. B. 1984. On the primacy of affect. American Psychologist, 39, 117–​123. Zeigarnik, B. 1927/​1934. On finished and unfinished tasks. In W. D. Ellis & K. Koffka (Eds.), A source book of Gestalt psychology, 300–​314. Gouldsboro, ME: Gestalt Journal Press. Zheng, R. 2016. Attributability, accountability and implicit attitudes. In M. Brownstein & J. Saul (Eds.), Implicit bias and philosophy: Vol. 2, Moral responsibility, structural injustice, and ethics, 62–​89. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Zhou, H., & Fishbach, A. 2016. The pitfall of experimenting on the web: How unattended selective attrition leads to surprising (yet false) research conclusions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 111(4), 493–​504. Zimmerman, A. 2007. The nature of belief. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 14(11), 61–​82.

INDEX

accidents, responsibility for, 13–​14 affordances, 36–​42, 46–​48, 115n23 Agassi, Andre, 183 agency, 103, 116, 141–​145, 189 fluent, 157 alief, 85–​97 RAB content of, 85–​91 Allman, John, 43n17, 47n28 allostatic load, 181 Allport, Gordon, 185 Alquist, Jessica, 181 This American Life, 101 Amodio, David, 6, 219–​221 amygdala, 111 Apfelbaum, Evan, 172 approach/​avoidance, 93, 168, 184–​185, 197 aretaic appraisals, 22, 103–​104, 120–​122, 132–​140 Arpaly, Nomy, 10, 102–​103, 144, 154–​160, 164, 204–​205 Asgari, Shaki, 149, 197 associations activation of, 68–​71, 90–​94, 169–​171, 194–​199, 217–​230 content-​driven change in, 70–​72 associative principles, 69–​72 and counterconditioning, 70–​71 and extinction, 70–​71 attention regulation, 187–​191 attitude-​behavior consistency, 175–​176, 219 attributability, 103–​122, 127–​150 care-​based theory of, 106–​122 judgment-​based accounts of, 111–​112, 145–​149 voluntaristic accounts of, 111–​112 attribution errors, 167 Augustine, St., 16 autonomy, 157, 191–​200, 209 awareness conditions, 43–​44, 65–​66, 103–​112, 123, 131, 139–​146 and Levy’s Consciousness Thesis, 140–​144

Balcetis, Emily, 49 Bar, Moshe, 44–​46 Bar-​Anan, Yoav, 78–​84, 215–​217 Barden, Jamie, 68 Bargh, John, 23–​24, 49 Barrett, Lisa Feldman, 43–​46, 111 Barrington, Keith, 143 basic actions, 143, 166n15 Bateson, Melissa, 191 Baumeister, Roy, 11, 181 belief attribution, 73–​82 belief, 72–​81 action-​guiding account of, 73–​81 context-​relative, 73–​81 contradictory, 73–​81 identity-​protective, 174–​176 indeterminacy of, 73–​81 truth-​taking account of, 73–​81 belief-​discordant behavior, 13, 86–​90, 117 Benes, Barton, 12–​13, 33–​42, 48, 67, 72–​73 benevolent sexism, 71 Bennett, Jonathan, 159–​160 Bird, Larry, 142 Bjorklund, Fredrik, 71 blind spot bias, 127n6, 175 Bottomless Bowl experiment, 191–​192 bounded rationality, 14, 174n26 Bourdieu, Pierre, 65n2 Bratman, Michael, 109, 116 Briñol, Pablo, 170–​171 Brody, Gene, 181 Bryan, William, 17–​18 Buchsbaum, Daphna, 166–​167 Cameron, Daryl, 10, 131–​137, 222 caring, affective account of, 110–​116 and the rational-​relations view, 145–​149 Carlsson, Rickard, 71

257

258

Carruthers, Peter, 82 Cesario, Joseph, 61–​62, 84, 192–​194, 230 Chan, David, 155–​156 Chemero, Anthony, 37 choice blindness, 172 chronic accessibility of concepts, 218 Churchill, Winston, 231 Clark, Andy, 33, 51 Clinton, Hillary, 22–​23 A Clockwork Orange, 179 closure, 77 co-​activation, 20–​21, 31, 61–​64, 85–​94, 120 cognitive behavioral therapy, 71–​72, 168 and exposure therapy, 71–​72 cognitive depletion, 171–​172 cognitive dissonance, 72, 141 balance effects of, 72 cognitive penetration, 40–​44 Cognitive Reflection Test, 175 compensation effect, 71 confabulation, 17, 172–​176 confirmation bias, 167–​168 Confucius, 10, 184 consciousness, global workspace theory of, 141 consequential validity, 223 consistency, individual, 77, 103, 175, 198 contact hypothesis, 185 context regulation, 191–​195, 198–​205 context sensitivity, 35–​36, 84, 180–​201 contiguity, 69–​72 core relational themes, 114–​120 Correll, Joshua, 60–​61, 120–​127 Costanza, George, 162 counterstereotypes, 45, 70, 149, 184–​200 the creepiness worry, 179 Currie, Greg, 88, 91 Cushman, Fiery, 13–​14, 32, 51–​55, 175 D’Cruz, Jason, 23, 153–​176 Dasgupta, Nilanjana, 68, 149, 197 de Ridder, Denise T. D., 180–​181 decision-​making, evaluative, 49–​58 model-​based, 53–​56 model-​free, 56–​58 and decision trees, 50–​54 deep self, 133–​137 alternatively, the whole self, 108n16, 134n18 mosaic conception of the, 135–​138, 206 unity of, 133–​137 deliberation, 110–​116, 153–​176, 205–​209 Dennett, Daniel, 177–​195 stances, 177–​209 Descartes, 16, 110 Devine, Patricia, 197–​200, 219–​225 dispositional accounts of attitudes, 4–​6, 81–​84

Index distance-​standing, 6–​7 dorsal visual stream, 166n15 Dretske, Fred, 114–​115 Dreyfus, Hubert, 18, 38–​39 dual-​system psychology, 16, 32, 86–​87 Associative-​Propositional Evaluation, 80, 222 explicit vs. implicit mental states, 15–​16 Meta-​Cognitive Model, 222 Motivation and Opportunity as Determinants, 219n10, 222 Reflective Impulse Model, 219n10 dual-​task experiments, 143 Duckworth, Angela, 180 dynamic feedback, 49, 68, 122 ecological control, 149n35 Egan, Andy, 76–​78 ego depletion, 11 embodied cognition, 185 emotion, 29–​32, 42–​46, 70–​71, 73–​75, 107–​122, 130, 140, 178, 180–​184, 190–​196 primary vs. secondary, 110–​116 somatic vs. cognitive theories of, 112–​116 epigenetic aging, 181 epistemic/​moral intersection, 62 Ericsson, K. Anders, 182–​184 evaluative conditioning, 70–​71, 149, 198 evaluative stance, 35, 134 Exhaust (in theories of visual phenomenology), 38–​42, 58 explicit monitoring theory, 143 expressive rationality, 174n26 Fazio, Russell, 19, 185 fight vs. flight words, 61–​62, 230 Finn, Huckleberry, 102, 137, 154, 158–​159 and sympathy, 159 Firestone, Chaz, 41 Flannigan, Natasha, 45 flow, 7–​8 Force Majeure, 164n13 Forscher, Patrick, 225 fragmented mind, 77–​78 FTBA relata, 20–​21, 31–​65, 91–​97, 116–​117 specifically, alleviation, 48–​63 specifically, behavior, 46–​78 specifically, feature, 32–​42 specifically, tension, 42–​46 strength of, 43 valence of, 42–​43 Gallo, Inge Schweiger, 190 Gawronski, Bertram, 61, 80, 192–​194, 200

Index Gemmel, Bruce, 207 Gendler, Tamar Szabó, 12–​13, 64–​65, 73–​74, 85–​94 Gibran, Kahlil, 10 Gibson, Bradley, 41 Gibson, J. J., 36–​37 and ecological psychology, 40 The Gift of Fear, 1–​5 Gilbert, Daniel, 51 Ginsborg, Hannah, 94–​97 Gladwell, Malcom, 10, 182–​183 Glaser, Jack, 61 Gollwitzer, Peter, 188, 191 good true self theory, 136–​137 Goodale, Melvyn, 34, 40n13 Goodman, Steven, 228–​229 Gopnik, Allison, 167 Guinote, Ana, 195 habit, 9, 17–​18, 23, 64–​65, 88, 139, 157, 168, 225 and the habit stance, 179–​209 and habitudes, 64–​65 vs. habitus, 65n2, 157 Hacker, Peter, 157 halo effect, 71 Hamilton, Holly, 61 Harter, Noble, 17–​18 Haslanger, Sally, 208–​209 Hawley, Patricia, 209 Hayes, John, 183 Herman, Barbara, 201–​204 Hu, Xiaoqing, 79 Huang, Julie, 23–​24, 49 Huebner, Bryce, 53–​54, 58, 73–​74 Hume, David, 12, 22, 69, 87 Ichino, Anna, 88–​89 identification theories, 106 if-​then plans. See implementation intentions imperatival perception, 20, 32–​41, 46, 58–​60, 190n13 implementation intentions, 80, 187–​191, 198–​199 implicit attitudes associative vs. propositional debate about, 80–​81 consciousness of, 103, 131–​133 control over, 103, 131–​133 dispositional view of, 217 form-​sensitivity of, 79–​81 malleability of, 179–​196 personal vs. subpersonal, 121–​122 implicit bias, 2–​4, 14, 21–​23, 46, 58–​63, 66–​67, 76–​82, 95–​97, 103, 119–​120, 131–​136, 147–​148, 167–​176, 184–​191, 195–​199, 208–​209, 224–​225, 229–​230

259

implicit stereotypes vs. implicit evaluations, 45, 60–​61, 93, 220–​222 implicit vs. indirect measures, 212n4 implicit, senses of, 15–​19 impulsivity, 10–​12, 209 in principle sensitivity, 146–​149 indirect psychological measures Affect Misattribution Procedure, 195, 215 evaluative priming, 83, 215 and eye trackers, 60 Go/​No-​go Association Task, 215 Implicit Association Test, 2, 36, 60–​62, 68, 79, 83–​84, 93, 126n5, 169n16, 170, 194–​201, 211–​231 and predictive validity, 218–​224 and process-​dissociation techniques, 197–​198 and the Quadruple Process Model, 171, 197n22 sequential priming, 19, 222 shooter bias, 2–​3, 60, 80, 119–​120, 126, 188, 199 and test-​retest reliability, 217–​218 inferential impoverishment, 78–​81, 94 inferential promiscuity, 78–​81, 91 innate architecture, 64, 86, 95–​96 institutional change, 193n17 insular cortex, 47n28 internal disharmony, 13 interpersonal fluency, 8–​9, 53, 133, 138–​139 interracial interactions, 172, 224–​225 intervention, 119–​120, 169–​176, 177–​180 context regulation as, 191–​195 durability of, 196–​201 generality of, 196–​201 pre-​commitment as, 187–​191 intuition, 1–​14, 65n5, 202–​205 inverse akrasia, 10, 102 Inzlicht, Michael, 226–​228 Iowa Gambling Task, 88–​89 Ito, Tiffany, 70–​71 James, William, 179 Jaworska, Agnieska, 107–​116, 128–​131 jazz, 88, 144 Johansson, Petter, 172–​173 Jonas, Kai, 61–​62, 230 Jordan, Michael, 68 Joseph Harp Correctional Center, 101–​104 Kant, Immanuel, 33, 159, 201–​205 Kawakami, Kerry, 184–​187, 197, 204, 225 Kim, Kimberly, 141–​147 knowledge-​how, 17

260

Knowles, Megan, 9n19 Korsakoff ’s syndrome, 45 Kriegel, Uriah, 87 Krishnamurthy, Meena, 209 Kubota, Jennifer, 70–​71 Lai, Calvin, 224–​225 Lazarus, Richard, 114 learning associative reward, 44 feedback-​error, 184 implicit, 18–​19 Pavolvian mechanisms for, 54n41 prediction-​error models of, 49–​56 temporal difference reinforcement, 54 Lebrecht, Sophie, 45 Ledecky, Katie, 207 Leder, Garson, 169 The Lego Movie, 5 Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 16 Levy, Neil, 65n5, 70, 78–​80, 117n27, 121n35, 123–​126, 134, 140–​144, 147, 170, 201 loaded gun case, 105–​106, 140 Machery, Edouard, 83–​84, 216–​217 Macnamara, Brooke, 184 Madva, Alex, 73, 79–​81, 185 Mallon, Ron, 121–​122 Mandelbaum, Eric, 69–​72, 80–​81, 170 Mann, David, 166n15 marshmallow experiments, 10–​11 Martin, Justin, 14 Martin, Trayvon, 3 memory, 111, 116, 169 episodic, 169 working, 77, 140–​141 Mendoza, Saaid, 198 mental habits, 64 Merleau-​Ponty, Maurice, 38 Messick, Samuel, 223 micro-​expression, 1–​3, 55 micro-​valence, 45 Mill, John Stuart, 159–​160 Miller, George, 18 Miller, Gregory, 181 Millikan, Ruth, 33 Milner, David, 33–​34, 40n13 Milyavskaya, Marin, 195 minimal group paradigm, 96n47 Mischel, Walter, 10–​11 Mitchell, Jason, 68 Modern Racism Scale, 220n11 moral credit, 201–​205

Index moral luck, 13–​14, 137, 175, 205 moral myopia, 13–​14 moral sentimentalism, 155 Moran, Tal, 76–​80 MOSAIC Threat Assessment System, 2 Moskowitz, Gordon, 48–​49 motivated numeracy, 173 motivated reasoning, 174–​176 motivation for debiasing, 195 Motivational Support Account, 123n3 Müller-​Lyer illusion, 75–​76 multinomial modeling, 71n16, 171 Nagel, Jennifer, 88–​91 Neal, David, 192 Necker cube, 41 neo-​Lockean approach to identity, 109, 116 New York City Subway Hero, 9–​10, 165 Newman, Barnett, 5–​6 Newman, George, 136–​137 Nike organisms, 24 Nisbett, Richard, 17, 172–​173 nudge, 191–​193 Obama, Barack, 3, 8–​9, 54–​55, 138–​139, 143–​147 occasion setter, 118, 194 Olson, Kristina, 227 omission, patterns of, 125–​127 Open Science Collaboration, 226 orbitofrontal cortex, 44 Oswald, Frederick, 218–​223 Papineau, David, 143, 166n15 Payne, Keith, 10, 46, 199, 222 Payton, Walter, 7, 21, 141 perception action-​first, 33–​34 rich properties of, 37–​38 spectator-​first, 33–​34 theories of, 3–​42, 208 perceptual unquiet, 20, 29–​30, 42 Peterson, Christopher, 181 Peterson, Mary, 41 phronesis, 9, 21, 155 Plato, 10, 13, 16 Polonyi, Michael, 17 practical salience, 35–​36 practice, 9, 139, 144, 163–​166, 225 rote, 182–​187, 191 pre-​commitment, 148–​149, 187–​191 prefrontal cortex, 110–​112 Pre-​Incident Indicators, 1–​4

Index primitive normativity, 94–​97 vs. naïve normativity, 95n46 Prinz, Jesse, 112–​120 Proffitt, Dennis, 40–​41 propranolol, 168–​169 prosocial behavior, 8, 191 psychological explanations of discrimination, limits of, 208 Railton, Peter, 7, 42–​43, 51n34, 77n28, 154–​157, 164–​165, 202–​203 Rand, David, 8 rational relations, 145–​149 Ratliff, Kate, 132 reasons responsiveness, 117n27 Reber, Arthur, 18 Redford, Liz, 132 Reed, Brian, 101–​102 regress problems, 23, 156–​158, 164–​165 renewal effects, 192–​193 replication crisis, 225–​230 p-​hacking, 225 Resource Computation Model, 230 responsibility, 123–​152 and accountability, 129–​131 and answerability, 129, 145–​146 and being vs. holding responsible, 127–​131 Rickey, Branch, 143 Rietveld, Erik, 47n29 Rivers, Phillip, 142 Robinson, Jackie, 143 Rooth, Dan-​Olof, 61, 221 Rust, Johnathan, 175–​176 Ryle, Gilbert, 17 Sarkissian, Hagop, 163, 184 Sartre, Jean-​Paul, 57 scaffolding, 54 Scanlon, Thomas, 145 Schaller, Mark, 68, 229 Schapiro, Tamar, 34, 64 Schneider, Walter, 18–​19 Scholl, Brian, 41 seemings, 75, 148 self-​control, 11, 180–​200 selfish goals, 23–​24 self-​regulation, 11, 180–​200 Ulysses-​type strategies for, 148–​149, 187–​191 Self-​Regulation of Prejudice model, 198 self-​trust, 209 Seligman, Martin, 55–​56, 181 Sheeran, Paschal, 188, 190n13

261

Shiffrin, Richard, 18–​19 Shift (in theories of visual phenomenology), 40–​41 Shoemaker, David, 108–​115, 128–​137, 147–​148 Shook, Natalie, 185 shooter bias, 2–​3, 60, 80, 119–​120, 126, 188, 199, 206 Skywalk cases, 12–​13, 46, 57, 67–​78, 86, 89–​90, 94–​95, 103 Slingerland, Edward, 10 smile, 163–​164 Duchenne, 163–​164 Pan Am, 163–​164 Smith, Angela, 111, 145–​149 Smith, Holly, 133–​134 Society for the Improvement of Psychological Science, 226 somatic neural markers, 184 soul, tripartite account of the, 10 Spinozan Belief Fixation, 80–​81 spontaneity, 153–​176 deliberation-​volatility of, 161–​167 Sripada, Chandra, 124–​125, 135, 146 Sterelny, Kim, 23, 33 Stewart, Brandon, 46, 199 Stich, Stephen, 78 stimulus-​response reflexes, 66–​69 subdoxastic state, 78 Sunstein, Cass, 193 tacit knowledge, 17–​18 Tennenbaum, Richie, 59 ten-​thousand hour rule, 182–​183 Thaler, Richard, 193 The Big Five personality traits, 203–​204 thought, affect-​ladeness of, 111–​116 Tietz, Jeff, 29–​30, 42 Toppino, Thomas, 41 trait-​based accounts. See dispositional accounts Transyouth Project, 227 utilization behavior, 35 Vazire, Simine, 231n30 virtue ethics, 9–​10, 203–​205 Vohs, Kathleen, 11 von Economo neurons, 43 Wallace, David Foster, 7, 57 “watch the ball” heuristic, 165–​166

262

Watching Eyes Effect, 191 Webb, Thomas, 190n13 Whitehead, Alfred North, 18 Wieber, Frank, 189–​190 Wiers, Reinout, 197 Wilde, Oscar, 162 Williams, Bernard, 164 Wilson, Timothy, 17, 172 Witt, Jessica, 40–​41

Index Woodward, James, 43n17 wu-​wei, 10, 161n6 Yarrow, Kielan, 53 Zeigarnik Effect, 57 Zimmerman, Aaron, 56, 73

Smile Life

When life gives you a hundred reasons to cry, show life that you have a thousand reasons to smile

Get in touch

© Copyright 2015 - 2024 AZPDF.TIPS - All rights reserved.